Transcript
Page 1: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

Kant's Teleological EthicsAuthor(s): Keith WardSource: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 21, No. 85 (Oct., 1971), pp. 337-351Published by: Blackwell Publishing for The Philosophical QuarterlyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2218659Accessed: 02/08/2010 19:52

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unlessyou have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and youmay use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Blackwell Publishing and The Philosophical Quarterly are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve andextend access to The Philosophical Quarterly.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

337

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS

BY KEITH WARD

Kant's ethical theory is frequently misportrayed and misunderstood. Only ignorance of the greater number of his published books and essays can lead to the sort of comment, still quite common in Britain, that Kant is a stern philosopher of duty for duty's sake, without regard to considerations of human fulfilment and happiness, or that the sense of duty has for him no necessary relation to human purposes or desires. My aim in this paper is to show conclusively, from important but neglected writings of Kant, that such estimates are mistaken; that, though Kant did stress, as no-one had previously, the categorical nature of moral obligation, yet Kantian ethics is, in a fundamental sense, a teleological ethic, concerned above all with ends of action and human fulfilment. I will outline briefly Kant's teleological ethics, trace its development throughout his published works, and, finally, suggest that the formalistic terminology by means of which Kant expresses his view, and which has helped to mislead commentators, is a derivative of the Critical epistemology badly adapted to express his ethical views.

My thesis is that Kant's main ethical concern was with human perfec- tion; while he rejected the Wolffian claim that one could define perfection independently of moral considerations, the categorical obligations of the moral law are, he believed, motiveless, arbitrary and absurd if they are not conceived as determining human perfection. Not only are some of Kant's modern critics so ignorant of Kant's view that they bring this view itself as an objection against him; but it may be claimed that he has seen further than they, in seeing clearly the impossibility of attaining perfection in this life, and the consequent necessity for such a view of postulating a wider religious context.

1. THE EARLY VIEW OF MAN'S SPIRITUAL DESTINY

Kant's view of ethics arises from, and is shaped by, his early view of human destiny as a process of infinite spiritual evolution-a view which combined features of Leibniz-Wolff Rationalism with elements drawn from his Pietistic upbringing, stressing the importance of individual moral free- dom. In the General History of Nature and Theory of the Heavens, published anonymously in 1755, Kant propounds a vision of Nature as an infinite realm of continuous creation and cosmic evolution. " But unsatisfied even yet with this immense object, whose transitoriness cannot adequately satisfy the soul, the mind wishes to obtain a closer knowledge of that being whose Intelligence and Greatness is the source of all ... and with what reverence

Page 3: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

338 KEITH WARD

must not the soul regard even its own being, which is destined to .. go on to fill all the infinitude of time and space with stages of perfection in thought that grow on to infinity, and which has to approach as it were step by step the goal of the supreme excellence of the Deity, without, however, being ever able to reach it."' Nature, conceived in the Leibniz- Wolff tradition of Rationalism as the best of all possible worlds, compels astonishment and awe. Yet its ruthless amorality and transitoriness lead man to consider that he "is not born to erect eternal dwelling places in this theatre of vanity; his whole life has a far nobler end ".2 Kant's belief in an infinite spiritual destiny of man, to be won through continued struggle within Nature, is here clearly expressed in his first published works. The view was never abandoned, and without it, the doctrine of the Categorical Imperative is, as I shall show, unintelligible.

The conception of a constantly evolving spiritual world, united in one community under an all-perfect Reason, is developed significantly in the Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, of 1766. That work is influenced both by Sweden- borg's Arcana Coelestia, a six-volume work on occultism which Kant eagerly awaited and purchased, and by Rousseau's Social Contract and Emile, which came to Konigsberg in 1762. Swedenborg claimed acquaintance with the intelligible world of spirits, and held that each man is, in this present life, in Heaven or Hell-that is, he is spiritually related to other spirits in accordance with inevitable laws of spiritual cause and effect. Kant adopts this view, maintaining that the human soul is " conjoined in its present life with two worlds at the same time . . . as a member of the spiritual world it receives and gives out the pure influences of immaterial natures ",3 while, of Newtonian physics. The system of spiritual relationships is only im- perfectly expressed in the material world, for " all morality must fail of its complete effect . . . according to laws of nature ";4 but the consequences of hidden purposes and motives inevitably make themselves known in the " immediate communion of spirits ", and determine one's true position in the system of moral intelligences. And the spiritual world makes itself known through "an actual and universally conceded observation . . . the

feeling for morality ".5

The undisputed fact of moral experience, he holds, is " a certain sensation of restraint ", which sometimes compels us to adapt our intentions to the welfare of others. Kant uses the notion of a " general will " derived from Rousseau, to interpret this " restraint " as the activity of a foreign will in us, subjecting our own inclinations to some sort of external consent. " The

1General History of Nature and Theory of the Heavens, trans. W. Hastie, in Kant's Cosmogony (Glasgow, 1900), pp. 154, 167.

20n the Causes of Earthquakes, trans. G. Rabel, in Kant (Oxford, 1963), p. 29. 8Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, trans. E. F. Goerwitz, ed. F. Sewall (London, 1900), p. 60.

as a member of the material world, it is subject to the mechanical principles 4Ibid., p. 65. 5Ibid., p. 62.

Page 4: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS 339

appearance of moral impulses . . . (is) the result of a truly active force through which mental creatures influence each other ". Or again, "the sense of morality would be the sensation of the dependence of the individual will upon the will of all, and would be a consequence of the natural and universal interaction whereby the immaterial world attains its unity "6. There is an impulse in us which bids us consider the wills of others and bring them into conformity with our own will, so that all acting beings may form one moral community. This impulse is " an appearance of that which actu- ally transpires in us ", a " natural and general reciprocity through which the immaterial world forms itself into . . . a moral unity and systematic connection according to purely spiritual laws ".7 Thus, Kant suggests, one may explain the feeling for morality as the result of a real mutual dependence of spirits upon one another in a " system of spiritual perfection ", the laws of cohesion of which would be laws of actual spiritual interaction, expressed in the feelings of love and respect, just as the material world coheres through the universal forces of gravitational attraction and repulsion.

On this remarkable view, moral feelings are appearances of a pattern of intelligible relationships by which I am constrained, as a legislative member of the spiritual world ; and these relations are given a formal characterization, in that they sustain a systematic harmony under the rule of the general will. So it is in the Dreams that Kant's fully-fledged notion of the formal character of morality is articulated, as acting so as to create and sustain a universal harmony of ends in an intelligible community of freely legislating wills. The Dreams is thus an important work for understanding Kant's ethical theory; it expresses Kant's transition from his earlier acceptance of the moral-sense theories of the British moralists to a more intellectually based theory of ethics; it shows the origin of the formalistic conception of the Categorical Imperative, and its true character as a principle of the har- monious development of ends, in a visionary dream of a spiritual world; it exposes the influences of Wolff, Newton, Swedenborg and Rousseau in forming the theory; and it also announces the renunciation of the visionary speculation in which it indulges. For the Swedenborgian view, he writes, is just " a phantom in the feverish brains of deceived enthusiasts ", a " futile dream ", a " fairy-tale ". Indeed, such dreams, whether based on visions or speculative metaphysics, are no more than " farts or belches ". " My analogy (between moral influx and gravitational force) ", he wrote to Mendelssohn in 1766, " is not intended seriously ".8

It seems that perhaps his visionary speculation was a joke. But the truth is that Kant was feeling the force of both scepticism and visionary belief. In the same letter to Mendelssohn he says, " the attitude of my own

6Ibid., p. 64. 7Loc. cit. 8Letter to Moses Mendelssohn, dated April 8, 1766; in Kant's Werke, ed. Rosen-

kranz u. Schubert, 11, 1 (Leipzig, 1842).

Page 5: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

340 KEITH WARD

mind is inconsistent . . . and I cannot help cherishing an opinion that there is some validity in (Swedenborg's) arguments ". His resolution of the con- flict is to renounce speculation and commit oneself to moral action, for " the allurement of arguments . . . can hardly decide the fate of honest men " ;9 so here the foundation is laid for the doctrine of the primacy of Practical Reason.

That this resolution was extremely short-lived shows the real strength of the hold visionary metaphysics had on Kant. In 1766, he wrote, " Now I put aside the whole doctrine of spirits as settled and finished; in future it does not concern me any more ".10 But in the Inaugural Dissertation of 1770, he constructs a fully Rationalist doctrine, for which moral concepts are " known by the pure intellect itself ",11 and the moral law is once again conceived as a real intelligible relationship in the noumenal world of pure spirits. The Critical philosophy was finally to destroy this dogmatic Rationa- alism; yet this was not a victory for scepticism, for Kant retained his early characterization of morality, and his belief in the spiritual context of moral- ity. These little-known pre-Critical works are vital for an understanding of the visionary origins of Kant's theory of ethics which were never totally abandoned by Kant. This emerges in two main ways: first, his continuing concern with the ends of moral action and with human perfection; and second, as a corollary of this, his postulation of a continued spiritual existence in which such fulfilment could be possible.

2. REASON AND THE PURPOSES OF NATURE

Many critics have accused Kant of being unconcerned with human purposes or fulfilment, in adhering to a purely formal principle of universal- izability in ethics. But this is a travesty of Kant's doctrine. He does speak of the moral law as expressing " the consistency of my free will with itself and with that of others ".12 But, as H. J. Paton has pointed out, the sort of inconsistency Kant has in mind here is not formal self-contradiction, but the sort of inconsistency which arises in having a purpose which conflicts with the purposes of others, or which one fails to implement. Thus Kant speaks indifferently of a " consistency " or " harmony " of purposes, which is to be established by conformity to universally valid purposes. In the Metaphysic of Morals, he provides, as a new formula of the Categorical Imperative: "Act according to a maxim of ends which it can be a universal law for everyone to have ".13 It is ironic that this formula, which, in re- ferring explicitly to ends of action, is perhaps the most adequate formula- tion of Kant's fundamental principle of ethics, does not appear in the Funda-

9Dreams, p. 121. l0Ibid., p. 90. 11" Inaugural Dissertation ", trans. Kerferd and Walford, in Kant: Selected Pre-

Critical Writings (Manchester, 1968), p. 58. 12Lectures on Ethics, trans. L. Infield (New York, 1963), p. 13. 13c" The Doctrine of Virtue " (Pt. 2 of Metaphysic of Morals), trans. M. J. Gregor

(New York, 1964), p. 55.

Page 6: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS 341

mental Principles. But it does make it quite clear that Kant is fundamentally concerned with ends of action; and, indeed, that " were there no such ends [which were also duties] a categorical imperative would be impossible ".14

Yet Kant's position is not merely that one must conceive oneself as setting up a purposive order of Nature, according to universal laws, as though one could arbitrarily choose anything whatsoever as one's purpose. One can see this if one takes Kant's list of examples of moral duties in the Metaphysic of Morals. Masturbation is against the purposes of Nature, in

forming the sexual organs; suicide contravenes Nature's purpose in estab- lishing self-love in order to preserve life. Lying " annihilates human dig- nity " and " abases humanity in one's own person ". One must seek educa- tion and develop one's intellectual and conative powers, because failure to do so would involve, not nullification, but neglect of the purposes of Nature in one. Finally, " holiness of will " must be pursued, as this expresses the absolute worth of the human person, in its freedom from sensuous impulses and its transcendence of Nature.

There are various stands here which cannot satisfactorily be bludgeoned into one fundamental principle. It is Nature which sets before man certain ends which, negatively, may not be violated, and, positively, need to be furthered by personal effort. The Metaphysic of Morals makes it clear that Reason must preserve and perfect the purposes of Nature. Moreover, it must finally transcend those purposes, in realizing its own infinite dignity. Legislative Reason promulgates, not a senseless set of absolute imperatives, but the rational condition of a harmonious system of ends, the greatest possible harmony of human purposes which are compatible with, yet trans- cend, the purposes of Nature. So Reason must take account of and seek to perfect the purposes of Nature; in doing so it freely determines Nature in accordance with Nature's own inner purposes; thus freedom is for the

purpose of fulfilment, and to use it otherwise is to contradict its essential character. It is this process of freely preserving and fulfilling the ends of Nature, against the opposition of inclinations, which gives human life its value, for Kant; " the end for which man is destined is to achieve his fullest

perfection through his own freedom ".15 Moral effort is of supreme worth; but it would be senseless, on Kant's view, if it were not aimed at the realiza- tion of one's natural perfections in a harmonious community. This is the doctrine implicit in the Fundamental Principles; and it is unfortunate that Kant's attempt to provide just one supreme principle of morality, and a

purely formal one at that, has helped to conceal it from those critics who have failed to take into account the Metaphysic of Morals, to which the Funda- mental Principles was meant to be a propaedeutic.

Yet the paradox of Kant's ethics is that, though moral action is thus

essentially concerned with the fulfilment of natural and moral perfection, 14Ibid., p. 43. 15Lectures on Ethics, p. 252.

Page 7: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

342 KEITH WARD

such fulfilment is impossible in this world. I am not always able to act consistently; my desires remain largely recalcitrant to reason; other people rarely have the will and power to do what is right; and nature does not ensure the satisfactory fulfilment of those moral purposes in which true happiness is to be found. Nevertheless, Kant maintains that it remains " an inflexible precept of the will " to do what a purely rational being would do in an ideal world, in which all other beings had the will and power to act rightly. For such a paradoxical view of morality to be intelligible at all, one must postulate that, somehow, Nature can be so determined that moral effort will not finally be in vain. This paradox may be unbearable; but it is essential for an understanding of Kant to see that it does exist; that is, that he is centrally concerned with human fulfilment, which he admits to be impossible in this life. It is sheer misconception to suppose that Kant is not concerned with human flourishing, even if his specific account of the relation between virtue and happiness seems weak or implausible.

Kant elaborates on this teleological view of nature in the third Critique and various essays on history, written between 1784-1795, in which he out- lines an evolutionary, purposive view of history, developing through wars and struggle to the foundation of a world-federation of states and " culture " -the development of natural, intellectual and artistic tendencies and of the conditions for moral freedom. " Nature has willed that man . .. should partake of no other happiness or perfection than that which he himself . . . has created by his own reason ".16 Nature, by means of social antagonism and even war, aims at developing all human talents to a stage at which man is released " from the womb of nature " as a freely choosing moral agent, finding in himself the final end of the world, and henceforth impelled to struggle to seek active, self-wrought perfection and happiness. The historical destiny of Nature is thus to form a being which must be fashioned through discord and strife to transcend its animal condition and realize its essential superiority to Nature, through its moral freedom.

In these essays, the first written before the Groundwork, Kant's teleo- logical view of nature is re-emphasized; but that teleology is clearly subor- dinated to a higher purpose, without which there is no value in nature whatsoever. This is the moral destiny of the free moral individual, a notion with which, as I have shown, Kant began his philosophy; without which the doctrine of the Categorical Imperative cannot be correctly interpreted; and with which, in Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone and the

Opus Postumum, Kant draws his work to a close.

3. EVIL AND CONVERSION In the Religion, he recalls the doctrine of the second Critique, that the

free moral acts of human agents express a noumenal, timeless choice, which is made once for all, and is the ground of all temporal moral choices. The

16" Idea for a Universal History ", trans. L. W. Beck, in On History, ed. Beck (New York, 1957), p. 13.

Page 8: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS 343

whole course of a man's life expresses one " act of intelligible choice ", which is " the ground antecedent to every use of freedom in experience ".17

And now he adds that all men have chosen, as their ultimate maxim, to allow the incentives of sensuous nature to determine their choices, which is moral evil. This "ultimate subjective ground of all maxims is entwined with and, as it were, rooted in humanity itself ",18 so that there is an innate, radical propensity to evil in all men. Since this is an intelligible act, it cor-

rupts all particular moral acts; so it seems that man is unable to obey the moral law, which yet retains its full force.

What is needed, Kant holds, is not a reform in one's particular acts, which is impossible, but a complete reversal of the order of incentives we have intelligibly chosen, a conversion of the intelligible act, so that the moral law can be re-established as the sole adequate incentive of all our maxims. This " noumenal conversion " will appear in time as an " endless

progress to holiness ", since man starts from a tendency to evil and his

temporal acts will always be defective. But to God such infinite moral

progress may be judged perfect as a whole, since He sees the intelligible, radical conversion to good.

Thus all men begin from a state of innate evil, but are also under obliga- tion to become a " new creation ". Moreover, since the noumenal world is

changeless, one must conceive each (converted) man as a sort of dual will; " there are not two moral acts . . . but only a single act " ;19 and, pheno- menally, there is in each person a " new man " he is becoming, and an " old man " whom he is continually putting off. The " death of the old man " is " a sacrifice and an entrance upon a long train of life's ills ", which are

punishments due for one's innate guilt. But what are punishments for him are " opportunities for testing " for the " new man ". The whole earthly life of man must be conceived as the temporal expression of a change of heart.

The difficulties of this account are only too apparent. What is meant

by a noumenal change, when noumena are timeless ? Can we be sure that all men are regenerate ? That the change will be completed ? If the " punish- ment " is infinite, must the new man sacrifice for eternity ? And how can one man intelligibly decide both ways at once ? Yet the account develops further Kant's central view of the moral life as a warfare of good and evil, in which man is absolutely claimed, yet aware of an innate corruption and

guilt, which requires a radical conversion and the hope of an inscrutable

power of grace to assure one of future consummation. This is a deeply religious view of ethics, and again it shows unmistakably Kant's concern with fulfilment, its impossibility, and the necessity of continuing hope, not

l7Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, trans. T. M. Greene and H. H. Hudson (New York, 1960), p. 17.

18Ibid., p. 28. 19Ibid., p. 68.

Page 9: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

344 KEITH WARD

as optional addenda to a complete formalistic view of ethics, but as defining the intelligible context of the formalistic view. And it emphasizes Kant's view that human fulfilment is not to be found in this world, so that im- mortality and the existence of a providential God must be postulated as a condition of its possibility.

4. THE POSTULATES OF PRACTICAL REASON It was Heine who cynically suggested that Kant introduced the Postu-

lates to comfort his manservant Lampe; and there has been a repeated tendency, in Kant criticism, to say that, as well as being based on very weak arguments, they are extraneous to and even incompatible with Kant's central stress on duty for its own sake. That Kant's specific arguments are weak is true; but then, his specific arguments usually are weak; the aston- ishing thing is that his underlying insights continue to exert intellectual fascination and power. The question of incompatibility is central to the interpretation of Kant's ethics, and must be explored in some detail; but it is clear that Kant saw the difficulty, and thought he had avoided it. He affirms that duty must be done because it is duty; but also that " The moral law . .. defines for us a final end, and does so a priori, and makes it

obligatory upon us to strive towards its attainment. This end is the summum bonum ".20 And he defines the summum bonum in this way: " The highest good means the whole, the perfect good, wherein virtue is always the supreme good .. .while happiness . . . presupposes conduct in accordance with the moral law as its condition ".21 These are clear statements that there is a supreme end of human action, which is determined a priori by the moral law; and it may be defined as " happiness in accordance with virtue ".

But what if this final end is impossible ? It might be said that the voice of duty would not be less absolute if the end which it commanded was not possible; for Kant is quite clear that moral " laws are formal and command unconditionally, paying no regard to ends (as the subject-matter of volition) ".22

Thus Kant says that the only thing an atheist would have to abandon would be " the premeditation of the final end ", not obedience to the moral law; but, on the other hand, he implies that the nullity of the final end would weaken " the respect with which he is immediately inspired to obed- ience ", which would in turn weaken the " moral sentiment ". Further, he

writes, " he must adopt the assumption (that the final end is possible) if he wishes to think in a manner consistent with morality ".23 It looks, at times, as though Kant wants both to have his cake and eat it; he wants to say both that the postulate of a possible summum bonum is necessary to the

practice of morality and that it is not. 20Critique of Teleological Judgment, trans. J. C. Meredith (Oxford, 1952), p. 118.

21Critique of Practical Reason, trans. L. W. Beck (New York, 1956), p. 115. 22Crit. of Judgment, p. 119. 23Loc. cit.

Page 10: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS 345

I think the solution to this difficulty is that Kant definitely wished to avoid making belief in God a condition of feeling moral obligation-this is the thesis of the autonomy of morals, for which he is justly famed. If this is so, it seems that the moral law must obligate, whether or not one believes that God exists. But what if one could know that God did not exist ? Kant denies the logical possibility of making this move, because of the necessarily limited nature of human knowledge, and the impossibility of theoretically establishing either the existence or the non-existence of a future life or God. Nevertheless, if we could, per impossibile, know the summum bonum to be impossible of attainment, obedience to the moral law for its own sake would be impossible and motiveless; " No man can possibly be righteous without having the hope . . . that righteousness must have its reward ".24 Why should men obey this law, in a world in which no possibility of future happi- ness is held out, either to the individual after death or to the human race in some future time ?

One might answer, with the Stoics, that one must just do one's duty because it is one's duty, even in the face of amoral nature. But this attitude is just that which Kant himself characterizes as " misanthropical ". " Mis- anthropic ethics ", he says, " sets moral conduct in opposition to all pleas- ures ".25 Though such an ethics "is productive of lofty deeds, and as such is good ", yet " it goes wrong . . . in holding that pleasure and morality are inconsistent with each other ". For " to renounce happiness is to differ- entiate it from morality in a transcendental and unnatural way ".26 It is mistaken and misanthropical to deny a necessary relation of morality and happiness. For, while they are different in kind, they are both necessary elements of man's final good, and neither is complete without the other. "Happiness is . . . a necessary corollary of morality ".27 Yet it must be the law which determines the will, not the summum bonum as object of desire, and not the thought of consequent happiness. For the happiness in question must be of a sort desire for which is awakened by the law itself, "to which no selfish mind could have aspired ".

Kant strongly criticizes all those moral-sense theorists who argue that moral action can be justified because it brings about a higher sort of happi- ness than that which comes from immoral or non-moral action. His criticism is on two main counts. First, if one believed that one would be more happy by being more moral, then happiness per se would be the end of moral action. This, Kant thinks, would reduce morality to prudential self-interest-moral conduct would be for the sake of one's own greater happiness. And this is the proposition the whole Groundwork so strongly contests.

Second, this distinction of " higher " and " lower " kinds of happiness

24Lectures on Ethics, p. 54. 25Ibid., p. 77. 26Ibid., p. 78. 27Loc. cit.

Page 11: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

346 KEITH WARD

in fact embodies a vicious circle. As he puts it, "A man, if he is virtuous, will certainly not enjoy life without being conscious of his righteousness in each action . .. but can one make him virtuous . . . merely by commending to him the contentment of spirit which will arise from the consciousness of

righteousness for which he as yet has no sense ? "28 That is, to say that a man will be happy only if he performs moral actions presupposes that one is talking about a moral man. It would not be true of a criminal, for in-

stance, that he would actually be more happy performing moral acts; their

performance would probably make him extremely miserable. But, one may say, would not his performance of immoral acts cause him to feel unhappy, by causing pangs of conscience ? The reply to that is to ask, in return, why one supposes that the man has a conscience. Conscience is a thing which can very well be suppressed; and only the man who is virtuous will cultivate his conscience. Thus, it may well be true that the happiness which derives from moral action is the greatest happiness, in some sense, but it can only be so for the man who is already moral. Therefore such happiness cannot be used as a motive to morality; the decision to act morally must be prior, logically and actually, to the judgment that a certain kind of happiness- moral happiness-is the best kind.

Kant holds, then, that the moral disposition must precede and be the condition of the desire for happiness: "morals has to do only with the rational condition of happiness and not with the means of achieving it ".29

No account of morals should leave happiness out of account altogether; but conformity to moral law is the formal condition of the sort of (self- wrought) happiness which alone deserves the name-moral happiness, which is derived from a priori laws, and is thus " a product of one's own human reason ".30 The moral law defines human perfection, and it is in attaining perfection that true, " self-created " happiness is to be found. Even though virtuous conduct does not causally produce happiness in this world, the notions of " duty ", " perfection " and " happiness " are intimately related; so that Kant can say, " the principle of self-sufficiency is the condition of all happiness . . . and determines man's absolute worth ".31

Kant himself locates his final doctrine between the two extremes of Stoicism and Epicureanism. The Stoics, he asserts, " left out of the highest good the second element (personal happiness), since they placed the highest good only in acting and in contentment with one's own personal worth . ... But the voice of their own nature could have sufficiently refuted this "32. The Epicureans, on the other hand, provide a motive for morality-happi- ness-but deprive it of all intrinsic worth. " Both were at fault" ;33 for

28Crit. of Practical Reason, p. 120. 29Ibid., p. 131. 30Lose Blatter aus Kant's Nachlass, ed. R. Reicke, 1 (Konigsberg, 1889), p. 16. 31Loc. cit. 32Crit. of Practical Reason, p. 132. s3Lectures on Ethics, p. 9.

Page 12: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS 347

what is needed is a sort of happiness which can only be attained through intrinsically worth-while action, realizing intellectual and moral perfection.

So Kant unequivocally asserts that the final end, of happiness in accor- dance with virtue, is "imposed upon us by the law of duty ", though it " is not the foundation of duty ".34 And, in the same place, he asserts that " could it [speculative reason] have perfect certainty as to the truth of this judgment [that happiness will not be accorded to moral beings], it would have to look on the moral law itself as a mere delusion of our reason in respect of practical matters ". So we must assume the possibility of the final end, " in order not to fall into self-contradiction ".

If the summum bonum is impossible, " the moral law which commands that it be furthered must be fantastic, directed to imaginary ends, and consequently inherently false ". Again, " the impossibility of the Highest Good must prove the falsity of the moral law also ".35 It is in this sense that " dogmatic unbelief cannot stand side by side with a moral maxim ".36 These statements unmistakably declare Kant's belief that the possibility of the summum bonum, with all that that implies, is a necessary condition of the intelligibility of the moral law, and of what he terms " the morality of intentions ".

5. REASON AND SENSIBILITY

The hope for future happiness is thus necessary to moral action, in the sense that man's nature, as at once a moral and a sensuous being, a member of the phenomenal and the intelligible worlds, would be brought into contra- diction with itself, if such a hope were illusory. One would be forced to say that the fulfilment of the moral law was at the same time the denial of one's sensuous nature; such fulfilment would be motiveless, in that it would come to seem an arbitrary and unintelligible imposition of abstract Reason upon man's sensuous nature. For Kant, if man consents to be deter- mined to action by his desires, whatever they may be, then he is heterono- mously determined; and thereby he abnegates his nature, as a rationally determinable being. Thus, the self-promulgation of the moral law is the

expression of man's autonomy and superiority over the sensuous bonds nature has set him. He thereby actualizes his transcendentally free nature and fulfils himself as a distinctively human person. The law of duty is thus known, practically, as supremely authoritative; all men, Kant holds, can come to know the obligatoriness of this law, in their own natures as men; for, in coming to know it, they are just coming to realize their own natures, as men. And, to realize his humanity, man must act solely out of

respect for this law of his own nature. But what if this law of autonomy is seen to contradict every object or

34Crit. of Judgment, p. 145, note. 35Crit. of Practical Reason, p. 118. 36Crit. of Judgment, p. 147.

Page 13: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

348 KEITH WARD

fulfilment of man's sensuous nature ? What if it imposes categorically upon every man the necessity of attaining absolute moral worth; but this is completely without relation to happiness or possible consequences ? As Kant is reported to have said, in the Lectures on Ethics, " Only God can see that our dispositions are moral and pure, and if there were no God, why ought we to cherish these dispositions ? ".37 He is not querying the fact that we intuitively perceive the obligation to cultivate a holy will to be categorically imposed upon as. But he is querying the validity of those intuitions, and suggesting the possibility that they may be delusory and irrational. For what they obligate us to attain is a holy will-something which in any case Kant holds to be finally unattainable in this life, and something which concerns the inner disposition, the personal fulfilment, of a man, rather than the nature of the world which is to be affected by his moral acts. Indeed, it is Kant's explicit doctrine that " even if . . . this will is entirely lacking in power to carry out its intentions .. and only good will is left . . . even then it would still shine like a jewel for its own sake ".38 But the cultivation of such a disposition could not be regarded as the law of our essential being if it contradicted or ignored the demand of our sensu- ous nature for happiness; and so we would lose the motive to cultivate it.

Kant always held that man is a being of both rationality and sensibility; and, while it would be wrong to allow one's sensuous impulses to govern one's reason-as Kant believed, with some reason, that Hume maintained-the freedom and autonomy of reason is not a freedom to contradict sensibility, but to order it in accordance with its own demands. The law of reason in ethics, the moral law, like the categories in physics, is a purely formal principle, which subjects the data of sensibility to itself. And in both cases, a transcendent ground of the finality of sensibility for reason is required, to establish the unity of the human person.

The doctrine of the two distinct, but necessarily related elements of the summum bonum-virtue and happiness-is just a particular instance of the

general Critical standpoint that man is a member of two worlds, the sensible and the intelligible, and that it is his vocation to subsume the data of

sensibility under the demands of reason. But if, in ethics, such a subsump- tion should turn out to be impossible-if reason can only contradict the end of our sensuous nature, happiness-then the human person falls apart into two contradictory principles; we cannot make happiness our goal, because reason always reminds us of the demands of morality; and we cannot make the pursuit of virtue alone our goal, because the voice of our own sensuous nature condemns such an ideal as futile and impossible.

In some way Kant needs to reconcile the two assertions, " As far as our nature as sensible beings is concerned, our happiness is the only thing of

37Lectures on Ethics, p. 80. 38Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. H. J. Paton, as The Moral Law

(London, 1948), p. 62.

Page 14: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS 349

importance ",39 and " the majesty of duty has nothing to do with the enjoy- ment of life ".40 Both of these assertions are true, but they leave a marked tension within human nature, which moralists have been prone to resolve by opting for one side of human nature at the expense of the other. In Kant's eyes, an adequate account of human morality must take full and equal account of both aspects. This can be done, he thinks, because in the end the whole phenomenal world is just an appearance of intelligible real- ity: " the person as belonging to the world of sense is subject to his own personality, so far as he belongs to the intelligible world ".41 In the world of appearance, it seems that man is determined by nature, and is dependent upon it for his weal or woe. But moral commitment licenses one in postulat- ing a real intelligible ground of nature, and, further, in supposing that, in one's moral decisions-or at least one's ultimate noumenal moral decision- one is oneself determinative of nature in its phenomenal aspects. Thus one can, and must, regard Reason as determining the harmonization of virtue and sensuous happiness; if this could not be done, man, qua legislative Practical Reason, could not be regarded as a real determining ground of nature; and then the moral law which Reason promulgates would be un- intelligible and ineffective, for the moral law must be regarded as the law of the fulfilment of man's whole nature, sensuous as well as intelligible.

6. GOD AND PRACTICAL REASON

If Reason in the individual must be conceived as determining the world of sense, some way must be found of relating that part of man which must be regarded as the ground of his phenomenal nature, other legislative moral agents, and the intelligible ground of nature as a whole. In the Opus Postu- mum, Kant makes explicit a doctrine which is implicit in many earlier works, that God and Practical Reason are identical. " God must be represented not as substance outside me, but as the highest moral principle in me ".42 Again, " The conception of God is . . . the pure practical Reason itself in its personality, and with executive powers in relation to the system of the world and its forces ".43 Kant still gives God " executive powers " over

nature; thus he does not, as Adickes suggested, abandon the postulate of a final ordering of nature so as to proportion happiness to virtue. But God is also, as practical Reason, within man, and is indeed man's true, intelligible Self. The view is clearly expressed thus : " There is a Being in me, distinguis- ed from myself as the cause of an effect wrought upon me, which freely . . judges me within, justifying or condemning me; and I as man am myself this being, and it is no substance external to me, and . . . its causality is

39Crit. of Practical Reason, p. 63. 40Ibid., p. 91. 4lIbid., p. 89. 42Kant's Opus Postumum, dargestellt und beurteilt, E. Adickes (Berlin, 1920), p. 826. 43Ibid., p. 821.

Page 15: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

350 KEITH WARD

no natural necessity but a determination of me to a free act ".44 Here Kant distinguishes Wille (practical Reason) and Willkur (the faculty of choice), the " being in me " which is also " myself, as man ", not an external sub- stance, and the " faculty of choice ", which is judged by my superior Self. The true man and the true Self are thus identical with God and truly free; practical Reason is somehow one in all men, the unitary intelligible ground of nature itself. Yet, qua Willkur, man is subject to sensuous as well as rational motives and impulses, and he has everywhere freely subjected himself to heteronomous determination by nature. Thus, though the moral law is the law of man's own nature, immanent in him and promulgated by him; nevertheless it is not the law his will (Willkur) has freely adopted into the maxims of his willing. Man has somehow been able to alienate himself from his " true Self ", by a free decision of will, which renders him incapable of fulfilling the demands of his own nature, and nature incapable of pro- viding the final good for man. Man is in radical evil, in thrall to the powers of sensuous nature, alienated from the ground of his own humanity. The best one can do, in face of the absolute demand of the immanent God and one's free alienation from it, is to hope for reconciliation by the pursuit of virtue through moral struggle for eternity. The prospect is a rather de- pressing and insecure one; but the central notions of demand, alienation and reconciliation define Kant's view of ethics as profoundly and essentially religious.

Moreover, the view is unmistakably Christian in origin; though it signifi- cantly amends Christian doctrine in a number of ways. The universe is a

purposive creation of God; but it is also the self-expressive appearance of the being of God, who is himself present, qua Practical Reason, in all men. There is a " Fall" into original sin; but this is a fall which is virtually inevitable in view of man's search for self-sufficiency and moral responsibility. Moral freedom and struggle is of supreme value; without it happiness is no more than animal contentment without point. But such struggle entails estrangement in nature, a realm with its own laws and purposes, which cannot ensure the fulfilment of man's moral purpose. There is a consum- mation at the last day to be hoped for; but it is more the hope of happiness in the attainment of perfection through the resolute pursuit of virtue than a redemption purchased through Divine sacrifice. In a sense, however, human history is itself the Divine sacrifice, since it is the incarnation of Practical reason in phenomenal nature. However, any sense of personal fellowship with God, revelation from God or redemption by God is entirely lacking in the Kantian scheme.

Kant's final view, it must be said, suffers from a radical internal inco- herence. It has abandoned the orthodox Christian stress on the independence of the individual in relation to God, by identifying Practical Reason, the true Self, with God. But it does not embrace the later Hegelian view of the

44Ibid., p. 824.

Page 16: [Keith Ward] Kant´s Teleological Ethics

KANT'S TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS 351

spatio-temporal world as the temporal manifestation of one absolute rational reality for which individuals are subordinate parts. Thus there remains in Kant to the end that tension between rational intelligibility and individual moral freedom, between Wolffian Rationalism and Pietistic individualism from which he started. The element of freedom makes the world incompre- hensible and unknowable, undermining the possibility of Rationalism; while the element of Rationalism makes freedom illusory and moral struggle inexplicable, undermining Pietistic individualism. Kant typically attempts to retain the advantages of both views; but he thereby renders his overall scheme incoherent.

It is this view, and the creative tension which it embodies, which is necessary to render Kant's better-known doctrine of the Categorical Im- perative intelligible, and to expose the full context of that doctrine. I have briefly traced the development of the view, and shown that it is one recog- nizably identical view, constant throughout Kant's writings. Many, if not most, of the common misunderstandings of Kant's ethics derive from ignor- ance of this wider context of the Categorical Imperative. It should be clear that Kant's ultimate concern in ethics was with human fulfilment in a harmonious and constantly developing community; his religious doctrines are attempts to establish the possibility of such fulfilment, which seems so uncertain in this life; and, without appreciation of that concern, the Ground- work must remain largely unintelligible.

Finally, it must be said that the vocabulary of ethical formalism, which derives from Kant's solution to his epistemological problems, is badly fitted to express the view I have outlined; and this, I suppose, is what has chiefly misled critics. Kant supposes that, as moral principles are necessary, they must derive from Reason, and therefore must be purely formal principles. This doctrine, to which Kant is epistemologically committed, cannot pro- vide for the close relation between virtue, perfection and happiness which Kant wanted, and makes his concern with the Postulates and with the fulfilment of the human personality appear as superfluous, even indefen- sible, addenda to his central, formalistic, theory. But, as I have shown, that is not the case. To understand Kant's ethical theory, one must con- sequently penetrate behind the terminology in which it is expressed, and which Kant so laboriously invented, to the underlying teleological view, which is frequently and unmistakably outlined in Kant's many published works.

King's College, London.


Top Related