designer genius an ethical investigation of cognitive enhancement

Upload: cygnusvesalius

Post on 07-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    1/37

    Designer Genius: An Ethical Investigation of Cognitive

    Enhancement

    Kenny Moran

    Ms Wu

    AP English Literature and Composition

    Los Altos High School

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    2/37

    Moran 2

    April 29, 2011

    "Adderall makes me feel like I'm superman; it makes me feel like I can get

    anything done, and I can do it in the best way humanly possible. Like, every

    single action I take is so finely tuned to perfection that there's absolutely no

    way I could be doing any better at anything, and that's really just an

    incredible feeling . . . the things you can do on Adderall are just incredible

    just incredible. By taking Adderall, the papers that Im putting out, the things

    that Im learning, the things that Im remembering are just so much

    better . . . so, I mean, if everybody was taking Adderall . . . wed all be doing

    so much better, wed all be so much smarter and the things that humanity

    could get done if everybody took Adderall it would be incredible. It would

    be incredible. I cant even begin to describe the kind of world that were

    missing out on.

    The short, dark-haired, alluring young woman that well call Danielle is not a

    very good student or at least, she wasnt born that way. Throughout high school,

    Danielle often wouldnt do her homework and wouldnt study for tests. Whenever

    she did try to succeed in school, she never found herself doing above-average work,

    and she barely managed to pull off the C average she needed to keep playing on

    her schools varsity softball team. After graduating, Danielle enrolled in community

    college and decided that she wanted to get her life back on track. When she

    started college, she still found herself struggling to overcome her lackluster study

    habits and her problems remembering all the information that her college classes

    threw at her but that hasnt stopped her from coming out at the top of all of her

    classes and performing well enough during her first two years of college to be

    accepted as a transfer student at UCLA.

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    3/37

    Moran 3

    Danielles life turned around when she met Jeff, a peer at community college

    two years her elder. Jeff is prescribed Adderall, a powerful psychostimulant

    composed of a number of amphetamine salts. Adderall is approved for the

    treatment of narcolepsy and Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder, more

    commonly known as ADHD. Jeff is diagnosed with ADHD, but he soon found that,

    without much effort, he could easily convince his doctor to prescribe him twice the

    dose he needed to function normally, allowing him to make a sizable profit selling

    his extra pills to peers. Danielle is a regular customer of Jeffs, and, with the help of

    Adderall, she has transformed herself from a below-average, apathetic student to a

    highly motivated, studious scholar who consistently receives excellent marks. What

    happened?

    Adderall is what neurologists would call a cognitive enhancer in other

    words, a smart pill. Many would immediately call Danielles decision to use a

    cognitive enhancer immoral and contemptible. Danielle has managed to get

    admitted into a prestigious university, despite the fact that her past history in high

    school would indicate that she clearly doesnt belong there. How could

    manipulating the system in this way be acceptable, let alone dignified?

    The question of whether or not Danielles actions are acceptable may seem

    like a simple one, but if we evaluate it on a deeper level, we see that it is far from

    simple, and it brings up a number of complex questions about the ethics of

    cognitive enhancement. We know that Danielle was performing below average

    before taking Adderall. Its also true that Jeff struggled in school before he was

    diagnosed with ADHD and prescribed Adderall. If its okay for Jeff to use Adderall to

    fix his problems in school, why isnt it okay for Danielle to do the same thing? Some

    might say that because Jeffs use is therapeutic and has the purpose of correcting a

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    4/37

    Moran 4

    disorder, it can be distinguished from Danielles use, which only has the purpose of

    making her smarter. As it turns out, though, figuring out where to draw the line

    between therapeutic cognitive enhancement and non-therapeutic cognitive

    enhancement is a very difficult task.

    So how do we distinguish between therapy and enhancement? Should we

    even have to? Is therapeutic enhancement morally objectionable, permissible, or a

    moral obligation? Most importantly, what implications does cognitive enhancement

    have for fairness and equality, and what should we do about it?

    What is Cognitive Enhancement?

    Before we can define exactly what is meant by cognitive enhancement, we

    must first define what it is that cognitive enhancement techniques aim to enhance:

    cognition. The term cognition is often used to refer to many different things by

    different researchers in different fields, but in general, it is agreed that cognition

    refers to a number of different psychological skills that are necessary for humans to

    think and live. These include skills like perception (the ability to ascertain

    information from ones environment), attention (the ability to control what

    information is perceived and what is not), memory (the ability to retain

    information), reasoning (the ability to manage, analyze, and synthesize

    information), motor skills (the ability to effectively and efficiently control ones

    movement in the manner that is most in accordance with the information managed

    by the aforementioned skills), and cognitive executive functioning, a term for the

    brains ability to effectively and efficiently allocate the brains energy among the

    five other cognitive abilities. (Bostrom/Sandberg), (Bostrom/Roache).

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    5/37

    Moran 5

    The collection of specific skills that depend on one or more of the six aspects

    of cognition is massive; in fact, its extremely difficult to come up with a skill that

    humans use that doesntdepend on cognition in one way or another. As such, it is

    no surprise that researchers and customers are enthusiastic about the prospect of

    enhancing cognition; in theory, cognitive enhancement alone could drastically

    improve ones performance in every aspect of life. In practice, however, it is not

    that simple. The scientific community has not developed a bona fide smart pill

    that substantially improves all six aspects of cognition, and it is unlikely that it ever

    will. Cognitive enhancers instead tend to target one or two aspects of cognition in

    particular. For example, some of the popular modern cognitive enhancers that are

    often used treat Attention Deficit-Hyperactivity Disorder target attention and

    cognitive executive functioning, whereas the forms of cognitive enhancement that

    are being developed to slow or stop the onset of Alzheimers Disease tend to target

    memory exclusively. Different types of cognitive enhancers can affect the brain in

    many different ways, and each form of cognitive enhancement has a unique set of

    ethical implications. Though it may be tempting to do so, to make a

    comprehensive, sweeping judgment about the moral value of cognitive

    enhancement would ignore the significant differences in efficacy, permanence,

    effects, and ethical implications between the different types of cognitive

    enhancement.

    With a definition of cognition and the six cognitive abilities in place, we can

    now turn to cognitive enhancement itself. Like cognition, the term cognitive

    enhancement can entail a number of different types of treatments with varying

    degrees of efficacy and feasibility. The safest and least effective form of cognitive

    enhancers available today is found in a number of substances that fall into the

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    6/37

    Moran 6

    category of nootropic agents. The term nootropic, derived from the Greek words

    nous, meaning mind, and trepein, meaning to bend, was coined in 1972 by

    Romanian chemist Corneliu Giurgea. Although the definition has changed

    substantially since it was coined, Girugeas original definition is a fairly accurate

    description of what is characteristic of modern nootropics. Girugea defined a

    nootropic drug as one that (1) enhances learning and memory, (2) enhances the

    brains ability to resist conditions that tend to disrupt memory and learning such as

    oxygen deprivation or intoxication, (3) protects the brain against physical or

    chemical injuries, (4) improves the brains control of psychological and somatic

    processes (i.e. improves cognitive executive function), and (5) has no substantial

    side effects and very low toxicity. (Malik).

    Since Girugea coined the term, many have neglected the fifth aspect of this

    definition, declaring any pharmacological cognitive enhancer to be a nootropic,

    even those that have profound side effects and risk factors associated with them.

    Still others use the term only to refer to those substances that only increase the

    availability of existing chemicals (e.g. Oxygen, enzymes, hormones, and

    neurotransmitters) in the brain, rather than drugs that introduce a new chemical to

    the brain in order to have an effect on cognition. For our purposes, we can discount

    the second and third requirements of Girugeas definition, because the brains

    physical and chemical resistance to damage does not is not an aspect of cognition

    as we have defined it. Thus, we can consider nootropics to include all substances

    that improve cognition in some way, however marginal, without any substantial or

    noticeable side effects or risk factors.

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    7/37

    Moran 7

    The idea of a pill that can enhance cognition without any side effects may

    seem romantic and appealing to many, but the reality is that all nootropics that are

    currently available only very marginally improve cognition. Examples of modern

    nootropics include supplements, herbs, and vitamins that already enjoy widespread

    use. The most common and popular nootropics are B-vitamin supplements and

    Omega-3 fatty acids found in many supplements such as fish oil capsules as well as

    herbal remedies such as ginseng and Gingko biloba. Although these nootropics

    improve cognitive function, they will not dramatically turn an average human into a

    genius, and their effects on cognition are typically not significant enough to be

    noticeable.

    More significant cognitive enhancement can be found in the (usually illegal)

    use of pharmaceuticals initially developed to treat mental disorders as a means of

    temporarily improving cognition. Most of these pharmaceuticals were initially

    developed to treat dementia, Alzheimers Disease (e.g.donepezil, ampakines),

    Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder (e.g. amphetamine, methylphenidate,

    atomoxatine, pemoline), narcolepsy (e.g. amphetamine, modafinil), depression (e.g.

    fluoxetine), hypertension (e.g. propanolol), or mental retardation. (Whitehouse).

    Just as these drugs were found to bring those with cognitive deficits up to a normal

    cognitive level in other words, to cognitively enhance such individuals many

    have found that taking such drugs can bring an individual with normal cognitive

    capacities to enhanced levels. Besides nootropics and caffeine, pharmaceutical

    treatments for cognitive limitations are the most prominent and most widely

    discussed class of cognitive enhancers today. Most cognitive enhancers that are

    being developed today are emerging from efforts intended to effectively treat

    severe mental disorders but among the bioethical community, these kinds of

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    8/37

    Moran 8

    cognitive enhancers are less interesting than hypothetical future forms of

    enhancement that are more powerful and more permanent.

    The forms of enhancement we have discussed so far are a far cry from the

    dramatic, futuristic, and powerful forms of enhancement depicted in films such as

    Flowers for Algernon, in which a revolutionary form of neurosurgery enhances a

    mentally retarded adult into a genius whose intelligence comes to exceed that of

    even the researchers who enhanced him and the 2011 thriller Limitless," in which

    a failing writer begins taking a pill that allows him to access 100% of his brain,

    rather than the usual 20%. (It should be noted that it is an urban myth that humans

    only use 20% of their brains; brain imaging techniques have in fact demonstrated

    that no significant part of our brain goes unused. To only use 20% of a brain as

    complex as ours would constitute a very inefficient allocation of ones energy, and

    such inefficiency is almost always selected against by evolutionary pressures. The

    mechanism of cognitive enhancement depicted in Limitless is not the way that

    any of the forms of enhancement we are discussing here enhance cognition. This

    mechanism of enhancement has different ethical implications about identity and

    fairness, but we need not consider it.) The disappointing reality is that no such

    wonder drugs exist today, and it will be a long time before we come close to these

    fantasies. Cognitive enhancement technology is rapidly advancing, though, and

    although more profound modes of enhancement are not yet available, ethicists are

    obligated to consider what cognitive enhancement could mean to us in the coming

    decades; current trends in the field indicate that someday, enhancement

    technology could enable us to permanently alter our brain chemistry and cognitive

    capacities, either through more advanced pharmaceutical agents or by way of

    neurosurgery or genetic engineering. In this way, we might be able to someday

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    9/37

    Moran 9

    fundamentally alter the way an individual thinks and functions. This is a profoundly

    novel concept that raises a number of fascinating ethical issues, and the majority of

    the debate surrounding cognitive enhancement in the neuroethical community is

    futurological in nature; that is, it is concerned principally with ethical questions as

    they apply to possible futures for humanity. We should be grateful that this is the

    case, for it is far preferable to the alternative scenario, where new technologies and

    scenarios must be confronted without any substantial ethical background with

    which moral judgments can be made.

    We cannot examine the implications of technologies that aim to permanently

    change the way our brains work without also making some mention of the

    intellectual and cultural movement known as transhumanism. In the strictest

    sense, transhumanists affirm that humanity will someday have the technology

    available to fundamentally alter the human condition by eliminating aging and

    greatly enhancing physical and cognitive capacities and that when this technology

    is available, we ought to embrace it and make it widely available. Transhumanists

    seek to facilitate humanitys transition into a posthuman future in which some or

    all descendents of todays humans have been so profoundly altered that they no

    longer resemble normal humans and can be more accurately be classified as a new

    species of posthumans. Transhumanism is concerned with much more than just

    the prospect of powerful and lasting cognitive enhancement techniques, but a

    significant portion of philosophical debates about the merits of transhumanism are

    important to developing an ethics of cognitive enhancement, because as humanity

    approaches the transhumanists ideal future, the relevant questions will be less

    concerned with the ethics of enhancement in general and more concerned with the

    implications of crossing species boundaries and relations between humans and

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    10/37

    Moran 10

    posthumans. It would be nave of us to make sweeping judgments about cognitive

    enhancement in a general sense, for to do so would be to ignore the massive

    differences in efficacy, permanence, and effects of different kinds of cognitive

    enhancement. At the same time, we cannot neglect any of the different levels of

    cognitive enhancement if we are to conduct a comprehensive ethical analysis of the

    topic. Each different form of cognitive enhancement compels us to ask different

    ethical questions about what we should be able to do to enhance our own

    capacities, and each deserves its own thorough ethical evaluation.

    At what point does cognitive enhancement cease to be therapeutic?

    A distinction that is of great relevance in defining and ethically evaluating

    cognitive enhancement is the distinction between therapy and enhancement. We

    generally define therapeutic treatment as treatment that fixes a problem, disorder,

    disability or disease in an individual to bring him or her back to normal function.

    Enhancement, on the other hand can be defined as treatment that improves the

    positive health of individuals who would have otherwise functioned at normal levels.

    (McMahan). Very few ethicists have the audacity to question the belief that the

    severely disabled are entitled to therapeutic enhancement and that society is

    obligated to provide it to them. As our thinking goes, the severely disabled do not

    have the same opportunity and potential for success that the rest of the population

    has, and therapeutically enhancing such individuals, if not a moral imperative, is at

    least morally defensible on the grounds that such therapeutic enhancement is

    necessary to preserve the principle of equality of opportunity that is integral to

    Western culture. On the other hand, moral critiques of cognitive enhancement

    beyond the societal norm are abundant in the neuroethical community. Whereas

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    11/37

    Moran 11

    therapeutic enhancement restores fairness and equality, enhancement beyond the

    norm, it is said, undermines these principles.

    It is tempting to accept this dichotomy at face value, as evidenced by the fact

    that the two of the most notable cultural assessments of cognitive enhancement,

    Flowers for Algernon and Limitless, come out decidedly against cognitive

    enhancement and associate it with greed, arrogance, and the allegedly impersonal

    and dehumanizing nature of modern science. Some scholars would even go so far

    as to claim that this distinction between therapy and enhancement alone gives us

    the only relevant moral constraint on cognitive enhancement. Therapeutic

    enhancement, they claim, is inherently noble, and enhancement of the healthy is

    inherently wrong, regardless of the circumstances. Such a view is expressed by

    bioethicist Karen Bramstedt, who concludes her paper analyzing childrens use of

    caffeine as a cognitive enhancer by declaring that she has figured out the answer to

    all our questions about cognitive enhancement:

    The test for whether or not cognitive enhancement is cheating is the

    concurrent presence or absence of a clinically diagnosed cognitive deficit. In

    the presence of such a deficit, drug-mediated cognitive enhancement is not

    cheating but rather correction of a medical problem. In the absence of such a

    deficit, drug-mediated cognitive enhancement is a form of cheating because

    it circumvents the honest way of attaining excellencethat is, diligent

    study. (Bramstedt).

    In other words, Bramstedt claims that therapeutic enhancement is okay because

    (by definition) it is a correction of a medical problem, but enhancement beyond the

    norm is cheating, because it circumvents the necessity to study and work hard to

    achieve excellence. Theres a reason why this reasoning seems so intuitive and

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    12/37

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    13/37

    Moran 13

    taking fish oil capsules every morning? We cant avoid the fact that different forms

    of cognitive enhancement require different ethical analyses, and we cannot wrap up

    all of the hairy ethical issues that the topic brings up in a simple and intuitive

    statement.

    Most importantly, though, we cannot rely on the therapy-enhancement

    distinction, as Bramstedt does, in order to construct a robust set of ethical

    standards concerning cognitive enhancement, because the line that separates

    therapy from enhancement turns out to be a very blurry one, and its difficult to

    decide exactly where this line should be drawn. Consider the following scenario: A

    man who in most respects can be considered normal begins to feel depressed.

    After undergoing a psychiatric evaluation, he learns that he does not meet the

    diagnostic criteria for clinical depression. For simplicity, let us assume that his

    depression cannot be attributed to any other psychiatric disorder, and he just

    happens to be experiencing low-grade, sub-clinical depression, an everyday reality

    for countless people. Unable to obtain a treatment for his depression from a

    psychiatrist, he goes about illegally securing prescription antidepressants, which

    eliminate all traces of his depression, and enable him to approach everyday

    challenges with a newfound enthusiasm and positive attitude. Are we to consider

    the mans nonmedical use of antidepressants as treatment or enhancement, and to

    what extent are his actions morally justifiable?

    Bramstedts ethical standard specifically defined the permissibility of

    enhancement to be contingent upon the presence of a clinically diagnosed

    cognitive deficit, which would classify the mans actions as enhancement, not

    therapy, making them morally objectionable in Bramstedts view. Many would

    agree that, since antidepressants are intended to treat those who are clinically

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    14/37

    Moran 14

    depressed, one should not take them without being diagnosed as such. There is an

    important difference, however, between the competitive academic setting in which

    Bramstedt discusses the therapy-enhancement divide and the setting of our

    thought experiment. Bramstedt objects to cognitive enhancement of the healthy

    because it circumvents the honest way of attaining excellencethat is, diligent

    study. Her argument rests on the judgment that there is virtue inherent in the

    non-enhanced experiences that enhancement avoids: in this case, diligent study

    as a means of attaining academic excellence. Although this is a relatively

    unsupported normative statement, such statements cannot be avoided entirely in

    any meaningful ethical argument, and, more importantly, the virtue of hard work is

    a significant element of Western culture that is espoused by many. Bioethicist D.

    Gareth Jones, however, questions whether we can assign virtue to the non-

    enhanced experiences that the sub-clinically depressed man avoided by enhancing

    himself:

    If [sub-clinical depression] is not an illness, are some of the treatments

    illustrations of enhancement? If this concerns us, it follows that if some forms

    of depression are normal, then we should refrain from treating them.

    However, is there any virtue in living with sub-clinical depression if it can be

    treated? What we are beginning to encounter here is the very fine line

    between the normal and the pathological. (Jones).

    There is no apparent reason to believe that living with sub-clinical depression is

    virtuous, and it is doubtful that anyone holds such a view. It may seem like this

    thought experiment concerning depression doesnt apply to our analysis of

    cognitive enhancement as we have defined it; after all, mood is not one of the six

    aspects of cognition we are looking at. However, a strong case can be made

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    15/37

    Moran 15

    arguing that mood is intimately entwined with cognitive executive functioning, if

    they are not the same thing. Regardless of whether or not we accept this

    argument, though, this thought experiment has some unexpected implications if we

    apply the same reasoning to enhancements of other aspects of cognition. What if

    the man suffered not from depression but instead from poor reasoning skills? Let

    us assume, as we did before, that the man does not meet diagnostic criteria for any

    psychological disorder, and that the man is just dull, as are countless others. Would

    he be justified in nonmedically securing a (hypothetical) treatment for mental

    retardation that substantially increases intelligence and reasoning skills? Here, it is

    even more intuitively appealing than it was in the last scenario to conclude that the

    mans actions in enhancing himself were unethical. If we reflect on this though,

    such a conclusion turns out to be just as irrational; are we really prepared to claim

    that it is virtuous to live life as a fool?

    Since treatment and enhancement are both defined in terms of notions of

    normalcy and pathology, the very fine line between health and disease is

    accompanied by an equally fine line separating therapy from enhancement, and

    such a distinction is not a good foundation from which to develop an ethics of

    enhancement especially considering the fact that the bioethical community seems

    to be wholly unable to come to a consensus on where the line between disease and

    health should be drawn:

    . . . it is not necessary, and indeed it is probably fruitless, to try to draw a

    conceptual line between legitimate treatment and nonmedical

    enhancements by trying to limit the former to curing diseases and the latter

    to improving positive health. The concept of disease is notoriously elastic . . .

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    16/37

    Moran 16

    an appropriate line can be drawn simply by striving to allocate fairly medical

    services within a population. (Whitehouse).

    This system of bioethics, developed by James Sabin and Norman Daniels, does a

    somewhat better job than Bramstedts generalization does in defining the line

    between treatment and enhancement, and exploring cognitive enhancement

    through this ethical lens sheds light on some of the deeper ethical issues

    surrounding cognitive enhancement that Bramstedts model glosses over. Whereas

    Bramstedts framework depends on a simplistic and relatively arbitrary assignment

    of virtue to hard work and diligent study as a basis for her normative judgments,

    Sabin and Daniels model relies on the principle of equality of opportunity as a

    normative foundation. Although there is a case to be made that this principle is

    arbitrary as well, it is nonetheless a more sophisticated, more agreeable, and more

    universally accepted ethical foundation than is the virtue of hard work, which is why

    Sabin and Daniels normal functional model of medical necessity is popular and

    widespread among bioethicists. It turns out that Sabin and Daniels model does run

    into problems, because it is exceedingly difficult to define the concept of species-

    typical function on which the model is based, but this is beyond our concern.

    Should the cognitively disabled be enhanced?

    Until now, we have made the assumption that therapeutic enhancement is

    always permissible due to the fact that such a view is held by an overwhelming

    majority of bioethicists. However, Jeff McMahans Cognitive Disability and

    Cognitive Enhancement introduces a novel way of looking at therapeutic

    enhancement by evaluating it in the setting ofprenatal cognitive enhancement of a

    cognitively disabled fetus, allowing him to persuasively argue that the virtue of

    therapeutic enhancement, at least in this context, is nowhere near as strong as we

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    17/37

    Moran 17

    might think it is, and other, stronger moral imperatives might take precedence over

    therapeutic enhancement in certain situations. McMahan begins by establishing

    what sort of conclusions we would come to about prenatal enhancement if we were

    to assume that our intuitions about the difference between therapy and

    enhancement were accurate, as Bramstedt does:

    Most people . . . seem to believe that there is no moral reason to enhance

    the future cognitive capacities of a cognitively normal fetus, and perhaps

    even a reason notto, at least by genetic means. Yet even those who claim

    that disabilities are not misfortunes tend to concede that there is a moral

    reason, if possible, to enhance the cognitive capacities of a fetus that would

    otherwise be cognitively limited, and to do so for its own sake. [his italics].

    (McMahan).

    The relevant difference between the conventional ethical evaluation of

    enhancement and McMahans approach is that, whereas until now we have only

    been forming judgments about the extent to which an individuals conscious choice

    to enhance himself is morally defensible, we are now faced with the challenge of

    actually making this choice for a cognitively limited fetus, and we thus have to

    evaluate prenatal enhancement in terms of the desirability of the different possible

    outcomes that could come about by enhancing such a fetus or refraining from doing

    so.

    There are three different interests we have to consider in this thought

    experiment: the interests of the fetus, the interests of the individual that the fetus

    would grow into, and impersonal, societal interests. Based on the fetuss interests

    alone, it seems at first glance that we could quite easily develop an ethical

    argument for enhancing a cognitively limited fetus: although it is debatable whether

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    18/37

    Moran 18

    a life with cognitive disabilities is inherently worse than a cognitively normal life, it

    is relatively noncontroversial to contend that the fetus would have more dimensions

    of well-being accessible to it if it grew into a cognitively normal adult than it would

    have otherwise. Therefore, the outcome of enhancing the fetus is better for the

    fetus than the outcome of not enhancing it, and we can therefore conclude that it is

    morally good to enhance the fetus to serve its own interests. McMahan does not

    object to the conclusion that therapeutic enhancement is morally good but he

    does object to conventional beliefs about how morally good it is.

    It is difficult, if not impossible, to quantify the normative values that we

    assign to different outcomes, but this does not mean that we cannot develop a

    means for comparing moral obligations derived from future interests. McMahan

    surmises that the difference in value between the two possible lives determines

    the strength of the individuals present interest in the better of the two, which

    would mean that the magnitude of the moral obligation to enhance a cognitively

    limited fetus is proportional to the difference between the better outcome, a

    cognitively normal life, and the worse one, a cognitively limited life but this way

    of understanding the strength of the fetuss interest . . . is misleading. (McMahan).

    McMahan contends that noting the difference in value between two outcomes is not

    enough to fully evaluate how strong an individuals interest is in the better of two.

    In order to more accurately model an individuals future interests, the difference in

    value between outcomes must be measured based on what McMahan calls time-

    relative interest.

    McMahans model of time-relative interest essentially posits that any value

    judgment about the appeal of a certain future to a certain individual should be. . .

    discounted for the degree of psychological discontinuity between [the individual]

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    19/37

    Moran 19

    now and [the same individual] in the future . . . (McMahan). In other words, the

    more psychologically distant an individual is from the outcomes in question, the

    weaker that individuals interests in that outcome are. Typical theories of rational

    self-interest in economics and some fields of ethics assume that identity is constant.

    With this assumption in place, the extent to which a thing will satisfy an individual

    once he or she attains it can be measured by the magnitude of the individuals

    current desire for that thing. In reality, though, identity is not constant, even if we

    act and think under the assumption that it is. While this may not matter in

    economics, it is of great importance both in evaluations of cognitive enhancement

    and in ethical debates that concern the interests of unborn fetuses.

    The notion of a variable identity may seem counterintuitive at first. Ask

    yourself, though: can you really say with confidence that you are the exact same

    person today as you were as a newborn? Of course, if we are to accept the

    conventional view of identity at face value, then we certainly can say this but if we

    consider identity to be defined by the sum of psychological characteristics, the

    question becomes: can any of us say with confidence that he has the exact same

    psychological characteristics today as he had as a newborn? We obviously cannot

    say this, for if that were the case, we would have had the same memories, skills,

    preferences, and perceptions when we were newborns as we have at the present

    moment. If we abandon the conventional notion of identity, it is clear that we do

    not have the same identity today that we had as infants. The psychological

    discontinuity between a given individual as a baby and the same individual as an

    adult is comparatively massive; we could perhaps even conclude that some of our

    peers who are the same age as us are closer in identity to us than our present

    selves are to ourselves as babies.

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    20/37

    Moran 20

    Now that we have established that a stricter definition of identity forces us to

    conclude that identity changes as an individual grows, we can come to an intuitive

    understanding of McMahans time-relative interest through another thought

    experiment. Assume you are offered some large amount of money to spend

    however you want with the condition that, if you accept this money, it is guaranteed

    that you will die painlessly and instantly in ten years, no earlier and no later. This

    offer will only be available for the next five minutes and will never present itself

    again. How much money would have to be offered for you to accept it? Many

    would say that no amount of money is enough to counteract such a shortening of

    ones lifespan. What if, though, you were guaranteed to die not after ten years, but

    instead after eighty years? Those who would have accepted a large amount of

    money in the first scenario would probably accept the offer in the second scenario

    for much less money, and those who refused the first offer would probably be much

    more inclined to accept the second offer for some large sum of money. Indeed, it is

    very likely that countless individuals would pay large sums of money to guarantee

    an additional eighty years of life, even if in doing so they had to literally guarantee

    their death at a certain point. The reason why we are much more inclined to accept

    the second offer for a given amount of money than we are to accept the first offer

    for the same amount is because, although our interests in not dying will be roughly

    the same in ten years as they will be in eighty years, our present time-relative

    interests in not dying are much stronger for the first offer than they are for the

    second offer. Even on an emotional level, this phenomenon tends to hold true; our

    fear of imminent death is one of the most powerful and profound emotions we can

    ever experience, but our fear of eventual death is much more abstract and

    detached, and is lesser in magnitude as a result.

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    21/37

    Moran 21

    Despite the strength and philosophical utility of McMahans model, time-

    relative interest is something of a misnomer. Factors other than time can cause

    psychological discontinuity, such as cognitive enhancement. With this in mind, we

    can return to McMahans thought experiment and apply the notion of time-relative

    interest to evaluate the strength of the moral obligation to enhance a cognitively

    limited fetus, if we can still say that one exists. We already determined that,

    without taking into account psychological discontinuities, a cognitively normal life is

    better than a cognitively limited one. The psychological discontinuity between any

    fetus and any adult into which it will develop is great; it is for this reason that the

    question of the permissibility of aborting a fetus is so much more complex and

    controversial than the question of the permissibility of murdering an adult. This

    psychological discontinuity diminishes a limited fetuss interests in a cognitively

    limited life as well as its interests in a cognitively normal life, and the fetuss

    interest in living a cognitively normal life is furtherdiminished by the psychological

    discontinuity caused by cognitively enhancing the fetus. Because the psychological

    discontinuity between the cognitively limited fetus and itself in the future with or

    without enhancement is so large, McMahan is able to conclude that a cognitively

    limited fetuss comparatively weak interest in having normal cognitive capacities as

    an adult grounds only a weak moral reason to provide it with cognitive

    enhancement.

    McMahans model is a powerful one, but it does have one fatal flaw that could

    invalidate our entire analysis. All of McMahans judgments about an individuals

    interests in some action being taken have been evaluated in terms of that

    individuals interests in the outcome of that action. What McMahan fails to answer

    is this: when exactly is the outcome? McMahan makes the arbitrary decision to

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    22/37

    Moran 22

    evaluate the fetuss interests in terms of the quality of the fetuss life after it has

    developed into an adult, but what would happen to his conclusions if we instead

    defined the outcome to be the moment right after childbirth? This would greatly

    diminish the psychological discontinuity between the fetus and itself at the time of

    the outcome that weakened the moral imperative to enhance the fetus, making the

    resulting moral imperative to enhance the fetus much stronger. On the other hand,

    if we extend the outcome far enough into the future, the outcome will be the

    same no matter what: death. If this is where we define the outcome, this method

    of analysis would find no discrepancies whatsoever between any two given future

    timelines!

    Fortunately, we can easily fix the model to avoid this problem. To do so, we

    will not evaluate an individuals interest in a particular action being taken in terms

    of the desirability of the outcome, but instead in terms of the sum of the

    individuals interests in all moments in that individuals life in the timeline that is

    brought about by taking a particular action, after diminishing each of the terms of

    this sum by the appropriate amount due to psychological discontinuity. This way,

    we avoid the ambiguity brought up by McMahans negligence to clearly define how

    to determine when the outcome is, and our analysis takes into account the results

    of defining the outcome at any moment in the rest of the individuals life.

    Although McMahans model has allowed us to make a strong case against the

    intuitive belief that there is a strong moral imperative to enhance a limited fetus,

    our entire analysis thus far has been conducted in the context of McMahans original

    thought experiment that aimed to determine the moral value ofprenatal

    therapeutic enhancement. One might think that this would mean that we cannot

    generalize the conclusions of our analysis to questions of therapeutically enhancing

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    23/37

    Moran 23

    individuals who have already been born. Recall, though, that we have only been

    evaluating the strength of the first of the three different interests that might ground

    a moral imperative for prenatal therapeutic enhancement: the interest of the fetus,

    as it exists at the present moment, in living a cognitively normal life. To figure out

    how our judgments about prenatal therapeutic enhancement would apply to

    cognitively disabled individuals after they have been born, we need only turn to the

    second of the three interests that need to be considered: the interest of the

    individual into whom the fetus will develop.

    The two outcomes under consideration remain the same; the individual will

    either live a cognitively normal life or a cognitively limited one. The magnitude of

    the future adult individuals interest in the fetus receiving enhancement, then, is

    measured in almost exactly the same way. As was the case when measuring the

    fetuss interest, the magnitude of the adult individuals interest in prenatal

    enhancement is proportional to the difference in value between the two outcomes.

    Since the outcomes under consideration here are the same as before, this step in

    the analysis does not reveal any distinctions between the interest of fetus and the

    interest of the adult in prenatal therapeutic cognitive enhancement. Unlike the

    fetus under consideration, the adult under consideration is not separated from the

    outcomes we are considering by time or by biological development, and the adults

    interests in prenatal enhancement are therefore not weakened by psychological

    discontinuity in this respect. However, the psychological discontinuity caused by

    cognitive enhancement still applies, and this discontinuity will also weaken the

    adults interests in being enhanced. Thus, the adult into whom the fetus will

    develop does have a weak interest in prenatal enhancement of the limited fetus,

    but it is not as weak as the interests of the fetus itself in being enhanced.

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    24/37

    Moran 24

    We will now concern ourselves with the question of how the interest in

    therapeutic enhancement will change if the cognitively limited individuals under

    consideration have already been born and now have the option of being

    permanently enhanced. In order to approach this question with the same method

    of analysis we have used to evaluate prenatal enhancement, let us make the

    assumption that the individual under consideration is so severely cognitively limited

    that we must make decisions for it, as we did for the fetus. As it turns out, there is

    no difference whatsoever between the interest that the individual into whom a

    cognitively limited fetus will develop has in prenatal cognitive enhancement and the

    interest that a cognitively limited individual has in post-birth therapeutic cognitive

    enhancement, because in the eyes of the ethical test we are using, the two

    scenarios are exactly the same; the outcomes that we are deciding between are still

    a cognitively limited life and a cognitively normal life; no significant psychological

    discontinuity arises from differences in time or biological development between the

    individual whose interests are under consideration and the individual who will

    experience the outcomes under consideration, but the ultimate moral imperative to

    enhance is weakened in both cases by the psychological discontinuity between a

    cognitively limited and a cognitively normal mind. We can therefore conclude that

    any moral obligation to enhance a cognitively limited individual will be a weak one

    but how weak will it be?

    The moral imperative to enhance was weakened due to the significance of

    the difference between the individuals psychological state before enhancement

    and after enhancement. It follows, then, that the moral imperative will be

    weakened more when this difference is greater. We must not forget, though, how

    McMahan initially assigned normative value to a given action: . . . the difference in

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    25/37

    Moran 25

    value between the two possible lives determines the strength of the individuals

    present interest in the better of the two. Although more powerful forms of

    enhancement yield greater psychological discontinuity between pre-enhancement

    and post-enhancement states, weakening the moral imperative to enhance, they

    also yield a greater difference in value between the two possible outcomes,

    strengthening the moral imperative. I will not take on the task of determining which

    of these effects is stronger, but it suffices to say that all forms of therapeutic

    enhancement, regardless of efficacy, are especially limited in virtue and

    relative importance, owing either to the insubstantial amount by which they

    improve the lives of cognitively disabled individuals or to the psychological

    discontinuity between the cognitively limited individual before and after

    enhancement. It may seem that, in making this judgment, weve lost sight of the

    precautions and standards for analysis that we deemed so important earlier: It

    would be nave of us to make sweeping judgments about cognitive enhancement

    in a general sense, for to do so would be to ignore the massive differences in

    efficacy, permanence, and effects of different kinds of cognitive enhancement, but

    notice that, unlike Bramstedt, we have considered the varying degrees of

    enhancement in our analysis, and we have put forth an argument for why the same

    judgment will hold true for all of them, so we are justified in making a generalized

    conclusion about enhancement in the abstract.

    Some might point out that although we have developed a very robust

    argument against conventional beliefs about therapeutic enhancement, we have

    only proved that the moral imperative to therapeutically enhance is weak, not that

    it does not exist at all. Proving this may seem like a pointless exercise, but even

    relative claims about the moral value of medical procedures can be very useful and

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    26/37

    Moran 26

    can have important applications. As of now, our society makes a number of implicit

    judgments about the extent to which we are morally obligated to help people with

    disabilities, including the cognitively disabled. These judgments are manifested in

    the amount of taxpayer money that we have decided to allocate to government

    programs like Medicaid and Medicare, which have to treat many cognitively

    disabled individuals, relative to other taxpayer-funded services. It is worth the

    effort to work through this ethical analysis of therapeutic enhancement, because,

    with a new understanding of the relative importance and virtue of therapeutic

    enhancement, we might decide that we ought to re-evaluate the way we currently

    allocate government resources to therapeutic enhancement relative to projects that

    fulfill other societal goals. Our conclusion, like most bioethical conclusions, might

    have comparably important applications for private insurance companies and

    hospitals as well.

    Should we want to enhance ourselves?

    The power of McMahans model is apparent in the way that it allowed us to

    generalize our conclusions about therapeutic enhancement to both fetuses and

    grown humans and to all different forms of enhancement. If this analysis can cross

    firm and substantial boundaries like the boundary between the interests of a fetus

    and the interests of a person and the boundary between nootropics and

    transhumanist, species-altering, cognitive enhancement technology, then perhaps it

    can also traverse a boundary that we have shown at length to be blurry, thin,

    ambiguous and elusive: the line between therapy and enhancement. If we are to

    consider the same amount of cognitive enhancer being used both to bring a

    cognitively limited person to a normal cognitive level and to bring an average

    person to an enhanced level, then theres actually nothing whatsoever that

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    27/37

    Moran 27

    distinguishes therapy from enhancement; although the outcomes being considered

    are different, the difference in value between enhancing and not enhancing from

    which the magnitude of interest in enhancement is being measured is the same for

    therapeutic enhancement as it is for enhancement beyond the norm. Similarly, the

    degree of psychological discontinuity between the unenhanced individual and the

    enhanced individual, and thus the extent to which these interests are weakened is

    the same for therapy as it is for enhancement. A cognitively normal individuals

    interest in being cognitively enhanced is thus the same as a cognitively

    disadvantaged individuals interest in being therapeutically enhanced. The average

    persons interest in cognitive enhancement beyond the norm is not associated with

    a proportionally strong moral obligation, as was the case with therapeutic

    enhancement, because in this case we are not exploring what is best for others but

    instead what is in our own best interest. Nonetheless, the conclusions we were able

    to draw about what is in the best interests of a cognitively limited individual apply in

    the same way to the best interests of cognitively normal individuals. This means

    that although normal individuals do have an interest in being cognitively enhanced,

    this interest is a weak one that is inferior to a number of other interests that the

    cognitively normal may have to weigh as well in making decisions.

    Those who find the idea of cognitive enhancement emotionally appealing

    may dislike being told that their seemingly strong interests in enhancement are

    actually relatively weak; for if this is the case, then why doesnt cognitive

    enhancement only come off as weakly appealing? Before moving on, it would serve

    us well to revisit why McMahans measure of time-relative interest is discounted by

    psychological discontinuities. We have established that ones net psychological

    state and, by extension, ones identity is not constant and will change as an

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    28/37

    Moran 28

    individual grows. As a result, your identity a year from now may resemble your

    identity today in most respects, but it will not be the same. Your identity in ten

    years will be even less similar to your identity today, and this is why things that are

    going to happen in a year tend to have more immediate emotional significance to

    you right now than things that will happen in ten years. The more that the identity

    of a future version of you differs from your current identity, the less you can

    accurately call that person yourself. Any desire essentially comes down to an

    interest in a future version of oneself experiencing some particular experience, for it

    is impossible for us to satisfy our present desires in the past or in the present

    (unless we are to act so fast that we instantly satisfy our desires the moment we

    come up with them). This means that we pursue desires by trying to make

    something happen for some future version of ourselves. Were not doing this out of

    sympathy for our future selves, whom we have never met and might not know

    anything about; if that was the case, wed be just as inclined to purchase a meal for

    a person sitting on the opposite side of a restaurant at which we were eating as we

    would be to purchase a meal for our (future) selves. We are still acting out of self-

    interest, but our actions only fulfill our self-interest to the extent that the future self

    psychologically resembles the present self. If one goes about trying to achieve

    some goal at age 15, but by the time this goal is achieved, three years have passed

    and 50% of the individuals brain has changed, then we might say the 15-year old

    only experiences 50% of the satisfaction that would have been experienced if the

    goal had been achieved instantly. The amount that an individual psychologically

    changes before attaining a goal is inversely related to the extent to which that

    individual enjoys the full benefits of attaining that goal.

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    29/37

    Moran 29

    Putting this in terms of cognitive enhancement, we can conclude the efficacy

    of the cognitive enhancer being used is inversely related with the extent to which

    our present selves will enjoy the benefits of being enhanced. If Harold takes a weak

    nootropic cognitive enhancer at 3:00 that only marginally enhances his cognition,

    Harold at 3:01 will only be a slightlydifferent person than Harold at 2:59, and the

    2:59 Harold enjoys almost all of the benefits from the nootropic that the 3:01 Harold

    experiences. In contrast, if Sara undergoes a reconstructive neurosurgical

    procedure from 3:00 to 4:00 that dramatically improves her memory, then Sara at

    4:01 will be a substantially different person than Sara at 2:59. As a result, although

    the 4:01 Sara will experience all of the benefits of the surgery, the 2:59 Sara

    experiences significantly less of these benefits, and the fraction of the total benefit

    (i.e. the benefit that the 4:01 Sara will experience) that the 2:59 Sara enjoys is less

    than the fraction of the total benefit that the 2:59 Harold enjoys, because the

    psychological discontinuity between 4:01 Sara and 2:59 Sara is greater than the

    psychological discontinuity between 3:01 Harold and 2:59 Harold. It may seem

    strange that we must be so insistent on evaluating what portion of the benefits 2:59

    Harold and 2:59 Sara experience despite the fact that the treatments do not

    begin until 3:00. Of course, the corporeal individuals that can be called Harold

    and Sara at all times (We must make sure that we maintain a tone that

    implements our stricter definition of identity, even though the conventional notion

    of identity is so intimately tied with the use of names in our culture that doing so

    seems a bit absurd and awkward at first.) will not literally experience the benefits of

    their treatments at 2:59. To understand this, we need to think of 2:59 Harold, 2:59

    Sara, 3:01 Harold, and 4:01 Sara to be four distinct individuals while simultaneously

    assuming that 2:59 Harold and 2:59 Sara arepartially preservedbeyond their

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    30/37

    Moran 30

    instantaneous moments of existence as distinct identities and incorporated into the

    identities of 3:01 Harold and 4:01 Sara, respectively. We cannot simply evaluate

    the treatments in terms the benefits that 3:01 Harold and 4:01 Sara experienced,

    because we are not trying to figure out how cognitive enhancement will benefit

    anyone at all we are trying to intuitively understand how cognitive enhancement

    will affect the individuals that exist before enhancement. Since the ethical analysis

    is conducted before any enhancement occurs, the 2:59 versions of Harold and Sara

    are the only relevant individuals who actually exist, and the only individuals whose

    interests in enhancement matter in our analysis. As we can see, our conclusion that

    there are only weak reasons for a healthy individual to cognitively enhance himself

    or herself does not disregard the emotional appeal of being cognitively enhanced.

    This appeal is represented by 2:59 Harolds interest in experiencing what 3:01

    Harold will experience and 2:59 Saras interest in experiencing what 4:01 Sara will

    experience. The reason why the 2:59 individuals interests in deciding to enhance

    themselves are not the same as their interests in experiencing what the post-

    enhancement individuals will experience is because making this decision will not

    bring about those experiences for the 2:59 individuals at least, not entirely. This

    is the crucial point to understanding why McMahans model works on an intuitive

    level, and it requires us to distance ourselves from the conventional notion of

    identity as much as possible. Thus, the forms of enhancement that are effective

    enough to be strongly emotionally appealing to you should actually be no more

    rationally appealing to you than the weaker forms of enhancement, because the

    extent to which you would get to see the benefit of this enhancement is much

    less for more effective cognitive enhancers.

    Is cognitive enhancement fair?

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    31/37

    Moran 31

    We may have established that cognitive enhancement is desirable to us,

    even if it is to a very weak extent. The strongest ethical problem cognitive

    enhancement faces, though, is that of fairness. Our society is dedicated to

    protecting the principle of equal opportunity for all, which was the moral principle

    behind the imperative to provide therapeutic enhancement to the cognitively

    limited. Does permitting cognitive enhancement undermine equality of

    opportunity? After all, cognitive enhancement gives some individuals an

    improvement in cognitive abilities that we could be expect to be accompanied by an

    increase in opportunity. If some individuals are able to increase their opportunity

    through enhancement, do we have a responsibility to ensure that everyone can

    increase their opportunity by the same amount? To determine how the bioethical

    community would approach this question, it benefits us to turn to a similar ethical

    debate that has already been well-developed and well-publicized: that of the

    permissibility of the use of anabolic steroids as athletic enhancement in professional

    sports.

    Those arguing that athletic enhancers should be allowed usually argued not

    that athletic enhancement itself was morally permissible, but instead that individual

    liberty should allow athletes to use anabolic steroids if they wish, or that a ban on

    steroids is unenforceable or would have negative consequences. There is a case to

    be made, though, that using athletic enhancers, even within competition, is in and

    of itself morally justifiable. How could this be the case? Because, some argue,

    athletic enhancement is already an important part of competitive sports. Most

    runners would run a faster mile wearing running flats than they would barefoot.

    Most baseball players would play a better game after weeks of training than they

    would after a year of vacation. Hockey players who want to win often seek out the

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    32/37

    Moran 32

    best brands of skates and sticks they can find. Anabolic steroids allow athletes to

    transcend their biological limitations and perform better but isnt this exactly the

    purpose of using better running shoes, better training techniques, and better

    hockey sticks? In effect, tools, training, and dieting techniques all can be said to fall

    under the label of athletic enhancement. Why should steroids be treated

    differently?

    To determine if there is any morally relevant distinction between standard

    use of tools and training as enhancement and the use of anabolic steroids and other

    pharmaceuticals as enhancement, we first have to decide whether we aim to

    measure participants objective abilities or participants abilities relative to their

    competitors. In competitions like the shot put and the long jump, players receive

    objective scores which measure participants innate abilities. In competitions like

    the SAT, however, a test which assigns participants a normalized score that

    measures a participants location in the distribution of all participants scores on

    that particular test, or in two-team competitions like baseball, basketball, and

    football, we are not concerned with measuring innate ability, only relative ability.

    Next we must determine whether the form of enhancement in question

    fundamentally changes an individuals demonstration of competency in the respect

    we which to measure it in. The introduction of fiberglass poles to pole-vaulting

    dramatically increased the heights that vaulters could reach and forced them to

    alter their technique, but they were permitted perhaps because they didn't

    change the fundamentals of the sport. If somebody wanted to wear roller skates to

    the Boston Marathon, however, it'd be hard to argue that the benefits provided are

    analogous to those provided by air-cushioned running shoes or running flats,

    because roller skates would dramatically change the fundamental meaning of the

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    33/37

    Moran 33

    sport. Whether or not anabolic steroids change athletes demonstrations of

    competency is still debatable, and is different for each sport, but the majority of

    sporting institutions continue to prohibit them.

    To evaluate whether cognitive enhancement would be unethical in cognitive

    competitions, like chess matches, spelling bees, and the SAT, we have to look at

    what it is we value in the contest itself, and whether the use of enhancers changes

    the participant's attempt at demonstrating competency in that respect. The use of

    calculators as a means of effective cognitive enhancement on the SAT is not

    prohibited, because the SAT aims to measure relative ability, and The College Board

    has determined that, provided that all students taking the test have access to them,

    calculators do not change students demonstration of relative ability.

    In light of our analysis of the time-relative merits of cognitive enhancement,

    we ought to point out a peculiar implication of enhancement in the competitive

    context that must be considered when the contest measures cognitive abilities

    rather than athletic abilities. Because athletic enhancement usually affects the

    body rather than the mind, the psychological discontinuity between a cognitively

    enhanced individual and the same individual without enhancement does not apply

    to athletic enhancement. As a result, there is no difference in identity between an

    unenhanced and an enhanced athlete (unless one considers the body to be an

    element of identity, which we have not done). As a result, if the enhancement

    fundamentally changes the athletes demonstration of competency, the legitimacy

    of the competition is threatened. Athletic enhancement changes ability but not

    identity; the competition therefore would therefore assess the same individual more

    favorably than intended. As we determined earlier, though, the psychological

    discontinuity associated with cognitive enhancement changes an individuals

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    34/37

    Moran 34

    identity to an extent that is proportional to the strength of the enhancer. The

    competition therefore does not judge the same individual more favorably than

    intended it instead judges a differentindividual with the same name and body as

    the unenhanced individual more favorably than it intended to judge the unenhanced

    individual. So although at first glance it may look like cognitive enhancement

    qualifies as cheating, the way that cognitive enhancement changes identity means

    that, in the strictest sense, it does not diminish the legitimacy of the competition

    like athletic enhancement does. Of course, cognitive enhancement only partially

    changes an individuals identity, so we cannot give cognitive enhancement a free

    pass. The extent to which the legitimacy of the competition is threatened is,

    somewhat counter-intuitively, greater for the least effective forms of enhancement.

    At the same time, though, the least effective forms of cognitive enhancement will

    have the least significant effect on the results. For each sport, the significance of

    the effect on the results, the significance of the psychological discontinuity between

    an unenhanced individual and the same individual after enhancement, and the

    extent to which the enhancement fundamentally changes participants

    demonstration of the factor we wish to measure must all be taken into

    consideration in determining whether using a particular cognitive enhancer is

    unfair.

    Examining the issue in this manner calls our attention to an interesting

    question which we can evaluate through another thought experiment. Assume a

    chemical is developed that drastically improved reasoning skills, but there are only

    enough resources to synthesize enough of this chemical for one person. The

    government decides that this chemical should be given to a person randomly

    selected from all babies born in the next year. Tom, who has an identical twin

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    35/37

    Moran 35

    brother named Tim, is selected and receives the enhancer in infancy, developing

    into a hyper-intelligent individual with extremely powerful reasoning skills. Tim, on

    the other hand, is average in all respects. While in high school, the two twins take

    the SAT on the same day. Tom scores a 2400, the maximum possible score, and

    Tom scores a 1500, the average score. If we make the assumption that the

    psychological differences between Tom and Tim significantly outweigh their

    differences in score, then, according to our analysis, Tom deserves to outscore Tim.

    Now assume that fraternal twins Tod and Rod take the same SAT test on the same

    day. Tod is naturally smarter than Rod, so much so that Tod scores a 2400 and Rod

    scores a 1500. Societal morals would imply that Tod deserves to outscore Rod, and

    it was because of these societal morals that we were able to conclude that Tom

    deserved to outscore Tim but why exactly does either Tod or Tom deserve to

    outscore his twin? Both of them did not receive their advantage through hard work;

    there is nothing in particular that would indicate that Tod and Tom are entitled to a

    cognitive advantage more than Tim and Rod are. Before coming into existence, Tod

    and Rod had the same chance of having such an advantage over the other, and

    before the smart pill was randomly assigned, Tom and Tim had equal chances as

    well. Does the fact that the distribution of cognitive advantage is random really

    make it fair that some individuals are naturally smarter than others? To answer this

    question, or to develop an ethical model that did not assume that it is fair that

    natural advantages are distributed by a genetic lottery would be a daunting

    philosophical task that I will not take on here, but this question deserves to be

    asked, and further research ought to be conducted in this area. If we can reject the

    fairness of the genetic lottery, then we can conclude that cognitive enhancement is

    without a doubt unfair in cognitive competitions, but as long as our society does not

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    36/37

    Moran 36

    take issue with the genetic lotterys distribution of cognitive advantages, some

    forms of cognitive enhancement will have to be permissible.

    Conclusion

    Answering ethical questions about cognitive enhancement is an exceedingly

    difficult endeavor, and it seems that the only way to responsibly develop an ethics

    of cognitive enhancement is on a case-by-case basis. Intuition would tell us that the

    only relevant distinction determining whether cognitive enhancement is permissible

    is the distinction between therapy and enhancement but as it turns out, finding a

    satisfactory definition of where this distinction lies is almost impossible. Ethicists

    ought to abandon their fruitless pursuit of a line that cleanly divides permissible

    therapy from contemptible enhancement, for there are much more sophisticated

    ways to ethically evaluate cognitive enhancement that hold true for both therapy

    and enhancement. Factors that need to be taken into consideration include the

    efficacy and permanence of the form of cognitive enhancement under

    consideration, the nature of the competition whose legitimacy is allegedly

    threatened by cognitive enhancers, and the magnitude of psychological

    discontinuity that enhancement causes.

    All of this analysis has been conducted within a moral framework that has

    questionable implicit assumptions. Our society currently has no issue with

    rewarding some people more than others simply because some are more

    genetically lucky. Although religion may see this issue differently, the extent to

    which this assumption holds in a secular society is extremely questionable. To

    maintain a consistent moral frame, ethicists have two options. We must decide

    between accepting the fact that cognitive enhancement will sometimes be

  • 8/6/2019 Designer Genius an Ethical Investigation of Cognitive Enhancement

    37/37

    Moran 37

    permissible or confronting the fact that our societal morals might be largely

    founded on a fallacious assumption. The latter task is a formidable one, but we

    have a responsibility as human beings with moral integrity to undertake it, even if it

    means we might have to drastically restructure the way our society works. The

    intuition of the layman may fiercely oppose such a transition, but, as we have seen,

    intuition often comes to deeply erroneous conclusions about what is best for the

    individual and for society. Attempts to question societal moral norms will

    undoubtedly be labeled as sinful, reprehensible, wicked, and vile but let us not

    forget why we undertake these tough ethical endeavors in the first place: to make

    the world a better place for all who inhabit it.