concept of other in anthropology

Upload: raclettes

Post on 03-Jun-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Concept of Other in Anthropology

    1/5

    The 'Other' in Anthropology and PhilosophyAuthor(s): Sundar SarukkaiSource: Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 32, No. 24 (Jun. 14-20, 1997), pp. 1406-1409Published by: Economic and Political WeeklyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4405512.

    Accessed: 28/04/2013 16:26

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Economic and Political Weeklyis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Economic and Political Weekly.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=epwhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4405512?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4405512?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=epw
  • 8/11/2019 Concept of Other in Anthropology

    2/5

    h e O t h e r

    n

    nthropology a n d

    hilosophy

    Sundar Sarukkai

    The totion of the 'other' has become very

    prevalent in social sciences. Here the 'other' is examined as it occurs

    in

    anthropology

    and

    philosophy,

    primarily

    through Levinas and Derrida. Based on this, a radical

    revision of

    anthropological knowledge,

    'ethicall)

    'oriented and

    incorporating

    subjectivity

    as

    an

    essential element,

    is

    suggested.

    Finall), it is argued that within such a frameworkfiction has to be considered as a valid ethnographic data.

    M N SRINIVAS makes a few provocative

    and timely comments n his recentarticleon

    Indian

    anthropology Srinivas 1996].

    Two

    important bservationshave to do with

    the

    notion

    of

    self-in-the-other nd he suggestion

    that ndian

    nthropologists

    houldnow move

    to the studyof the self fromself-in-the-other.

    Unfortunately,

    he has not

    developed

    these

    concepts in

    more detail.

    The

    thematisation

    of the other

    and the self is of fundamental

    importancend s primarilynformed hrough

    philosophyandpsychology. The aim of this

    paper

    s to

    explicate the natureof

    the other

    and the self as

    they occur

    in

    anthropology

    and

    philosophy,

    hus

    addressing he

    nherent

    tensions

    in

    ethnography.

    After

    a

    brief introduction o

    the way

    the

    other is

    understood

    in

    anthropology,

    the

    more

    philosophical approaches through

    Levinas

    and Derrida are

    explained.

    The

    importanceof

    cknowledging he

    Levinasian

    other

    in

    anthropological discourse

    is

    underlined.

    This

    demands of

    ethnography

    an

    'ethical responsibility' owards

    he

    other

    which will go beyond objectifying he other.

    Srinivas' remarkson self-in-the-otherand

    on

    the

    relevance

    of

    autobiography

    as

    ethnographys discussed nconnectionwith

    this other.

    Finally, it

    is

    argued that the

    perpetual

    absence of the other

    which

    manifests

    itself

    only

    in

    terms

    of

    its

    traces

    gives

    a

    valid reason to look towards

    fiction

    as a legitimate tool for

    anthropological

    studies.

    The

    Anthropological

    'Other'

    Jacob Pandian n his clear

    exposition

    on

    anthropology

    and the

    other, suggests

    that

    the 'Judeo-Christian

    ymbol(s) of divinity

    and the Christianconceptionof the human

    self'

    [Pandian

    1985:5],underliesthemodem

    anthropological

    iscourse.The construction

    of

    the

    other was with

    'characteristics

    which

    are

    alien

    to

    the

    western

    tradition'

    [Pandian

    1985:6].

    Modern

    anthropology

    arose when

    it began to contrastand alienate he cultures

    which were different from the

    west,

    and in

    fact the

    uniqueness

    of

    anthropology

    itself

    'stems from the use of

    the

    human other'.

    The

    primnary

    ole

    of

    anthropology

    thus

    was a

    process

    of

    'inventing

    he

    human

    other'

    in order

    o

    develop

    a

    theory

    of

    humankind.

    This

    anthropological other is basically

    epistemological.

    It is based on the notion

    of

    perceiveddifferences and is a

    cognitive

    process nvolving observation, ollection

    of

    dataandtheorising.Thus, there s a

    plethora

    of

    human others which appear

    in

    anthropology.

    Pandian lists some of the

    dominantothers

    used n thisdiscoursewhich

    includesthe

    fossil other,savage

    other.

    black

    other and the ethnographicother.

    In the

    discourse

    on

    progress,development

    and

    rationality which had

    become

    characteristic f the west as described

    by

    themselves.the search for

    the

    basic human

    condition gave rise to the fossil other. The

    non-western people were seen to

    embody

    what the primeval west was before

    its

    'progress' and thus were seen as 'living

    fossils'. The

    historicalgrowthof

    these

    ideas

    show inherent

    deas

    of

    domination. Thus,

    the

    idea

    of

    the non-western people

    as the

    living fossil drewsupport rom he historical

    and biological theories

    of

    the times.

    Consistently,

    he other

    stood

    for an inferior

    human and was even

    understood

    in the

    paradigm

    of

    the

    native children as

    against

    the

    adult west.

    Much of these ideas overlap in the

    constructionof the

    savage other,

    primarily

    oriented towards

    the

    Africans and which

    subsequently

    encompassedeven the Indian

    people. Similarly,

    or the

    black

    other,

    whose

    continued

    mportance

    ies in the validation

    of racism

    itself.

    Pandian also establishes a

    critique

    of

    ethlnography

    and the

    ways

    in which the

    preoccupation

    f the west

    regarding

    he

    non-

    west still reflectsmuchof theirprejudices.

    The reasons

    why ethnography tself

    'works'

    seems to be

    more a reflection of economic

    and social dynamics of inter-cultural

    relationships. In fact, he suggests that

    'eliminatingprejudice

    would be

    eliminating

    anthropology' [Pandian

    1985:92].

    The

    basic

    problem

    n

    the

    anthropological

    other

    is

    that it

    is

    never a

    recognition

    of the

    other;

    rather t

    is

    just

    an

    epistemological

    other which perhaps says more about the

    epistemological

    ystems

    of the

    ethnographer

    rather han

    any

    'honest'

    description

    of

    the

    other.

    Anthropology,

    unlike other

    sciences,

    is

    not.a

    study

    of inanimate-ness nd thus has

    to

    go beyond

    the

    epistemological

    models

    derived

    fromthesedisciplines. suggestthat

    the problem of the anthropologicalother is

    due to this process, and one way out is to

    look for anotherway to thematise he other,

    through a process which will grant to

    anthropology its unique status as a study

    of humans.The way out is to re-understand

    the other and perhaps integrate into its

    epistemology an ethical responsibility

    towards the

    other.

    The anthropological other is one based

    purelyondifference.Butthisdoesnotaddress

    the basic

    ssue

    of

    the human elf constructing

    the other.

    The notion

    of

    the othercannot ie

    only in difference; if so, thereis really no

    difference in acknowledgingthe othemess

    of a rose plantor a zebraand hatof a person.

    Rightly too, one can make a distinction

    between observing the behaviouralpatterns

    of

    a

    community

    of zebrasand a

    community

    of

    people.

    If

    the latter

    constitutes

    ethnography,

    then

    ethnography comprises

    more than

    mere observation and

    categorisation of behavioural patterns or

    kinship tructures.Whatmakes heothemess

    of humans the other is more than this.

    Following Levinas, and ater

    Derrida,

    place

    the thematisation

    of

    the

    other

    in

    an ethical

    domain. It is the ethical imperative, an

    acknowledgement f thedemandof

    the

    other

    that creates the

    responsibility

    towards

    the

    other.

    It is this

    responsibility,

    which fills the

    notion of

    the other

    in

    Levinas, that

    differentiates he otherness of zebra andof

    humans.

    The anthropological other, based on

    difference,

    has forsaken he

    responsibility

    of

    the subject towards the other.

    In

    the model

    of

    epistemology of the physical sciences,

    it

    has

    forsaken the notion

    of

    responsibility

    from

    the objectivedomain.Anthropological

    knowledge,

    n

    constructing he

    otherwithout

    theethical mperative,acrificestheotherness

    in order o

    objectify

    humans nto

    things

    and

    subsume he other

    nto the

    'same'.

    Objective,

    rational

    pistemology

    is based on the denial

    of

    any

    ethical relationbetween the

    self and

    the

    object. Founding

    its

    epistemology

    on

    thismodel,ethnographys blind o thedictates

    of the

    other.This

    anthropological

    thermakes

    animals out

    of

    humans,

    if not worse.

    A

    reprieve

    was

    given

    to

    anthropology

    n

    the

    guise

    of Malinowski who

    emphasised

    the

    importance

    of

    studying

    alien

    cultures

    n

    the form of

    participant-observation.

    But

    1406 Economic and Political Weekly June 14, 1997

    This content downloaded from 194.94.96.194 on Sun, 28 Apr 2013 16:26:42 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Concept of Other in Anthropology

    3/5

    Malinowski's

    ethnography still remains

    a

    categorisation

    of

    difference, a

    taxonomy of

    humanobjects. It does

    not even come close

    to addressingthe

    fundamentalproblemof

    otherness.

    Participant-observationttempts

    to build on this

    but its response falls

    way

    short.

    The process of the

    anthropological

    'stranger'

    seeking

    to define

    the native

    has

    made

    the native alien

    while upholding

    the

    autonomy

    f the

    western

    elf. In his

    scenario,

    the alien

    who invades the

    territory

    of

    the

    native takes

    over the spirit of the native

    by

    constructing hem as the other. The

    nature

    of

    the other in this case is vcry clear: it is

    otheras

    not-self. The

    nitial

    anthropological

    othersuffers

    ontinuously rom his

    violence,

    a violence of

    the

    refiguration

    of

    the

    constitution of

    the native self. This other

    in this

    case

    is

    all that the

    ethnographer

    s

    not. It s this

    othernessof the

    ethnographer's

    self that this

    kind of ethnographic

    study

    yields andnot theselfof the native.

    Coupled

    to this is

    the

    distancing

    of

    subjectivity

    in

    staking

    an

    epistemological

    claim

    to

    anthropologicalobservation which further

    risks

    osing the 'essence'

    ofthe native's self.

    This

    activity s

    in

    its most fundamental

    ense

    an

    objectification

    of the natives which in the

    process ends

    up

    objectifying

    the

    impartial

    observer

    him/herself.

    In

    participant bservation,

    he 'distance';

    of the

    native from the

    observer s

    sought

    to

    be reduced

    by becomingone of the natives.

    The

    dress,

    the

    customs and

    language

    are

    borrowed,

    however

    imperfectly,

    to fit the

    gaze

    of theobserver.But

    afterall he

    attempts

    at

    assimilation,

    he

    gaze

    is still not lost.

    Here

    the other is understood differently. By

    simulating

    the

    otherness

    of

    the

    native,

    the

    observer

    constructs

    his

    self as

    'not-other'.

    Although

    in

    opposition

    to

    constructing

    he

    otheras not-self. The

    constructionof self as

    'not-other'does

    equalviolence

    on

    the

    notion

    of otherness. The

    observing

    self

    continues

    to remain

    the

    epistemological

    'not-other'.

    As

    long

    as the

    gaze

    of

    the

    observer

    searches

    out for

    structuresuntold and

    hidden

    by

    the

    natives,

    it becomes a

    violent act. Violence

    arises

    here in the Levinasian

    sense of not

    heeding

    the

    ethical call of

    the other,

    the

    ethicalcall

    whichdemands

    responsibility

    of

    theobservingself towardsthe native other.

    Thus,

    n

    both

    hesecasesof

    anthropological

    observation,

    he other s

    constructedandnot

    realised on a

    pre-categorical

    level.

    Only

    epistemological categories of the other as

    'not-self and the

    self as 'not-other'

    remain.

    Both

    these continue with the

    supposition

    that

    there

    is

    no

    responsibility

    to the

    other

    andremain eaf

    o its call. Suchan

    abrogation

    of

    responsibility

    is

    only because the

    epistemological

    models

    are

    understoqd

    o

    be

    so. But this

    obviously

    does not serve the

    anthropological

    concern and

    opens

    anthropology

    o the charge of

    colonialism.

    II

    The

    Philosophical Other

    I would like to

    approach he discussion

    of

    the other n philosophyprimarily

    hrough

    Levinas

    andDerrida.Levinas'coflcem

    arises

    at

    a

    pre-philosophical, pre-cognate level.

    The

    ability to

    distinguish humans from

    animals is

    by

    acknowledging the human

    otherasother.This

    other

    s

    more undamental

    than

    any human activity. It is

    the

    responsibility towards the other

    that even

    makes dialogical peech

    andreason'possible

    [Degnin 1995]. In his

    reading of Levinas,

    Degnin situates the

    importance

    of

    the 'face

    of

    the other' as

    evoking the subject.It

    is

    the

    call

    of the otheras one

    like me which begets

    this ethical

    responsibility.Thus, theOther

    is

    the

    first

    truth,but not in

    a cognitive sense.

    Ratherthis truthis

    the experience of the

    ethical call that

    eventuates

    prior

    to and is

    constitutive of

    reason, metaphysics and

    discourse

    [Degnin 1995].

    When the self

    attempts

    to

    subsume

    the

    other nto the

    'same',

    then

    there

    s

    violence

    done

    against

    the

    other. There is an ethical

    responsibility not to

    violate the other by

    reducing

    t to one's own

    system

    of

    thought.

    The violence arises in

    ignoring this a priori

    ethical call.

    Ignoring

    he call is also to

    view

    the

    other

    as

    an

    object

    of

    knowledge. Doing

    so, only

    eliminates the

    identity

    of

    the other

    and

    re-figures

    t in

    the

    eyes

    of

    the

    subject,

    'thereby incorporating

    he other into

    the

    identity

    of the

    constituting ubject'

    [Powell

    1995].

    The deeper problem here

    is

    one of

    representation.

    he other s

    represented,

    nd

    perhaps

    even constituted

    through,

    this

    representationn the way of the subject.It

    is the

    process

    of

    representing

    heotherwhich

    subsumes

    it

    into the

    intelligibility

    of

    the

    subject

    and

    negates

    its

    identity.

    Levinas'

    writings

    on the

    other

    situateshis

    concern

    n

    the ethical

    space.

    But thisethics

    is

    not the ethics

    ordinarily

    understood as

    system

    of moralsand

    prescriptions.

    He

    points

    the

    path

    not to a

    theory

    of

    ethics but

    of

    orientingthe ubject owards

    acknowledging

    and

    responding

    o the

    'ethical',

    before

    it is

    categorised by

    knowledge.

    As

    Derrida

    remarks, what Levinas

    proposes

    to

    understand

    s

    the

    essence

    of the

    ethical

    relation in general [Derrida 1978]. Ethics

    has o

    be basedon a

    'pre-given

    thicalrelation

    to

    which all ethics

    responds' [Powell

    1995].

    Powell makes

    the

    point

    that ethics is

    dependent

    on a

    theory

    of the

    subject

    and the

    ethical edifice is

    based on the

    'active

    agent

    as the

    foundationof ethics'.

    Levinas

    draws

    us to the

    recognition

    of

    the ethical which is

    not

    based

    on

    the

    hegemony

    of the

    subject

    but

    ratheras

    one which

    responds

    o the

    pre-

    cognitive

    relationwith

    the other. In

    fact,

    as

    Powell

    remarks,

    the

    very

    notion of

    subj}ectivity

    risesonly because the

    subject

    is responding o the other, who is

    prior to

    the

    subject n the

    sense

    that the

    other makes

    possible

    the transformation romsubjectto

    subjectivity.

    Knowledgeof theother, n terms

    of its

    representation,omes after his

    response

    to the other

    and

    prior

    to the

    taking-up

    of

    history, I

    have already responded to the

    other, he

    meaning

    of

    ethics has

    alreadybeen

    given, I have

    already been subjectedto

    the

    history of the

    other [Powell 1995].

    In his later work[Levinas

    1981], Levinas

    shifted to the notion

    of trace

    in

    order

    to

    understand

    the other. The

    Derridean

    'differance' would be an

    ideal

    word to

    describe

    this

    other

    -

    not

    only

    is

    the

    other

    different but it is also in

    perpetual

    postponement. When I

    grasp towards the

    other,

    I

    am left

    holding,

    continuously,

    races

    of

    the other. The traces

    constitute the

    perpetualabsence of the

    other; because he

    Other is

    structurally

    absent

    -

    always

    unreachable

    [Degnin 1995].

    My

    responsibility

    towards

    the other makes

    me

    plod

    along diligently, going from one trace

    to

    the

    next,

    forever

    thus

    constructing

    the

    othemess. It

    is

    in this

    acknowledgement

    of

    theperpetual

    ostponement hat

    heotherness

    lies.

    Acknowledging

    this is

    accepting the

    implausibility

    of

    completeness; the

    responsibility

    ies in

    accepting

    what s

    granted

    and

    to

    plod

    on in

    the

    path

    of

    possible

    infinite

    significations.

    But this

    responsibility

    s

    not

    ontological, not

    so

    long

    as it sees the other

    only

    as a

    knowable

    entity.

    The

    awareness

    of the

    other

    in

    terms of an

    ethical

    responsibility

    is what makes

    the

    process

    ontological. Thus,

    in

    order to be 'true' to

    the

    other,

    ethnography

    hould

    base

    itself on

    the

    concept

    of

    differance rather than

    one

    based on difference.

    Theideaofthetraceis

    importanttoDerrida

    in his

    critique

    f the

    'metaphysics

    f

    presence'

    -

    even as we

    prioritisepresence

    we

    lose

    all

    that s

    present

    hrough

    absence.

    This

    presence

    of absence is

    marked

    hrough

    with the trace

    oftheother.

    Keameypoints

    out

    that

    although

    the

    early

    Derrida's work

    focused on the

    epistemological

    contrast

    between

    presence

    and

    absence,

    his

    later

    works

    show

    'emphasis

    on the

    question

    of

    ethical

    responsibility'

    [Kearney1993].Theethical ssue hereshould

    beunderstoodnthe

    contextdescribed

    bove;

    as

    Kearney

    remarks,

    deconstruction's

    obsession with alterity is compatiblewith

    the

    ethics of

    'increased

    responsibility '

    [Kearney

    1993].

    Deconstruction,

    unlike

    many

    mistaken accounts of

    it. partakes

    a

    responsibility

    which n its foundational

    ense

    is

    a

    search for the other. The continued

    onslaught

    n the

    reduction nd

    representation

    of the

    other

    impels

    the

    ethical

    directedness

    of

    deconstructionwhich

    above all becomes

    'an openness

    towards the

    other'

    [Kearney

    1993].

    The above

    discussion

    suggests that the

    apparent

    polarity of the self

    and the

    other

    is still immersed n the

    subject/objectdivide.

    Economic and Political

    Weekly

    June

    14, 1997

    1407

    This content downloaded from 194.94.96.194 on Sun, 28 Apr 2013 16:26:42 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Concept of Other in Anthropology

    4/5

    The presenceof the otheralso continuously

    points to its absencewhich is manifestedby

    its traces. The inevitability of

    trace also

    points o the impossibilityof having

    a 'final'

    reference which does

    not refer to anything

    else. Thecontinual

    postponementof rasping

    the

    other n its fullness s

    the absenceof

    such

    a reference.At the most fundamental

    evel,

    there is left only the notion of ethical

    responsibility

    which binds the self and the

    other.Languagecannot

    ranscend

    his;

    rather,

    it

    reflects

    hisresponsibility

    n its

    full entirety

    -

    'language

    is ethics' [Kearney 1993].

    Thus, the philosophical deliberations

    on

    the other strikeat the fundamentalproblem

    with the anthropologicalother. This

    other

    is

    basedon

    an

    artificial

    ubjectlobject ivide,

    which,as manyphenomenologistshave

    ong

    argued,

    is untenable. In fact, Derrida,

    as

    quoted by

    Kearney,has

    this to

    say,

    ...it

    is

    the other

    which invokes and provokes

    the

    subjectbefore any genuinc questioning

    can

    begin Kearney1993].Theabovediscussion

    perhapspoints

    to the

    importance

    f

    integrat-

    ing this notion of the other within the

    anthropologicaldiscourse,

    but

    it is a

    vexing

    problem

    as to how

    one

    integrates

    he notion

    of ethical

    responsibility

    withinan

    epistemo-

    logical system.

    Althougha clear

    answer is

    not

    available,

    it

    opens

    us

    to

    the illusion

    of

    complete and closed description

    of any

    'object'

    of

    inquiry.

    It also

    suggests

    that

    anthropologyhould inddifferentparadigms

    of

    knowledge

    whichare

    basedon the

    critique

    of

    westernmetaphysics.

    One of the ways

    of

    doing this

    is

    discussed

    in the final section.

    III

    Self-in-the-Other

    Srinivas n his article

    (1996) points

    to an

    underlying

    difference'

    between

    an Indian

    anthropologiststudying

    Indian tribals

    as

    against

    the

    'foreign' anthropologist.

    Since

    the Indian anthropologist

    and the tribals

    inhabit the

    'same cultural

    urverse',

    he

    suggests

    that he tribalsare

    never

    )tally

    the

    other.This relationshipof inhabitin-g

    n

    the

    same

    space

    leads him to

    suggest

    that

    n this

    case it is self-in-the-other

    which s

    operative.

    Whether this

    will be acceptable to the

    practicing

    ield worker rom

    another ulture

    is not the issue addressedhere. My main

    interest

    s in

    understanding

    he other andin

    this

    context

    the

    other used by

    Srinivas

    also

    carries with it the

    baggage

    of the anthro-

    pological

    other. Self-in-the-other

    s

    not an

    ontological

    category. The

    other of Levinas

    towards

    which

    the subject

    has the ethical

    engagement

    is

    'pre-philosophical

    and

    pre-

    cognitive'.

    But there

    is

    an

    important onsequence

    of

    this

    self-as-the-other.

    would ike to

    explicate

    this in more

    detail

    by basing

    it on

    the

    notion

    of subjectivity,which, I suspect, s atthe

    root

    of this view.

    If the tribalother is accessible

    as a totally

    objectifiedother

    hen it does not matterwho

    the ethnographers. In other words,

    if

    the

    subject/object divide

    is

    enforced

    in the

    traditionalway, then the object

    s 'out there'

    waiting to be

    discoveredand categorisedby

    the ethnographer. The adequacy

    of this

    description

    will then depend on the

    competence of

    the ethnographer.

    Phenomenologists, in general, have

    difficulty

    in

    accepting

    such a facile

    subject/

    object divide.

    To

    them,

    objectivity

    is

    intricately

    enmeshed

    with the notion

    of

    subjectivity.It is the subject's orientation

    which informs what the object

    is. Further

    discussion on

    this is

    beyond

    the scope

    of

    this

    paper.

    The

    point

    nevertheless

    is

    important

    to place the

    self-in-the-other as one more

    expression

    of the presence

    of

    subjectivity

    n

    all

    humanactivity, including epistemology.

    The perception

    of theother.for example,

    the tribalother,

    is

    dependenton

    the

    subject

    who

    perceives.

    For an enthropologistwho

    has a shared

    history/culturewith the tribals,

    the perceptionof the tribalswill definitely

    be differentbecause

    of

    the

    orientation

    f

    the

    anthropologist

    towards

    the tribal other.

    Srinivas' call to a

    study

    of

    the self-in-the-

    other suggests

    a

    revision in

    the

    way

    anthropologists

    should think

    about the

    subject/object

    ichotomy.Immersed s they

    are in western metaphysicalepistemology,

    they

    fail

    to see the

    importance

    f

    recognising

    epistemological

    systems

    in

    which

    the

    subjective plays

    the central

    part.

    There

    shouldbe a little caveatevenamong

    anthropologists

    o

    the

    claim that

    the

    study

    of

    tribals

    by

    an Indian

    anthropologist

    would

    be 'different' than by a 'foreigner'. But

    serious

    disagreements

    may

    ariseon themerits

    of

    this

    difference, primarily

    because

    of the

    belief

    that

    there

    is some true

    knowledge

    outside

    us

    waiting

    to

    be discovered.

    But in

    placing hisdebateon thephenomenologist's

    position

    on

    subjectivity, hey

    would be hard

    pressed to counter

    the

    importance

    of the

    concept

    of

    self-in-the-other.

    I

    give

    a

    rather tenuous example

    of the

    importance

    f the

    role

    cultural

    history

    of the

    subject plays

    in

    ethnography.

    f we look at

    the idea

    of the

    other, primarily through

    common

    anguage

    used

    n

    India,

    we

    find

    that

    the otherhas a different meaninghere than

    in the west. There

    is, maybe

    in all Indian

    languages,

    a

    conception

    of the other

    which

    is

    different from the

    way

    the

    word is

    used

    in

    English

    or

    French,

    for

    example.

    The

    commonly

    used

    word for the other

    n

    Tamil,

    Kannada

    r

    Malayalam,

    or

    example,

    s

    'one

    more'. The phrase 'one

    more' has different

    connotations than

    the 'other'.

    Firstly,

    it

    quantifies

    his notionof otherness.

    Secondly,

    it

    implies

    that the

    other

    is

    nothing

    but one

    more of the self. The

    distancing

    of

    the

    self

    and the other s totally different

    as reflected

    in such usage. This conception hides in it

    the notion of self-in-the-other.

    n

    Hindi, the

    commonly used

    word for

    other

    s

    translated

    as 'second' and ess

    commonly,

    'one

    more'.

    Once again, hese arequantified ermswhich

    stand for the other and carry

    with

    them the

    implication

    of

    the other

    as

    extension

    of one's

    self. For a person steeped in this tradition,

    this

    does make a

    qualitative

    difference in

    constructing

    he other. think

    his,

    n

    essence,

    is what Srinivas' call to Indian

    anthropologists

    s about.

    IV

    Autobiography and the

    Other-in-the-Self

    Srinivas suggests that the autobiography

    of an individual should

    be a valid

    ethno-

    graphic ool. 'Why cannot

    an

    anthropologist

    treat his own

    life

    as an

    ethnographic

    ield

    and

    study

    it?'

    [Srinivas

    1996]. I would

    like

    to

    bring

    this

    importantpoint

    nto

    the

    context

    of the above discussion.

    The essence of

    autobiography

    s the

    other-

    in-the-self. Self-in-the-other respondsto a

    relationship primarily mediated spatially

    between

    the self and the other. It is this

    perpetualdistance rom

    he

    self and he other

    which underlies ethnography. A temporal

    characters also

    present

    n

    such

    a

    relationship

    but

    is not

    manifested

    in its

    immediacy.)

    The case of autobiography

    s

    different. It

    is

    fundamentally

    n articulation f theother-

    in-the-self. The self writes its

    biography

    at

    a

    given present.

    The

    reconstruction

    of the

    self

    in

    this act is to recordevents

    in

    the

    past.

    The autobiographybecomes a collection of

    the residue of the self and is

    temporally

    constituted. The autobiography.s nothing

    more than an inscriptionof the other within

    oneself.

    The self which inhabited itself

    becomes

    the otheronce

    it

    goes past

    he

    iving

    moment.

    Thus,

    a life's recollection

    gives

    a

    series of

    pictures of the

    other which is

    continuously

    connected o

    the

    present, iving

    self.

    Thisotheriscapturednotthroughpatial

    distancing

    of

    the

    self from the

    other

    but

    purely

    as a

    temporal process.

    The

    anthropological

    other-in-the-self

    is

    thus

    a

    recreation

    of

    the other

    which inhabits

    the

    self.

    The

    ontological counterpart

    f this

    is not

    available,

    at least in

    my reading

    of

    Levinas. But this point of omission can be

    rectified. In

    autobiography

    as

    a written

    act,

    as

    self-reflection

    of our

    past,

    the self comes

    face to face with the other

    which

    once

    inhabited

    he

    self.

    Coming

    face

    to

    face

    with

    my-other

    has all

    the characteristics f

    coming

    face to face with an-other.Levinasianethics

    is

    directed o

    the

    otheroutside

    myself

    without

    taking

    into account this

    possibility

    of the

    response

    of

    myself

    to

    the other

    which

    resides

    in

    me. And this shows the

    implausibility

    of

    the ethical

    responsibility ndependent

    f the-

    .'direction'

    of the gaze towards heother.The

    ethical response to the other-in-my-self s

    1408

    Economic and

    Political

    Weekly

    June

    14,

    1997

    This content downloaded from 194.94.96.194 on Sun, 28 Apr 2013 16:26:42 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Concept of Other in Anthropology

    5/5

    different from the one

    towards an other

    spatially separated rom me. The call 'not

    to kill'

    [Degnin 1995], is a

    corporeal call

    which

    neglects the possibility of the other

    which resides in me,

    unless, in this case, it

    is seen as a call not to

    commit suicide.

    I

    would ike to call thisethnographic tudy

    of one's own life as

    auto-ethnography. t is

    easy to

    understandwhy such a methodwould

    belookeduponwithsuspicion.

    Thedominant

    reaction

    against this

    activity will be based

    on

    the excessive presence of

    subjectivity

    in such a

    process. Since knowledge,

    anthropologicalor

    otherwise,

    has

    made a

    virtue of making the

    subject

    invisible,

    this

    processof

    auto-ethnographywould be seen

    as

    epistemologically suspect.

    But as our

    previous

    rguments howed,

    this

    forcedexile

    of the

    subject

    is

    totally misplaced. The

    richness of

    epistemology

    increases as the

    subjectiveelement

    is

    absorbed.Thus, at the

    conflux of

    anthropologyand

    philosophy we

    can situate the

    re-discovery

    of the

    subject

    into our

    knowledge games.

    In this

    case,

    auto-ethnography

    ecomes a valid tool of

    anthropological knowledge.

    Srinivas'

    emphasis

    on the

    self-in-the-other and his

    suggestion

    of

    auto-ethnography

    hows his

    underlying

    unease

    with

    the exclusion of

    the

    subject

    romthe

    anthropological

    discourse.

    He,

    tops

    at

    this

    uncture

    but an

    extrapolation

    of the above ideas

    naturally

    leads me to

    consider

    iction as a valid

    ethnographic

    ool.

    V

    Anthropology

    and Fiction

    The

    relevance

    of fiction in

    anthropology

    is not a new idea, as many quotable quotes

    by

    eminent

    anthropologists

    attest. What I

    shall do here

    is

    suggest

    cogent

    reasons to

    consider fiction as

    a

    valid

    tool in

    anthropology,

    ased

    on

    theabove

    arguments.

    Fiction tands

    as

    the

    exemplarof ubjective

    construction

    f the

    world.

    Anthropologyby

    its exclusion of the

    subjectiveposition by

    objectifying

    human

    communities

    and

    by

    creating

    he

    anthropological

    other can

    have

    no

    use

    for

    fiction.

    This

    distancing

    of fiction

    is best

    exemplified by

    the

    way

    anthropological

    theris

    constructed,

    s

    based

    on

    difference and

    clearly

    referential. The

    ambiguityof the otheris repressed n order

    to

    get

    as

    'true' a

    picture

    as

    possible.

    Within

    such

    a

    dogma, fiction,

    by

    its

    exploding

    possibilities,

    n its

    refusal o exile the

    subject,

    is

    immediately

    ruled out.

    If

    anthropology

    s

    willing

    to

    go beyond

    this other it constructsand into

    recognising

    its

    function as

    answering

    the ethical call of

    the

    other,

    then we

    will

    have

    to

    address the

    relevanceof fiction as

    ethnographic

    data.

    It

    is in the nature

    of

    the other that

    such

    a

    possibility

    arises.

    The

    other,

    as mentioned

    above,

    is a trace as we grasp

    toward,>

    t,

    it escapes leaving behind just

    the trace of

    its

    presence. The complete grasping of the

    otherig

    mpossible. t sjust this

    phenomenon

    which is the spirit of

    fiction. A story of

    a

    community, for

    example, is filled with the

    tracesof the

    other, n termsof itspossibilities

    and actualities.The

    footprintsof the other

    dot the

    work of fiction which

    when taken

    together will allow us

    an archive of traces.

    It is within

    this that the other is constituted.

    Fictionis also a

    method which allows for

    subjective

    orientations in

    describing the

    world.

    The richness, the ambiguity and

    contradictions of

    this description are

    anathema

    o

    the

    objective

    epistemological

    schemes which rest

    on the belief towards

    attaining

    completeness

    and non-

    contradiction.But as

    we

    have

    seen, the world

    cannot

    sustain the

    burden

    of

    being

    broken

    artificially nto the

    subjectandobject;cannot

    base itself on the

    terrorof finite and closed

    knowledge.

    Thus,

    if

    anthropology

    wants to extend its

    domain

    beyond 'objective'

    ethnography,

    f

    it

    s

    willingto accept

    ts

    responsibilityowards

    t4c other,

    then the

    relevance of fiction

    as

    a

    valid epistemological tool should be

    acknowledged. Since the other

    is not

    an

    'object'

    which

    can

    be

    completely

    accessed

    through rational'

    pistemologies,and since

    its

    presence derives

    through

    its

    perpetual

    absence,

    fiction

    becomes one

    of the

    most

    important

    ways through

    which the traces

    of

    the

    other can

    be

    identified.

    Perhaps

    there

    is

    a

    lesson

    in

    this for

    all

    social

    sciences,

    including philosophy.

    Philosophy

    is not immune from such

    a

    criticism

    and

    artificial

    distinctions

    between

    philosophy and

    iterature re

    also

    untenable.

    Rorty, who

    perhaps hould

    be

    consideredas

    the

    spokesperson

    or this

    view,.shouldhave

    the last

    word:

    ...the

    mportant

    lace

    to

    draw

    a

    line is not

    between

    philosophy and

    non-

    philosophy

    but rather

    between

    topicswhich

    we know how

    to argue

    about

    those

    we do

    not

    [Rorty

    1993].

    [I hankMNSrinivasorenthusiasticiscussions

    which

    madethis

    work

    possible. I

    also thank

    Dhanu

    Nayak or her

    manycritical

    omments.]

    References

    Degnin, Francis

    Dominic (1995): 'Laughter

    and

    Metaphysics: Interruptionsof Levinas

    and

    Nietzche',

    Philosophy Today, 39:1.

    Derrida,Jacques 1978):

    Writingand

    Difference,

    (translated

    Alan

    Bass),Universityof

    Chicago

    Press, p 111.

    Kearney,

    Richard 1993): 'Derrida's

    EthicalRe-

    turn' nGary

    Madison(ed),

    WorkingThrough

    Derrida,

    Northwestern

    University Press.

    Levinas,Emmanuel 198

    1):Otherwise han

    Being

    or

    Beyond

    Essence, (translated

    Alphonso

    Lingis), MartinusNijhoff.

    Pandian, Jacob (1985):

    Anthropology and the

    WesternTradition,

    Waveland Press, Inc.

    Powell, Jeffrey (1995): 'Levinas

    Representing

    Husserlon

    Representation:

    An

    Ethics

    Beyond

    Representation',Philosophy

    Today, 39:2.

    Srinivas,

    M

    N

    (1996): 'Indian

    Anthropologists

    and the

    Study

    of

    Indian

    Culture',

    Economic

    and

    Political

    Weekly,

    Vol

    XXXI,

    No

    11,

    March.

    Rorty, Richard

    (1993): 'Is

    Derrida

    a

    Transcendental

    hilosopher'

    n

    Gary

    Madison

    (ed),

    WorkingThroughDerrida,Northwestern

    University

    Press.

    REVIEW OF WOMEN STUDIES

    April 26, 1997

    Pursuing Third

    World

    Women's Interests:Compatibility

    of Feminism with Grass Roots Development

    -Archana Kalegaonkar

    Women's Paid Domestic

    Work and Rural Transformation:

    A

    Study

    in

    South

    Gujarat

    -Uma Kothari

    Women Panchayat Members

    in Kerala: A Profile

    -Manu

    Bhaskar

    Female

    Infanticide

    n Tamil Nadu:

    Some Evidence

    -Sheela Rani Chunkath

    V

    B Athreya

    Unmet

    Need

    for

    Family

    Planning

    in

    Gujarat:

    A Qualitative Exploration

    -Leela Visaria

    The Review of Women Studies

    appears

    twice

    yearly

    as a

    supplement

    to the last

    issues

    of

    April

    and

    October.

    Earlierissueshave

    focused on: Genderand

    Development

    Indices (October 1996);

    Women and Science

    (April 1996);

    Women's Rights

    and

    Social

    Change (October

    1995);

    GenderIssues in

    Theory

    and Practice

    (April 1995);

    Women'sMovementinThirdWorld(October994);

    Genderand

    tructural

    djustment

    (April 1994), Women and Public Space (October 1993);

    Community,

    State and

    Women's Agency (April 1993).

    For

    copies

    write to

    Ciwculation

    Manager

    Economic and

    Political

    Weekly

    Hitkari

    House, 284,

    Shahid

    Bhagatsingh Road,

    Mumbai 400 001

    Economic and Political Weekly

    June 14, 1997

    1409

    This content downloaded from 194.94.96.194 on Sun, 28 Apr 2013 16:26:42 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp