causation according to the chinese hua-yen tradition

Upload: brad-sommers

Post on 03-Apr-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    1/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    Causation in the Chinese Hua-Yen TraditionBy Francis Cook

    Journal of Chinese Philosophy

    V. 6 (1979)

    pp. 367-385

    Copyright 1979 by D. Reidel Publishing Co.

    .367

    he Chinese Hua-yen tradition is an academic form of Buddhism which arose in the later part of the seventh centu

    nder the leadership primarily of Fa-tsang (643-712) and his two later successors, Ch'eng-kuan and Tsung-mi. It important form of Buddhism because, first, in its predominantly syncretistic and interpretive work, it drew togethehe diverse philosophical strands of Buddhism and rewoven them into the one Dharma which Buddhism is suppose. It thus shows that all the philosophical traditions and schools of Buddhism are parts of an integral whole. Secoecognized as it has been since its formation as the culmination of Buddhist philosophical enterprise, its descriptiohe structure and nature of existence has served for over a thousand years as the metaphysical presupposition of Zend Pure Land Buddhist ethics and practice. But the reason why this tradition is of some interest to students of

    Western process thought is that, in its predominant concern with the problem of causality, in its tendency to equateeality and causal efficacy, in its generally Buddhist belief that the what of things can only be understood in termshe how of things, and in its portrayal of reality as a dynamic continuum of constantly changing, interdependent p

    has more in common with Western process thought than any other form of Buddhism, not excluding Naagaarjun

    Maadhyamika.

    Hua-yen may be described as the Chinese response to Naagaarjuna's thought, specifically the teaching of emptins interdependent being. Ya.h pratiityasamutpaada.h `suunyataam taa^m praca.smahe. (Kaarikaas ch. 24, vs. 18). B

    more generally Hua-yen represents the Chinese way of understanding the dominant philosophical concern of the wrevious history of Buddhism, which is the concern with causality. It is my belief that Hua-yen Buddhism shows t

    Chinese Buddhists by Fa-tsang's time clearly understood the Indian emptiness doctrine and that the Hua-yen treatmf the doctrine is in no sense a distortion of the Indian material. The observable differences are due, I believe, to arucial shift in emphasis, and the potential for such

    .368

    shift was latent in the Indian data. The new interpretation and emphasis were due to a gradual tendency on the pahe Chinese to fit the Indian doctrine to certain presuppositions, patterns of thought, and esthetic orientations whic

    were peculiarly Chinese and which felt right to them. This difference in emphasis may be stated in various ways.While both Indian and Chinese Buddhists understood emptiness as being synonymous with interdependence, thendians emphasized the point that, because of this pervasive interdependence, things lack any ultimate reality and nworthy of attachment. For the Indians, emptiness as the absence of any enduring permanence, substantiality, andalue was of paramount importance. The Chinese chose to stress the point that emptiness is the interdependentelationship of real phenomenal events. The Indian view tends to be negative in its devaluation of events, and reduhem to the level of insignificance and triviality. The Chinese view tends to raise all events to a common level ofupreme value by seeing their crucial roles in the nexus of interconditionality. Fa-tsang himself recognized thisifference in negative and affirmative appreciations of emptiness, when he says, in the Hua-yen i-ch'eng chiao i fe

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    2/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    h'i chang,

    Naagaarjuna's argument is based on negation, while the [Hua-yen] six meanings of cause rely onaffirmation. In his 'eight noes,' the principle of emptiness is revealed through the negation of common-sense judgements. In the six meanings of cause, common-sense judgements are negated through anaffirmative revelation of the principle. However, the two methods are just six of one and a half dozen ofthe other.[1]

    hus, both traditions rest on the principle of emptiness, but Naagaarjuna achieved this by negating the common-se

    udgements that things are born and cease, arrive and depart, and so on. Fa-tsang instead shows how all things deppon each other in the ceaseless process of interdependent becoming, and in doing so, these same judgements areegated. But the vision of things mutually creating and sustaining gave rise to gratitude, respect, and somethingpproaching love which were absent in the Indian view.

    The doctrine of `suunyataa is, stated in the most direct way, a denial of the independent existence of any thing. riticising events as empty, the `suunyavaadins rejected the view according to which an event or thing is what it isirtue of an underlying substratum of a metaphysical nature which endows the event with self identity over a spanme. Any event is that particular event for an exceedingly brief period of time, if it can indeed be said to endure and then it becomes a new event. This constant change in turn

    .369

    s due to the changing nature of the conditions which constitute the environment of the particular event. Thus, themptiness doctrine should not be understood as a naive rejection of the material world as pure illusion; it indeedecognizes the existence of the natural world but denies that it has any duration or independent being. In fact, beinejected in favor of a constant, never-fully-completed becoming. The utterly impermanent, substanceless nature ofecoming process is underscored in the Kaarikaas when Naagaarjuna negates even the concept of causality. Consi

    with his radical critique of mundane experience, he points out that there can be no causation unless there is some thwhich can act as a cause, and since anything which we may isolate as a cause is itself the impermanent effect of otvents, there is nothing which can be identified as cause.

    Between the time Naagaarjuna systematized the emptiness doctrine in the middle of the second century and the t

    f the final systematization of Hua-yen by Fa-tsang in about 700 A.D., the Chinese had come to understand the Inoctrine perfectly. It is true that in earlier generations, there had been a tendency to misinterpret both the meaning unction of the doctrine, but Hua-yen treatises show that by Fa-tsang's time, not only did the Chinese understand toctrine adequately, but they also had assimilated the doctrine so well that in their own writings they could discusdea creatively in a manner consistent with native sensibilities. Hua-yen Buddhist thought is Chinese because the bormats which were Indian in origin came to be expressed through the medium of patterns of thought and estheticendencies which are distinctly Chinese. I should add here that while the Chinese treatment of emptiness does not iolence to the Indian idea generally, it is true that Fa-tsang's treatment is in some ways at variance with that of

    Naagaarjuna. However we must remember that Naagaarjuna represents one form of `suunyavaada and handles it innique manner, and there is a vast amount of `suunyavaada literature which adopts a different approach. While

    Naagaarjuna's Maadhyamika is `suunyavaada, not all `suunyavaada is Maadhyamika. In many ways, the Indian

    octrine paralleled concepts which were parts of Chinese thought. However, the Indian concept arrived in Chinaolored with Indian patterns of thought and presuppositions, and it was finally appropriated by the Chinese when itltered through Chinese patterns of thinking and presuppositions.

    Specifically, well before the beginning of the Christian era, Chinese thinkers such as Lao-tzu and Chuang-tzurticulated a view of existence as

    .370

    ne of harmonious coexistence in interdependence of the many particulars which constitute the organic whole callxistence. In Chuang-tzu's writing, particularly in the section named, "Seeing Things as Equal," we find a classica

    Chinese enunciation of a vision of a world in which things are naturally what they are by virtue of a pervasive,

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    3/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    horoughgoing interdependence. As in Whitehead's system, such a world of particular events is not to be seen asnhering in or growing out of anything beyond itself, nor may we look beyond it for any causal agency. It is itself ustaining and self-creating, and this is achieved through the interaction of a conditioning nature of all its parts. Anxample of this view is clearly expressed in the Kuo-hsiang commentary on Chuang-tzu's writing:

    When a person is born, insignificant though he may be, he has all the requisites necessary for his life.However trivial his own life may be, he needs the whole universe as a condition for his existence. Nothing in the universe, nothing that exists, can cease for a moment without some effect on him. If one factoris lacking, he might not exist any longer. If one principle is violated, he might not live.[2]

    Other passages similar to this one might be quoted. Students of process thought can observe several major areasgreement between Taoist and process thought. One is the understanding that existence is process and change.

    Whitehead's "creative advance into novelty" is prefigured in the Taoist view of the natural world as constantransformation. Indeed, this vision of constant change and newness is probably the central feature of Taoist thoughtarting with the Book of Changes. Second, the world is organic in nature. Each individual exists and changes byppropriating its whole environment, with which it is intrinsically related. As Kuo-hsiang says, the individual needhe totality of existence as a condition for its being. Thus, the individual is an organism, and so then is the whole arger organism. Perhaps nothing in Chinese culture exhibits this view of things so clearly and concretely as itsandscape paintings. Third, Whitehead's dictum that we need not look beyond the actual entities for something moasic or fundamental is clearly reflected in the Taoist rejection of an underlying substance or mysterious external

    gency. Other areas of agreement might be discovered, but these three major ideas indicate an interesting similarityetween the two philosophies. Of equal interest is the fact that Mahayana Buddhism shares these same concepts ineaching of universal emptiness.

    The point I wish to make here is that the Chinese - mainly Taoist - view

    .371

    f existence had a transforming effect on the Indian Buddhist data. The Chinese reacted differently to thenderstanding that things are not embedded in any enduring substratum. The Taoist came to feel a deep respect anppreciation for the many transient things of the natural world inasmuch as each of them played an important role he nexus of interdependence. Once an individual was able to put aside the normal human penchant for arranging

    hings in a hierarchy of values - such penchant being a function of ego-gratification - he may be able to perceive art of the 'Great Barn' as having equal value, and a supreme value, for all things function identically as parts of th

    whole. Ordinary things are thus respected and prized, and the changing scene is one of charm and fascination. Indhe very transience and fragility of things adds a certain dimension to their beauty. Cessation of attachment to certarts of the whole, along with its corollary turmoil, was achieved by elevating all things to a rank of supreme goo

    when all things are good, there is no longer anything to pick and choose. The Indian Buddhists were able to achievhis same freedom from attachment only by concluding that since things are impermanent and lacking in any ultimubstantiality, there is nothing worthy of attachment. Indeed, there are no real things to become attached to or evenecome attached. The vision of universal emptiness was able to destroy attachment because it robbed the world of

    worth and charm; a world in which all things are equal in their emptiness is a world equal in its valuelessness.

    As I mentioned earlier, Fa-tsang seems to have accurately assessed the difference between Indian `suunyavaada he Hua-yen version when he spoke of the difference between negative and affirmative approaches. Another indichat this is the case may be observed in the interesting fact that in his writings Fa-tsang tends to substitute the Chin

    erm li with its ancient Taoist connotations, for the term k'ungwhich usually translated the Sanskrit `suunyaOther Chinese also frequently made the same substitution, and the reason seems to be that although they wished toaithfully with the concept of emptiness, they felt that k'ung (emptiness) carried with it negative connotations oravoring which li did not. Li, meaning something like 'pattern' or 'principle,' always had 'warm' connotations for th

    Chinese.[3] Thus, both k'ung and li were used to denote interdependence, change, and substancelessness, but theormer connoted voidness and valuelessness, while the latter connoted fullness and goodness. I do not consider thie a distortion of the emptiness doctrine itself, for it is primarily an esthetic

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    4/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    .372

    rientation towards the fact of interdependence which is the basis for the Indian doctrine itself. The affirmation ofnterdependent things is thus a different way of responding to interdependence and change.

    But now let us turn to the Hua-yen system itself. Fa-tsang's philosophy of interdependence and identity is formehree steps. First, he demonstrates the fundamental Mahayana teaching of the identity of form and emptiness asresented in the Praj~naapaaramitaa literature. The result of his discussion is the assertion of the identity of all thinr events by virtue of this common emptiness. Next, he shows that events are causally interdependent. This causal

    elationship is not, as in Whitehead's process thought, the asymmetrical one whereby the past is prehended in theresent. Hua-yen causality is completely multidirectional, moving from past to present, future to present, and, momportantly, existing among contemporaries. Finally, in an analogy of a building and a rafter, Fa-tsang shows theelationship of identity and interdependence existing between the part and the whole. The bulk of the remainder ofaper will be devoted to a description of these three phases.

    The initial phase in the development of the discussion of identity consists of a demonstration of the identity ofvents, which Fa-tsang calls "form" (an abbreviation. for 'phenomenal existence'). and the absolute or uncondition

    which goes by many names but is usually called "emptiness" or "principle." In classical Buddhist terminology, thio claim that sa^msaara and nirvaa.na, the natural world and the cosmic body of the Buddha, and so on, are identichis part of Fa-tsang's argument is not much more than a demonstration, probably for the sake of completeness. of

    ecurrent passage in the Praj~naapaaramitaa Suutra which says that form and emptiness are one and the same thinguupam `suunyataa `suunyataaiva ruupam. His method of showing this is interesting for many reasons to the stude

    Buddhist intellectual history, but I shall not discuss it here out of considerations of space. Fa-tsang did not invent toncept, which is fundamental to all of Mahayana Buddhism. Emptiness is not a more 'real' or spiritual entity lurk

    within illusory phenomena; the phenomena themselves, just as they are, are what is meant by emptiness.

    Such a doctrine is not a species of pantheism or panbuddhism, nor is it the reintroduction into Buddhism of the f substance. The equation of form and emptiness simply means that by emptiness is meant the how of things, andoints to a situation in which there are not any actual static forms to

    .373

    e found, but only a never-completed forming. It points to the fact that by 'existence' we mean something happeniwhich occurs on the basis of a mutual conditioning at all points of the continuum. Since emptiness points to the m

    f becoming of phenomena, it seems obvious that if there were no emptiness, there would be no form, and withoutorm, there would be no emptiness. Emptiness is thus exactly coincidental with the process of forming by mutualonditioning, it is not a separate order of being apart from phenomenal events, any more than the Whiteheadianreativity' is something apart from the passage of nature.

    I have greatly abbreviated the discussion of the identity of form and emptiness because it is a well-known conceMahayana Buddhism and because it serves only as a prelude to a doctrine which is not so well known but which isharacteristically Hua-yen. I mean the doctrine of the identity of phenomena, form, or events. The particulars whiconstitute existence are all obviously different in form and function. A louse and the emperor of China look differnd act differently; fire is hot and can cook food, while ice is cold and can chill the same food. And yet they aredentical. The differences are not annulled in Hua-yen thought, for the identity of things is an identity in differencendeed, the paradox is that they are identical just because they are different. The genius of Hua-yen is that theerception of universal emptiness does not in any way obliterate or devalue the vibrant, lovely world of things .

    The claim that things are identical is not as unlikely as it may seem. We all recognize identity in difference on onevel. We know that there is a common denominator that links all races, despite differences in color, hair, languagend so on. They are all identical on the basis of their humanity. Once we can accept the fact that all things are emp

    we can see that despite differences in form and function they are identical because they are all empty. Hua-yenbserves, even celebrates, the difference, but for purposes of emancipation and enlightenment, the identity of thingheir common emptiness is more significant than the fact that some things are long, some short, some red, some sqund so on.

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    5/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    But this kind of identity is a static identity based on a significant property possessed in common. These things,owever, are very real things which interact dynamically with each other, each thing having a dynamic relationshi

    with its whole environment. Ultimately, identity results from this dynamic interaction. Fa-tsang illustrates this withnalogy of ten coins (ten symbolizing totality in Hua-yen literature).

    .374

    Let us imagine the ten coins spread out in a row. They symbolize the totality of things existing in a togetherness

    hey are, in other words, contemporaries, and there is no question of temporal priority. Fa-tsang first selects the firoin in the row (an arbitrary choice) and asks what its relationship is to coin #2, coin #3, and so on throughout the

    whole row of coins. He says that the first coin is identical with the second coin, the third, and so on. Why is this?tarting with the Buddhist axiom that there are no self-existent entities, Fa-tsang says that coin #2 can not be coin ll by itself, but its 'coin twoness' is dependent on coin #1. This means that coin #2 is merely the conditioned resultoin #1. If this were not so, coin #2 would be coin #2 even in the absence of the first coin; i.e., it would inherentlyoin 2,' possessing that character independently of external circumstances. In other words, it would possess aubstance identifying it as 'coin 2'. But it does not. Thus, seen from the standpoint of the first coin, the second coinmpty. But the first coin is a real, concrete individual which bears causal power and exerts it on the second coin, ahis capacity it is said to exist. That is, 'existence' refers to the concreteness and conditioning power of the first coi

    while 'emptiness' refers to the conditioned nature of the second coin. It should be remarked here that in actuality thecond coin is conditioned simultaneously by all of the other nine coins, not just by the first one.

    But so far identity has not been established, and the reason is that in our analysis of the relationship of coin #1 the other nine coins, the first coin has always been seen as conditioning, while the other nine coins have been seenhe conditioned result. To stop at this point would be tantamount to asserting that there is one single origin of causower, but Hua-yen in fact recognizes no such causal center. The first coin, which seems to possess so much moreolidity and responsibility than the others is no less empty than those others. For 'coin #1' is itself not a self-existenoin #1' but receives its being from the conditioning power of coins 2,3,4, and so on. Now we may say that from ttandpoint of coin #2, coin #1 is empty as a conditioned result of the second coin, and this second coin is existent,eal object which exerts causal power. The same may also be said concerning the relationship of coin #3 to the firsoin. Finally, it needs to be noted that each of the ten coins is both the empty result of the conditioning power of thest of the totality individually and collectively, and is simultaneously a real, existent entity exerting causal power

    he whole. The identity of event

    .375

    with event derives from this situation: each event conditions and is conditioned; it is simultaneously empty andxistent.

    The above analogy has always seemed to me to be a little unconvincing, the reason being that we can imagine thoins being laid out in sequence, with a coin #1 having that character because it was placed on the table first. Howis only an analogy, and we must remember that the point to this is that contemporaries constituting a totality hav

    ertain kind of relationship. If we use the human body as an analogy, we would be noting that the cells of the bodydentical in this sense inasmuch as each cell is dependent on the rest of the cells and simultaneously is a condition he existence and change of all the others collectively and individually. The body is an organism precisely becausehis relationship between the part and the whole. Our task is to try to see that the 'Great Barn' which we call existens no less organic in this sense.

    Before going on to a discussion of causality per se, I would like to digress briefly and explain the curious Hua-ylaim that things are identical because they are different. To revert for a moment to the analogy of the human bodyay that my nose and liver are identical is not an attempt to nullify the obvious differences in shape, location, andunction of the two organs. In fact, if I insisted that my liver is only identical with my nose, and if I insisted that th

    were no differences at all, I would in effect be just one large nose. To put it another way, I could not be this body,ince my body is constituted of much more than a nose. In order for my body to be this body, I must have nose, li

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    6/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    yes, hands, brain, and so on, and when all parts are what they are, in the places where they are supposed to be,unctioning as they do, I am this body. This is just to say that when we speak of 'whole,' parts are implied, for thero whole apart from its constituents. When each part plays its own role, there is a whole, and the identity of discrearticulars results from the situation whereby each particular acts as a necessary condition for the whole identicall

    with all other particulars when it plays its own unique role. If all things are literally and exactly identical, there cane a whole. The Mahayana Buddhist life of respect and gratitude for all things finds its ideological support in thisnderstanding of identity. What can I legitimately despise or devalue if everything is a condition for my own life ahe life of all other things?

    The matter of causality per se has of necessity been discussed somewhat in the above analysis of identity, becaueality they can not be separated.

    .376

    he reason for this is that identity and interdependence are simply two different ways of looking at one situation. Wmay inspect the static nature of events and recognize their identity in sharing this nature, or we may choose to insphe dynamic interaction among these same events; but in both cases, we are merely recognizing the universal emptf things. Things are empty because they are interdependent, and in their interdependence they are identical.

    Each event or phenomenal object is a distinct individual with its own unique form and function, and as anndividual it has a relationship with its environment. How extensive this environment is may be a matter of debate

    Hua-yen Buddhists claim that the whole universe is the environment of any individual. It is a venerable position iBuddhism also that no one thing (Or dharma or event) can of itself alone be the cause of another thing, for amultiplicity of conditions is required in order that another event occurs. A single dharma-event does not possess al

    ualities required to bring about a certain result. For instance, if we take the example of a blade of wheat, it is obvhat more is required than just a seed, for the causal seed can not bring about the resultant blade of wheat. More isequired, such as soil, sunlight, water, the absence of crows, and many other conditions. The seed alone lacks theualities of support, warmth. moisture, and so on. As a matter of fact, Hua-yen would say that the whole universe unction as a condition for the blade of wheat. This does not have the obvious meaning that the seed needs the aidhese other conditions, but that in some sense these qualities of the other conditions are borrowed by, or, to use ona-tsang's terms, are usurped by, the wheat seed. What Fa-tsang wants to say is that these other conditions-qua-ecessary qualities are included within the seed. This is in fact what is meant by 'interpenetration' in the Hua-yen

    radition. It may be more helpful for the reader to imagine it as a situation in which things cooperate to bring abouesult, but it is said to be a matter of interpenetration because any single event, as a condition for the whole, is saidnclude within itself all these other conditions.

    The above analogy (and case) of the blade of wheat is not a perfect analogy because there the direction of causaower flows only in one direction; it is an obvious case of temporal causality. Causality in Hua-yen is not so restrlthough it includes this temporal causality, but rather is completely multidirectional. Thus, what is ordinarily seenhe cause is also seen simultaneously as the result of other conditions, including the event

    .377

    onventionally seen as the result. Event 'a' as cause of result 'b' is also the simultaneous result of 'b' (as well as manther conditions). What is more, the categories of 'cause,' 'result,' and 'aiding conditions' are completely fluid andnterchangeable, for the conditions which collaborate with a causal event to produce a result are themselves the ref the cause, because each event is seen as being the cause for the whole. These same helping conditions, which arlso the result of the cause, are at the same time (i.e., simultaneously) the cause of the one event being considered ause of the whole. Consequently, there is no one event which is only a cause, a result, or a helping condition; eaching is simultaneously all three. It is true that wheat grows from seeds. Yet, the seed is the cause only in relation toesultant sprout; if there is no result, it is not a cause, and so the cause is conditioned by the result. Moreover, the oonditions such as the rain, soil, and heat which aid the seed as supportive elements are at the same time the causehe seed and are caused by the seed.

    In the discussion of identity, the identity of one thing with all other things was asserted on the basis of the

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    7/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    ossession of each thing with the simultaneous natures of emptiness and existence. Intercausality, or interpenetratesults from the event's possessing the qualities of causal power and lack of causal power. To have causal power mhat by absorbing into itself the qualities of all other events, a certain event acts as a cause for the whole. This also

    means in turn that those other events not being considered the cause are conditioned, empty events. Conversely, laausal power means that this same event which was previously considered to be the cause from its own point of vis simultaneously the empty, conditioned results of a host of other events, seen from the standpoint of these others.

    The categories of causal power and lack of causal power would thus seem to function as a means of showing thany single event may be seen as both a concrete event serving as a necessary condition for the whole, and

    imultaneously as an empty, conditioned result of the causal whole. And to return briefly to the matter of identity, will be recalled, identity is claimed on the basis of this endowment by all things of the nature of being a condition

    eing conditioned. We all - men, rocks, weeds, tigers, saints, and stars - are alike in our essential emptiness, for wll conditions for each other.

    Fa-tsang concludes his "Treaties on the Five Doctrines" (the translation of a shorter title of the above-mentionedHua-yen i-ch'eng chiao i fen-ch'i chang) with a description of the relationship between a rafter and the whole bui

    .378

    f which it is a part. It is an analogy for any whole and its parts. By means of it, Fa-tsang shows the relationship odentity and interdependence (or interpenetration) discussed earlier. He analyzes this relationship by means of sixharacteristics which are possessed by each part of the whole. The six are totality, particularity, identity, differencentegration, and non-integration. In terms of the rafter, this means that the rafter is the totality, a particular, identic

    with all other parts and consequently with the whole, different in form and function, integrated into, and thus part he whole, and non-integrated in the sense that the rafter remains an observable, removable part with its own naturhe rafter is all six simultaneously.

    What do we mean first of all by 'totality'! Fa-tsang answers, "It is the building." But the building is just a numbeonditions, such as a rafter. What is the building itself? Again Fa-tsang replies, "The rafter is the building. The reas that this rafter itself completely creates the building. If you remove the rafter, there is no building. If you have aafter, you have a building." But how can a rafter all by itself wholly create the building if there are no roof tiles, nnd other things?

    It can not, says Fa-tsang, because if there are no roof tiles, nails, and the like, there is no such thing as arafter. A real rafter is only a rafter in the context of the whole building, and therefore, when it is a realrafter, it wholly creates the building. A non- rafter can not do this.[4]

    Several points should be noted in this slight paraphrase of the original. First, Fa-tsang clearly says that it is aarticular object - the rafter - which is the building. We might insist that the rafter is only part of the building, not uilding. but we would be missing the point. It is a particular, with a definite shape, location, and function, but if wemove each particular comprising the whole in order to find the real building, we will never find it. For it is just tarticulars in their conjunctive togetherness which we call 'building.' However, we must not overlook the other pahe relationship, which is that the rafter is only a rafter in the context of the building, and it is therefore itself the ref the causal building. In claiming that the rafter-part is the building whole, Fa-tsang is making the point that the tre completely interdependent, for there is no whole apart from parts and no part separate from the whole.

    Consequently, the parts which conjunctively make up the whole are not independently existing individuals at all; tre empty of independent being. The individual is simply a function of the whole environment and at the same timhe whole. We might note here that in

    .379

    hysics, the Mach principle portrays a very similar situation. Mach said that the inertial mass of any bundle of mas not an intrinsic property of the matter being analyzed, but rather is a function of all the rest of the matter in theniverse, such that if all matter were to vanish except for the one bundle of matter, the inertial mass of the latter wommediately be reduced to zero.[5] We are speaking, then, of a pervasive interconditionality or interdependence w

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    8/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    enies the autonomy of any particular.

    It is evident also from the above passage that the traditional linear, temporal causality has been partially rejectedthough not completely) for an alternative view in which the categories of cause and result are completelynterchangeable. This is, after all, what is meant by mutual conditionedness or inter-dependence. It is true in a sensnd probably in fact, that as the father of my son I am the cause and he is the result, but it is not less true that myatherhood is the result of the appearance in existence of a being I call 'son.'

    While the part is universalized by its integration into the whole, the part does not at all lose its particularity,

    niqueness, or special character, for a whole necessarily implies parts.

    All the various conditions such as the rafter are parts of a whole. If they were not parts, they could notmake a whole, because without parts, there is no whole. This means basically that the whole is intrinsicallycomposed of parts, so that you can not have a whole without parts. Also, the parts are parts because of thewhole.

    But if the part and the whole are identical, how can there be a whole?

    It is a whole precisely because it is identical with the part. Just as the rafter is the building and therefore isthe whole, so also because it is a rafter it is a particular. If the rafter is not the building, it is not a rafter; ifthe building is not the rafter, it is not a building. Whole and particular are identical.

    But if they are identical, how can you even speak of parts? Isn't the part obliterated in its identification with thewhole?

    I speak of parts because they are parts on the basis of their identification with the whole. If whole and partare not identical, the whole would exist without parts, but then how could you have a building withoutparts? The parts would also then exist outside the whole, but then they would not be parts.[6]

    hus, Fa-tsang recognizes the reality of the individual. It is no less real, no less significant than wholeness; indeedwo necessarily go together.

    Much is said of Eastern 'mysticism,' a highly unsatisfactory term which

    .380

    eems to cover much phenomena. Fa-tsang was not a mystic. If anything, he was a realist in the Chinese tradition ealism. He might in fact be called a radical realist, for his vision of process, change, and interdependence does nonally, as it does in Whitehead's system, have to include the consequent nature of God or some such supposition. ll Buddhists, he insisted on knowing what reality is, whatever it is, and when he glimpsed it,it was not with alarmpprehension but with something akin to joy. He found no need to reinvest his vision of incessant change and nov

    with some human value and meaning which would give him solace.

    Fa-tsang continues his discussion by showing how a thing is both identical with and different from other things

    ow all are united in a unity of integration and yet maintain their individualities (the categories just discussed in thbove paragraph), but they are essentially elaborations and variations of the discussion of whole and part, and I wot summarize these arguments. The discussion of the relationship of the many and the one is typical of the Hua-yttempt to draw out the implications of the central point of its system, which is that existence is an interdependentxistence only. The ethical. esthetic, and practical life of the Buddhist follows from this situation.

    In conclusion, I would like to draw some comparisons between the Hua-yen system and Whitehead's thought. Fseems clear that for both Whitehead and the Hua-yen thinkers, the universe is alive and dynamic through and

    hrough. Whitehead's statement that actualities act is reflected in the Hua-yen picture of a universe in which to eximeans necessarily to exert a conditioning influence on all things and to be conditioned by them in turn This is not rue of obviously living things but also of the not-so-obviously living ones such as earth, stone, water, and so on.

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    9/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    here is no discernible entity anywhere, in either system, which is static, for process and transformation are the vessence of existence. On the convention level (the level of samvriti-satya to use Buddhist terminology), we maybserve events about us which apparently possess enough permanence for us to deal with them practically, but in tparamartha-satya) everything is new from moment to moment. The change at any point of the unbroken totality iapid and continuous that Buddhism had to conclude, as did Whitehead centuries later, that permanent 'things' werbstraction from process, the results of a complicated mental act of synthesis. Buddhists, like Whitehead, recognizhe reality of a certain amount of continuity which made

    .381

    ractical day-to-day life possible, but the fact of constant change and newness held a potential for religious life thermanence or continuity did not.

    Second, it will have been observed from all the analogies used that the conditioning or causal power exerted by vent on another exists among contemporaries and between successive events. The Hua-yen doctrine of simultaneausality is somewhat similar to our own recently discovered understanding of ecological interdependence, althoughe Hua-yen version is a 'cosmic ecology,' to use a term I have used in a recent monograph on Hua-yen thought.

    While recognizing the reality and importance of temporal causality, the Chinese Buddhists were equally interestedmutual causality among contemporaries. There appears to have been a predisposition in pre-Buddhist China to seendividuals as deeply involved in each other, and it is interesting to think of the Hua-yen cosmology as anxtrapolation and more comprehensive version of the kind of relationship seen in the Chinese family, which wasonsidered a whole of dynamically interacting, mutually supporting parts. Harmony of parts is a desirable feature oth the family organism and the larger, cosmic family. The Chinese Buddhists included temporal, sequential caus

    within their more comprehensive view, of course, as they had to as Buddhists. The Buddhist doctrine of karma andebirth is basically a recognition of a situation in which an individual becomes what he has experienced from momo moment. The perfuming residue of karma is prehended by each of us and eventually is responsible for the qualiur lives. It is therefore basically a concept of sequential causation, for the present act serves as cause for a futureffect. Each of my 'lives' - what I am from moment to moment - is included in the next moment or life and is neveost. The cause will have a result. To this extent, Hua-yen agrees with Whitehead that causation is sequential. But

    Hua-yen goes beyond this to claim other forms, such as the important 'horizontal' causation. The Hua-yen thinkersepeat, were more interested in the question of the relationship between contemporaries, for this had importantmplications for ethics and practice.

    Third, the Hua-yen insistence that the world is a world of identity in differences seems to parallel Whitehead'soncept of a pluralistic universe which is nevertheless one continuum or field. It must be strongly emphasized that

    Hua-yen teaching of identity does not obliterate the world of distinct, different events, and hopefully some of thearlier discussion in this paper has made it clear how things are different yet the same. The delightful

    .382

    aradox of the Hua-yen teaching is that things are identical because they are different. Thus, things are identicalecause they are all identically conditions for the whole, and this Great Immensity, in all its throbbing vitality, colrama, and, yes, ultimate Goodness, could not be what it is if each thing were not what it is. In stressing the compldentity and equality of all things as necessary conditions for the whole, Chinese Buddhists were able to freehemselves from hatred, the greed born of attachment, pride, and delusion, and thus achieve the self-transcendences at the heart of Buddhism. In seeing that this equality and identity lay in the very difference of the ten thousandhings, the Chinese Buddhist could find a place in his heart for everything just as it is. His 'yes' of affirmation wasnconditional and unbounded. I find this a significant feature of Chinese Buddhism and a departure from the Indiiew of the natural world. This approach to the religious life is not only distinctly Chinese and different from thendian approach, but to make a flat value statement, I personally find it superior. Impermanence and change are noccasions for despair and horror, to be left behind for higher ethereal realms of freedom and joy. This world, with irth and death, joy and sorrow, angels and devils, butterflies and cobras, disease and health, is itself the very bodhe Buddha, the Pure Land; the absolute is nothing other than process itself.

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    10/11

    sation in the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    //ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-JOCP/jc26777.htm[11/2/2010 2:04:43 PM]

    There are various areas where Whitehead and Hua-yen do not seem to agree. There is no Buddhist equivalent ofWhiteheadian 'eternal objects,' nor do Buddhists feel any necessity for the categories of 'objective immortality' and

    onsequent nature of God.' to name just a few concepts. But the problem which needs the most clarification is thewhole matter of causality, which is central to both systems.

    Several questions may be asked. Is Whitehead's version of causality the only possible one? It may be said in rephat his idea of causality is in conformity with the facts of physics and the dictates of logic, but is the causality to bound in the world of atoms or molecules the only legitimate form of causality? Is the logic which is the pride of th

    Western world the only logic? Western thinkers have no logical equivalent of what D. T. Suzuki called the Buddh

    ogic of soku-hi ('x' is a 'non-x', therefore it is 'x') but it is a powerful and effective logic in Buddhism. Do we in faven know what causation is and is not? Is Hua-yen causation really causation at all? I have used the terms 'causeondition' throughout this paper, and they are literal translations of Chinese terms, but the question may remain as

    .383

    whether we should use the words 'cause' and 'condition' when speaking of the kinds of relationship discussed in thaper. Yet, the Chinese texts certainly speak of cause and conditions. The relationship of one event with another in

    Hua-yen philosophy is similar to the relationship between a yucca tree and a yucca moth; without the moth, no trend without the tree, no moth. May we legitimately speak of each as being a necessary condition for the other? Ma

    we legitimately say that the moth is a cause for the tree and vice-versa? Does causation have anything to do withnterdependence? We might multiply the questions, but these indicate some areas that need to be clarified.

    The Hua-yen causation works in all directions, from past to present, present to future, future to present, future tast, and mutually among contemporaries. There seems to be a strong reluctance on the part of process thinkers todmit, for instance, that the future has a causal effect on the present, an idea which has tremendous implications foractice for the Buddhist. There seems to be some feeling on the part of Professor Hartshorne and others that suchorm of causation would result in the lack of freedom of choice or self-determination by the individual, though it ilear to me that this is necessarily so. Buddhism is able to maintain both positions in equilibrium; the future influehe present, but the individual is free from moment to moment to choose what he will become, and Buddhist literaonstantly exhorts the individual to choose enlightenment and freedom from the cycle of birth and death. Yet, thisecision is made by an individual who is conditioned by time, place, heredity, economics, weather, food supply,arental training, and, of course, the millions of volitional acts performed by himself and all other living beings in

    lanet's past.

    I believe that part of the problem is that scholars such as Charles Hartshorne read too much determinism into theBuddhist view of causation or conditioning. There certainly is some determination, as most would agree, but beingonditioned and being determined are two different things. Is it not possible, for instance, that out of the countlessonditions which make us what we are, one condition or even several conditions are such as to allow for freedom hoice and some degree of self-determination? Free will and determinism are hoary problems in western intellectuircles, but they have never been among Buddhists. The Buddhist would ask the process philosopher, 'Just who or s it that is determined or has free will?' This may be the crux of the whole problem.

    .384

    The value of the Buddhist understanding of reality is well known; it was never meant to be philosophy for its owake but was meant to be a lure to decision and action and a corrective to egocentric and homocentric pride. Underool, objective scrutiny of the meditator, the world of selves encased within their own skins, autonomous andndependent, evaporated into a complex web of interdependence, in which events found their being and meaning a

    mere functions of the totality. The belief in a self or substance became philosophically untenable, and the belief inman's supreme importance was dissolved by a vision which allowed of no hierarchies in nature. But the Hua-yen

    hilosophy was never meant to demean or nullify. For in the growing understanding of the way in which things exn interdependence, the Buddhist was led to a broadening of concern, a concern which encompassed more and mohe whole of existence, extending to other animal forms, the vegetable world, the 'inanimate' world, and finally touman artifacts. To understand the world as essentially interdependent is to understand how things need each othe

  • 7/28/2019 Causation According to the Chinese Hua-Yen Tradition

    11/11