capital punishment: race, poverty & disadvantage · 1965 exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10...

40
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE Yale University Professor Stephen B. Bright Class Two - Part One: McGautha - Furman Decline in the Use of the Death Penalty in the 1940s, 50s and 60s U.S. executions reached their peak in 1935, when 199 people were put to death. After that, the number dropped off steeply. 1947 was the last year with more than 150 executions, 1951 the last year with more than 100. There were only 42 executions in 1961 and only 21 in 1963. The southern states executed 105 people in 1947, 48 in 1957, and 13 in 1963. 1968 was the first year in U.S. history during which not a single person was executed. Per capita, the execution rate had been dropping steadily since the 1880s. From Stuart Banner, THE DEATH PENALTY: AN AMERICAN HISTORY: The territories of Alaska and Hawaii abolished the death penalty in 1957. Delaware abolished it in 1958, only to bring it back in 1961. Oregon conducted a referendum in 1964 in which more than 60 percent of the electorate voted for abolition. New York, Iowa, Vermont, and West Virginia abolished it in 1965. When New Mexico abolished the death penalty in 1969, it became the fourteenth state to do so. There had never been so many. Executions in the United States by year and average for five-year intervals, 1935-69 ====================================== Number of Five year Year Executions Average ====================================== 1935 199 1936 195 1937 147 1938 190 1939 160 178 1940 124 1941 123 1942 147 1943 131 1944 120 129 1945 117 1946 131 1947 153 1948 119 1949 119 138 1950 82 1951 105 1952 83 1953 62 1954 71 83 1955 76 1956 65 1957 65 1958 49 1959 49 61 1960 56 1961 42 1962 46 1963 21 1964 15 36 Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 1 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Upload: others

Post on 30-Sep-2020

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

CAPITAL PUNISHMENT:RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE

Yale UniversityProfessor Stephen B. Bright

Class Two - Part One: McGautha - Furman

Decline in the Use of the DeathPenalty in the 1940s, 50s and 60s

U.S. executions reached their peak in 1935,when 199 people were put to death. After that, thenumber dropped off steeply. 1947 was the lastyear with more than 150 executions, 1951 the lastyear with more than 100. There were only 42executions in 1961 and only 21 in 1963. Thesouthern states executed 105 people in 1947, 48 in1957, and 13 in 1963. 1968 was the first year inU.S. history during which not a single person wasexecuted. Per capita, the execution rate had beendropping steadily since the 1880s.

From Stuart Banner, THE DEATH PENALTY: AN

AMERICAN HISTORY:

The territories of Alaska and Hawaii abolishedthe death penalty in 1957. Delaware abolished itin 1958, only to bring it back in 1961. Oregonconducted a referendum in 1964 in which morethan 60 percent of the electorate voted forabolition. New York, Iowa, Vermont, and WestVirginia abolished it in 1965. When New Mexicoabolished the death penalty in 1969, it became thefourteenth state to do so. There had never been somany.

Executions in the United States by year andaverage for five-year intervals, 1935-69

======================================

Number of Five year

Year Executions Average

======================================

1935 199

1936 195

1937 147

1938 190

1939 160 178

1940 124

1941 123

1942 147

1943 131

1944 120 129

1945 117

1946 131

1947 153

1948 119

1949 119 138

1950 82

1951 105

1952 83

1953 62

1954 71 83

1955 76

1956 65

1957 65

1958 49

1959 49 61

1960 56

1961 42

1962 46

1963 21

1964 15 36

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 1 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 2: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

1965 7

1966 1

1967 2

1968 0

1969 0 10

[There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.]

Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics, U.S. Department ofJustice, Capital Punishment 1978, at 16, Table 1 (1979).

Executions in five-year intervals for four regions of the United States, 1935-69====================================

Five-year Northintervals Northeast Central West South

1935-39 145 113 100 524

1940-44 110 42 73 413

1945-49 74 64 76 419

1950-54 56 42 65 244

1955-59 51 16 51 181

1960-64 17 16 45 102

1965-69 0 5 3 2

Totals 453 298 413 1,887

====================================Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics, U.S. Department of Justice, Capital Punishment 1981, at 15, Table 2 (1982).

Executions by regions, 1977 through 2012====================================

Northeast Midwest West South

4 155 82 1,079

Source: Death Penalty Information Center, Facts About theDeath Penalty at 3 (Jan. 14, 2013) (available atwww.deathpenaltyinfo.org/documents/FactSheet.pdf).

Executions in five-year intervals for Southern states performing over 100 executions from 1930 to 1969, and total executions by those states from 1977 to 2011============================================================================

5-yr intervals GA TX NC FL SC MS AL LA AR KY_____________________________________________________________________________________

1930-34 64 48 51 15 37 26 19 39 20 18

1935-39 73 72 80 29 30 22 41 19 33 34

1940-44 58 38 50 38 32 34 29 24 20 19

1945-49 72 36 62 27 29 26 21 23 18 15

1950-54 51 49 14 22 16 15 14 14 11 8

1955-59 34 25 5 27 10 21 6 13 7 8

1960-64 14 29 1 12 8 10 4 1 9 1

1965-69 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0

Totals

1930-69 366 297 263 170 162 154 135 133 118 103 39 years

Executions

1977-2012 52 492 43 74 43 21 55 28 27 3 34 years

============================================================================Sources: Bureau of Justice Statistics, U.S. Department of Justice, Capital Punishment 1981, at 15, Table 2 (1982); Death Penalty Information Center, Facts About the Death Penalty at 3 (Jan. 14, 2013) (available at www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/documents/FactSheet.pdf).

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 2 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 3: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

Capital Punishment in the Rest ofthe World

By the 1960s, capital punishment has beenabolished or abandoned in much of the world.Mexico abolished capital punishment for politicalcrimes in 1857, and the federal government andthe Mexican states abolished it for all crimes in1929. Portugal was the first Western Europeancountry to abolish capital punishment, doing so in1867; it then reinstated the penalty for treason, butpermanently abolishing it in 1976. Germany,Austria, and Italy stopped executions after theSecond World War although they did not formallyabolish capital punishment until later.

Great Britain abolished the death penalty formurder in 1969. The last execution, by hanging,took place in 1964. Statues providing for the deathpenalty for treason and piracy with violence werenot repealed until 1998.

Canada removed capital punishment from thecriminal code in 1976, while retaining it the for anumber of military offenses, including treason andmutiny. However, it was not applied for thosecrimes and in 1998 it was abolished entirely withlegislation removing all references to it from theNational Defence Act.

Denmark abolished the death penalty in 1978.France abolished it in 1981. The effort in Francewas led by Robert Badinter, the minister of justice,who had defended some of the last men executedand was a long time opponent of capitalpunishment. See Robert Badinter, ABOLITION: ONE

MAN’S BATTLE AGAINST THE DEATH PENALTY

(2008). France amended its Constitution to ban thedeath penalty in 2007. The last execution inFrance, by guillotine, took place in 1977. It wasthe last execution in the Western Europeancountries of Belgium, France, Germany, Italy,Luxembourg and the Netherlands. See AndrewHammel, ENDING THE DEATH PENALTY: THE

EUROPEAN EXPERIENCE IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE.(2010).

The Council of Europe, made up of 47 memberstates, has made abolition of the death penalty aprerequisite for membership.

The Constitutional Court of South Africadeclared the death penalty unconstitutional in oneof its first decisions after the end of apartheid. State v. Makwanyane, Constl. Ct. of South Africa,June 6, 1995, 16 HUMAN RTS. L. J. 154 (1995).

At least 23 countries carried out executions in2010, and 67 imposed death sentences. China isbelieved to have carried out thousands, but it doesnot release statistics on the number executed.Other countries which carried out a significantnumber of executions were Iran (252+), NorthKorea (60+), Yemen (53+) and the United States(46).1

Maxwell v. Bishop

A statistical argument that Arkansasdiscriminated against African Americans in theapplication of the death penalty for rape waspresented to the United States Court of Appealsfor the Eighth Circuit in the case of William L.Maxwell, a black man who had been sentenced todeath in 1962 upon conviction of rape of a whitewoman in Garland County, Arkansas. Maxwell v.Bishop, 398 F.2d 138 (8th Cir. 1968).

Maxwell, represented by Anthony Amsterdamand the NAACP Legal Defense and EducationalFund, presented the results of a survey conductedin the summer of 1965 of 55 rape convictionsduring the period 1945-1965 in 19 counties thatmade up more than 47% of the population ofArkansas. It was part of a larger study of suchsentencing in 12 southern states.

The survey included a number of variables suchas the defendant’s race, age, occupation, and priorcriminal record; the victim’s race, age, occupation;aspects of the prior relationship, if any, betweenthe defendant and the victim; and certaincircumstances of the offense such as the degree ofthreat or violence, and the injury inflicted; and theinvolvement of alcohol or drugs. However, thestudy did not include Garland County, whereMaxwell was convicted and sentenced, becausethe black population of the county was less than

1. See Amnesty International, Death Sentences and

Executions 2010 (2011).

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 3 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 4: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

19,000.

Dr. Marvin Wolfgang, a criminologist-statistician from the University of Pennsylvania,testified that the most critical variables with regardto sentence were the race of the offender and therace of the victim. An African American manconvicted of raping a white woman had about a 50percent chance of receiving a death sentence,regardless of the facts and circumstancessurrounding the crime, while a man convicted ofraping a woman of his own race had about only a14 percent chance of receiving the death sentence.Dr. Wolfgang testified that the difference couldnot be attributed to chance.

Maxwell also presented an exhibit prepared bythe United States Bureau of Prisons that showedthat, for the years 1930 to 1962, 446 persons wereexecuted in the United States for rape and that, ofthese, only 45 were white but 399 were black andtwo were of other races, and that, for the sameperiod, 3,298 were executed for murder and, ofthese, 1,640 were white, 1,619 were black, and 39were of other races.

The Legal Defense Fund argued that inferencescould be drawn from the its evidence that appliedto the entire state and to Maxwell’s case.Therefore, it argued, Maxwell had made a primafacie case of racial discrimination and was entitledto relief because the State presented no evidence toovercome it. It also noted that on three previousoccasions it had presented evidence ofdiscrimination and been rejected each time“notwithstanding that on each successive occasionthe evidence tended in the direction of more depthand completeness.” This demonstrates, it was said,“how difficult it is for Negro litigants generallyand those without means particularly, to makecourts see ‘the reality of the world, indeed * * *the segregated world’ * * * in which they live[.] ** * [T]he law [needs to] ‘see what all others see.’”

Harry Blackmun, then a judge on the EighthCircuit, wrote the opinion rejecting Maxwell’sclaims. He noted that Maxwell’s evidence did notrelate specifically to Garland County where he wasconvicted and sentenced to death; it did not takeevery variable into account; and it did not showthat race was the reason that the jury sentenced

Maxwell to death.

The Court noted that with regard to GarlandCounty, for the decade beginning January 1, 1954,Maxwell’s evidence was that seven whites werecharged with rape with four not prosecuted andthree sentenced on reduced charges; that threeblacks were charged with rape, with one of a blackwoman not prosecuted and another of a blackreceiving a reduced sentence, and the third,Maxwell, receiving the death penalty. It alsoobserved that in the last fourteen years the menexecuted for rape in Arkansas had been two whitesand two blacks.

Emphasizing that it was “concerned with * * *Maxwell’s case and only Maxwell’s case,” futureJustice Blackmun wrote for the Court of Appeals:

We are not ready to condemn and upset theresult reached in every case of a Negro rapedefendant in the State of Arkansas on the basisof broad theories of social and statisticalinjustice. This is particularly so on a record sospecific as this one. And we are not yet readyto nullify this petitioner’s Garland County trialon the basis of results generally, but elsewhere,throughout the South.

We therefore reject the statistical argumentin its attempted application to Maxwell’s case.Whatever value that argument may have as aninstrument of social concern, whateversuspicion it may arouse with respect tosouthern interracial rape trials as a group overa long period of time, and whatever it maydisclose with respect to other localities, we feelthat the statistical argument does nothing todestroy the integrity of Maxwell’s trial.

The Court acknowledged:

We do not say that there is no ground forsuspicion that the death penalty for rape mayhave been discriminatorily applied over thedecades in that large area of states whosestatutes provide for it. There are recognizableindicators of this. But, as we have notedbefore, with respect to the issue of juryselection, improper state practice of the past

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 4 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 5: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

does not automatically invalidate a procedureof the present.

Finally, Judge Blackmun stated with regard toMaxwell’s case, which was before the Court for asecond time:

[T]he efforts on behalf of Maxwell would notthus be continuing * * * were it not for the factthat it is the death penalty, rather than lifeimprisonment, which he received on his rapeconviction. This fact makes the decisionalprocess in a case of this kind particularlyexcruciating for the author of this opinion whois not personally convinced of the rightness ofcapital punishment and who questions it as aneffective deterrent. But the advisability ofcapital punishment is a policy matter ordinarilyto be resolved by the legislature or throughexecutive clemency and not by the judiciary.

The Supreme Court granted certiorari and twiceheard oral argument in Maxwell’s case. However,the Court resolved the case in a brief per curiamopinion in which it set aside Maxwell’s sentencebased on a recent juror qualification decision,Witherspoon v. Illinois, 391 U.S. 510 (1968).Maxwell v. Bishop, 398 U.S. 262 (1970). The juryqualification issue had not been raised by Maxwellin either the state or federal courts.

For consideration and discussion

Maxwell argued that “the law needs to see whatall others see” with regard to racial discriminationin the infliction of the death penalty upon AfricanAmericans convicted of rape.

How would that be done is his case or any case?

What are the primary obstacles that make itdifficult?

Is it ever possible?

Dennis Councle McGAUTHA, Petitioner,v.

State of CALIFORNIA.

James Edward CRAMPTON, Petitioner,v.

State of OHIO.

United States Supreme Court402 U.S. 183, 91 S.Ct. 1454 (1971)

Mr. Justice HARLAN delivered the opinionof the Court.

Petitioners McGautha and Crampton wereconvicted of murder in the first degree in thecourts of California and Ohio respectively andsentenced to death pursuant to the statutes of thoseStates. In each case the decision whether thedefendant should live or die was left to theabsolute discretion of the jury. In McGautha’s casethe jury, in accordance with California law,determined punishment in a separate proceedingfollowing the trial on the issue of guilt. InCrampton’s case, in accordance with Ohio law, thejury determined guilt and punishment after a singletrial and in a single verdict. We granted certiorariin the McGautha case limited to the questionwhether petitioner’s constitutional rights wereinfringed by permitting the jury to impose thedeath penalty without any governing standards.We granted certiorari in the Crampton case limitedto that same question and to the further questionwhether the jury’s imposition of the death sentencein the same proceeding and verdict as determinedthe issue of guilt was constitutionally permissible.For the reasons that follow, we find noconstitutional infirmity in the conviction of eitherpetitioner, and we affirm in both cases.

IIt will put the constitutional issues in clearer

focus to begin by setting out the course whicheach trial took.

A. McGautha’s Guilt TrialMcGautha and his codefendant Wilkinson were

charged with committing two armed robberies anda murder on February 14, 1967. In accordance withCalifornia procedure in capital cases, the trial wasin two stages, a guilt stage and a punishment stage.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 5 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 6: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

At the guilt trial, * * * [t]he jury found bothdefendants guilty of two counts of armed robberyand one count of first-degree murder as charged.

B. McGautha’s Penalty TrialAt the penalty trial, which took place on the

following day but before the same jury, the Statewaived its opening, presented evidence ofMcGautha’s prior felony convictions andsentences, and then rested. Wilkinson testified inhis own behalf, relating his unhappy childhood inMississippi as the son of a white father and aNegro mother, his honorable discharge from theArmy on the score of his low intelligence, hisregular attendance at church, and his good recordfor holding jobs and supporting his mother andsiblings up to the time he was shot in the back inan unprovoked assault by a street gang. Thereafter,he testified, he had difficulty obtaining or holdingemployment. About a year later he fell in withMcGautha and his companions, and when theyfound themselves short of funds, one of the groupsuggested that they “knock over somebody.” Thiswas the first time, Wilkinson said, that he had everhad any thoughts of committing a robbery. Headmitted participating in the two robberies but saidhe had not known that the stores were to be heldup until McGautha drew his gun. He testified thatit had been McGautha who struck Mrs. Smetanaand shot Mr. Smetana.

Wilkinson called several witnesses in his behalf.An undercover narcotics agent testified that he hadseen the murder weapon in McGautha’s possessionand had seen McGautha demonstrating his quickdraw. A minister with whom Wilkinson hadboarded testified to Wilkinson’s church attendanceand good reputation. He also stated that beforetrial Wilkinson had expressed his horror at whathad happened and requested the minister’s prayerson his behalf. A former fellow employee testifiedthat Wilkinson had a good reputation and washonest and peaceable.

McGautha also testified in his own behalf at thepenalty hearing. He admitted that the murderweapon was his, but testified that he andWilkinson had traded guns, and that it wasWilkinson who had * * * killed [the victim].McGautha testified that he came from a brokenhome and that he had been wounded during World

War II. He related his employment record, medicalcondition, and remorse. * * *

The jury was instructed in the followinglanguage:

in this part of the trial the law does not forbidyou from being influenced by pity for thedefendants and you may be governed by meresentiment and sympathy for the defendants inarriving at a proper penalty in this case;however, the law does forbid you from beinggoverned by mere conjecture, prejudice, publicopinion or public feeling.

* * *

You may also consider all of the evidence of thecircumstances surrounding the crime, of eachdefendant’s background and history, and of thefacts in aggravation or mitigation of the penaltywhich have been received here in court.However, it is not essential to your decision thatyou find mitigating circumstances on the onehand or evidence in aggravation of the offenseon the other hand.

* * * Notwithstanding facts, if any, proved inmitigation or aggravation, in determining whichpunishment shall be inflicted, you are entirelyfree to act according to your own judgment,conscience, and absolute discretion. * * * Now,beyond prescribing the two alternative penalties,the law itself provides no standard for theguidance of the jury in the selection of thepenalty, but, rather, commits the whole matter ofdetermining which of the two penalties shall befixed to the judgment, conscience, and absolutediscretion of the jury. In the determination ofthat matter, if the jury does agree, it must beunanimous as to which of the two penalties isimposed.

Deliberations began in the early afternoon ofAugust 24, 1967. * * * Late in the afternoon ofAugust 25 the jury returned verdicts fixingWilkinson’s punishment at life imprisonment andMcGautha’s punishment at death.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 6 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 7: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

C. Crampton’s Trial.Petitioner Crampton was indicted for the murder

of his wife, Wilma Jean, purposely and withpremeditated malice. He pleaded not guilty and notguilty by reason of insanity. In accordance with theOhio practice which he challenges, his guilt andpunishment were determined in a single unitaryproceeding.

* * * [Two months after leaving the state mentalhospital, where he was undergoing observationand treatment for alcoholism and drug addiction,Crampton shot his wife. He had previouslythreatened her and she had urged him to return tothe hospital and requested police protection.]

* * *

The defense called Crampton’s mother as awitness. She testified about Crampton’sbackground, including a serious concussionreceived at age nine, his good grades in junior highschool, his stepfather’s jealously of him, hisleaving home at age 14 to live with variousrelatives, his enlistment in the Navy at age 17, hismarriage to a girl named Sandra, the birth of a son,a divorce, then a remarriage to Sandra and anotherdivorce shortly after, and finally his marriage toWilma [the victim]. Mrs. Crampton also testifiedto Crampton’s drug addiction, to his brushes withthe law as a youth and as an adult, and to hisundesirable discharge from the Navy.

Crampton’s attorney also introduced intoevidence a series of hospital reports whichcontained further information on Crampton’sbackground, including his criminal record, whichwas substantial, his court-martial conviction andundesirable discharge from the Navy, and theabsence of any significant employment record.They also contained his claim that the shootingwas accidental[.] * * * All the reports concludedthat Crampton was sane in both the legal and themedical senses. He was diagnosed as having asociopathic personality disorder, along withalcohol and drug addiction. Crampton himself didnot testify.

The jury was instructed that:

If you find the defendant guilty of murder in thefirst degree, the punishment is death, unless yourecommend mercy, in which event thepunishment is imprisonment in the penitentiaryduring life.

The jury was given no other instructionsspecifically addressed to the decision whether torecommend mercy, but was told in connection withits verdict generally:

You must not be influenced by anyconsideration of sympathy or prejudice. It isyour duty to carefully weigh the evidence, todecide all disputed questions of fact, to apply theinstructions of the court to your findings and torender your verdict accordingly. * * * Considerall the evidence and make your finding withintelligence and impartiality, and without bias,sympathy, or prejudice, so that the State of Ohioand the defendant will feel that their case wasfairly and impartially tried.

The jury deliberated for over four hours andreturned a verdict of guilty, with norecommendation for mercy. [The death sentencewas imposed about two weeks later.]

* * *

II* * * Our function is not to impose on the States,

ex cathedra, what might seem to us a better systemfor dealing with capital cases. Rather, it is todecide whether the Federal Constitution proscribesthe present procedures of these two States in suchcases. In assessing the validity of the conclusionsreached in this opinion, that basic factor should bekept constantly in mind.

III* * * [P]etitioners contend that to leave the jury

completely at large to impose or withhold thedeath penalty as it see fit is fundamentally lawlessand therefore violates the basic command of theFourteenth Amendment that no State shall deprivea person of his life without due process of law. ** *

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 7 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 8: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

AIn order to see petitioners’ claim in perspective,

it is useful to call to mind the salient features ofthe history of capital punishment for homicidesunder the common law in England, and subsequentstatutory developments in this country. Thishistory reveals continual efforts, uniformlyunsuccessful, to identify before the fact thosehomicides for which the slayer should die. * * *

* * *

* * * [I]n this country, * * * there was rebellionagainst the common-law rule imposing amandatory death sentence on all convictedmurderers. Thus, in 1794, Pennsylvania attemptedto reduce the rigors of the law by abolishingcapital punishment except for “murder of the firstdegree,” defined to include all “willful, deliberateand premediated” killings, for which the deathpenalty remained mandatory. * * *

This new legislative criterion for isolatingcrimes appropriately punishable by death soonproved * * * unsuccessful * * *. The result wascharacterized in this way by Chief Judge Cardozo:

What we have is merely a privilege offered tothe jury to find the lesser degree when thesuddenness of the intent, the vehemence of thepassion, seems to call irresistibly for the exerciseof mercy.

At the same time, jurors on occasion took thelaw into their own hands in cases which were“willful, deliberate, and premeditated” in any viewof that phrase, but which nevertheless were clearlyinappropriate for the death penalty. In such casesthey simply refused to convict of the capitaloffense.

In order to meet the problem of jurynullification, legislatures did not try, as before, torefine further the definition of capital homicides.Instead they adopted the method of forthrightlygranting juries the discretion which they had beenexercising in fact. Tennessee was the first State togive juries sentencing discretion in capital cases,but other States followed suit, as did the FederalGovernment in 1897. Shortly thereafter, inWinston v. United States, 172 U.S. 303 (1899), this

Court dealt with the federal statute for the firsttime. The Court reversed a murder conviction inwhich the trial judge instructed the jury that itshould not return a recommendation of mercyunless it found the existence of mitigatingcircumstances. The Court found this instruction tointerfere with the scheme of the Act to commit thewhole question of capital punishment “to thejudgment and the consciences of the jury.”

* * *

BPetitioners * * * assert[] the death penalty is

imposed on far fewer than half the defendantsfound guilty of capital crimes. The state andfederal legislatures which provide for jurydiscretion in capital sentencing have, it is said,implicitly determined that some – indeed, thegreater portion – of those guilty of capital crimesshould be permitted to live. But having made thatdetermination, petitioners argue, they have stoppedshort – the legislatures have not only failed toprovide a rational basis for distinguishing the onegroup from the other, but they have failed even tosuggest any basis at all. * * * [P]etitioners contendthe mechanism is constitutionally intolerable as ameans of selecting the extraordinary cases callingfor the death penalty, which is its present-dayfunction.

* * * Those who have come to grips with thehard task of actually attempting to draft means ofchanneling capital sentencing discretion haveconfirmed the lesson taught by the historyrecounted above. To identify before the fact thosecharacteristics of criminal homicides and theirperpetrators which call for the death penalty, andto express these characteristics in language whichcan be fairly understood and applied by thesentencing authority, appear to be tasks which arebeyond present human ability.

* * *

In light of history, experience, and the presentlimitations of human knowledge, we find it quiteimpossible to say that committing to theuntrammeled discretion of the jury the power topronounce life or death in capital cases isoffensive to anything in the Constitution. The

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 8 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 9: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

States are entitled to assume that jurors confrontedwith the truly awesome responsibility of decreeingdeath for a fellow human will act with due regardfor the consequences of their decision and willconsider a variety of factors, many of which willhave been suggested by the evidence or by thearguments of defense counsel. For a court toattempt to catalog the appropriate factors in thiselusive area could inhibit rather than expand thescope of consideration, for no list of circumstanceswould ever be really complete. * * *

IV* * *

ACrampton’s argument for bifurcation runs as

follows. [H]e enjoyed a constitutional right not tobe compelled to be a witness against himself. Yetunder the Ohio single-trial procedure, he couldremain silent on the issue of guilt only at the costof surrendering any chance to plead his case on theissue of punishment. He contends that under theDue Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment,he had a right to be heard on the issue ofpunishment and a right not to have his sentencefixed without the benefit of all the relevantevidence. Therefore, he argues, the Ohioprocedure * * * creates an intolerable tensionbetween constitutional rights. Since this tensioncan be largely avoided by a bifurcated trial,petitioner contends that there is no legitimate stateinterest in putting him to the election, and that thesingle verdict trial should be held invalid in capitalcases.

* * *

The criminal process, like the rest of the legalsystem, is replete with situations requiring “themaking of difficult judgments” as to which courseto follow. Although a defendant may have a right,even of constitutional dimensions, to followwhichever course he chooses, the Constitutiondoes not by that token always forbid requiring himto choose. * * *

B* * * We see nothing in the history, policies, or

precedents relating to the privilege [against

compelled self-incrimination] which requires suchmeans to be available.

* * *

C* * * Petitioner’s contention therefore comes

down to the fact that the Ohio single-verdict trialmay deter the defendant from bringing to thejury’s attention evidence peculiarly within his ownknowledge, and it may mean that the death verdictwill be returned by a jury which never heard thesound of his voice. * * * Assuming that in thiscase there was relevant information solely withinpetitioner’s knowledge, we do not think theConstitution forbids a requirement that suchevidence be available to the jury on all issues towhich it is relevant or not at all. * * *

V* * * It may well be * * * that bifurcated trials

and criteria for jury sentencing discretion aresuperior means of dealing with capital cases if thedeath penalty is to be retained at all. But theFederal Constitution, which marks the limits of ourauthority in these cases, does not guarantee trialprocedures that are the best of all worlds[.] * * *The Constitution requires no more than that trialsbe fairly conducted and that guaranteed rights ofdefendants be scrupulously respected. * * *

* * *

Separate opinion of Mr. Justice BLACK.

I concur in the Court’s judgments and insubstantially all of its opinion. However, in myview, this Court’s task is not to determine whetherthe petitioners’ trials were “fairly conducted.” TheConstitution grants this Court no power to reverseconvictions because of our personal beliefs thatstate criminal procedures are “unfair,” “arbitrary,”“capricious,” “unreasonable,” or “shocking to ourconscience.” Our responsibility is rather todetermine whether petitioners have been deniedrights expressly or impliedly guaranteed by theFederal Constitution as written. * * * The EighthAmendment forbids “cruel and unusualpunishments.” In my view, these words cannot beread to outlaw capital punishment because thatpenalty was in common use and authorized by law

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 9 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 10: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

here and in the countries from which our ancestorscame at the time the Amendment was adopted. * ** Although some people have urged that this Courtshould amend the Constitution by interpretation tokeep it abreast of modern ideas, I have neverbelieved that lifetime judges in our system haveany such legislative power.

Mr. Justice DOUGLAS, with whom Mr.Justice BRENNAN and Mr. Justice MARSHALLconcur, dissenting.

In my view the unitary trial which Ohio providesin first-degree murder cases does not satisfy therequirements of procedural Due Process under theFourteenth Amendment.

* * *

The truth is * * * that the wooden position of theCourt, reflected in today’s decision, cannot bereconciled with the evolving gloss of civilizedstandards which this Court, long before the time ofthose who now sit here, has been reading into theprotective procedural due process safeguards ofthe Bill of Rights. * * *

The Court has history on its side – but historyalone. * * *

* * *

Who today would say it was not “cruel andunusual punishment” within the meaning of theEighth Amendment to impose the death sentenceon a man who stole a loaf of bread, or in modernparlance, a sheet of food stamps? Who todaywould say that trial by battle satisfies therequirements of procedural due process?

* * * It is a mystery how in this day and age aunitary trial that requires an accused to give up oneconstitutional guarantee to save anotherconstitutional guarantee can be brought within therubric of procedural due process. * * *

* * *.

Mr. Justice BRENNAN, with whom Mr.Justice DOUGLAS and Mr. JusticeMARSHALL join, dissenting. * * *

* * *

* * * Unlike the Court, I do not believe that thelegislatures of the 50 States are so devoid ofwisdom and the power of rational thought that theyare unable to face the problem of capitalpunishment directly, and to determine forthemselves the criteria under which convictedcapital felons should be chosen to live or die. * ** Finally, even if I shared the Court’s view that therule of law and the power of the States to kill arein irreconcilable conflict, I would have nohesitation in concluding that the rule of law mustprevail.

* * * [I]f state power is to be exerted, thesechoices must be made by a responsible organ ofstate government. * * * If there is no effectivesupervision of this process to insure consistency ofdecision, it can amount to nothing more thangovernment by whim. But ours has been “termeda government of laws, and not of men.” Marburyv. Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 163, 2 L.Ed. 60 (1803).Government by whim is the very antithesis of dueprocess.

It is not a mere historical accident that “[t]hehistory of liberty has largely been the history ofobservance of procedural safeguards.” McNabb v.United States, 318 U.S. 332, 347 (1943)(Frankfurter, J.). * * * Such procedures may takea variety of forms. The decisionmaker may beprovided with a set of guidelines to apply inrendering judgment. His decision may be requiredto rest upon the presence or absence of specificfactors. * * * The specificity of standards may berelaxed, directing the decisionmaker’s attention tothe basic policy determinations underlying thestatute without binding his action with regard tomatters of important but unforeseen detail. He maybe instructed to consider a list of factors – eitherillustrative or exhaustive – intended to illuminatethe question presented without setting a fixedbalance. * * *

I.[Justice Brennan then discusses extensively

various aspects of the Due Process Clause andconcludes as follows:]

* * * First, due process of law requires the Statesto protect individuals against the arbitrary exerciseof state power by assuring that the fundamental

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 10 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 11: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

policy choices underlying any exercise of statepower are explicitly articulated by someresponsible organ of state government. Second,due process of law is denied by state proceduralmechanisms that allow for the exercise of arbitrarypower without providing any means wherebyarbitrary action may be reviewed or corrected.Third, where federally protected rights areinvolved due process of law is denied by stateprocedures which render inefficacious the federaljudicial machinery that has been established forthe vindication of those rights. If there is any wayin which these propositions must be qualified, it isonly that in some circumstances the impossibilityof certain procedures may be sufficient to permitstate power to be exercised notwithstanding theirabsence.* * * Before we conclude that capitalsentencing is inevitably a matter of suchcomplexity that it cannot be carried out inconsonance with the fundamental requirements ofdue process, we should at the very least examinethe mechanisms developed in not incomparablesituations and previously approved by this Court[such as the termination of welfare benefits, seeGoldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254, 255 (1970).] * **

IIA legislature that has determined that the State

should kill some but not all of the persons whomit has convicted of certain crimes must inevitablydetermine how the State is to distinguish thosewho are to be killed from those who are not. * **

* * *

* * * I see no reason whatsoever to believethat the nature of capital sentencing is such thatit cannot be surrounded with the protectionsordinarily available to check arbitrary andlawless action. * * *

III* * *

A* * *

There is in my view no way that this Ohiocapital sentencing procedure can be thought topass muster under the Due Process Clause.

* * *

* * *The policies applied by the State of Ohio todetermine that James Edward Crampton should diewere neither articulated to nor explained by thejury that made that decision. Nor have they beenelsewhere set forth. * * *

* * * [T]he capital sentencing process in Ohiocontains elements that render difficult if notimpossible any consistency in result. Presumablyall judges, and certainly some juries (i.e., thosewho are specifically so instructed) will becognizant of the possibility of parole from asentence to life imprisonment. Other juries willnot. If this is an irrelevant factor, it is hard tounderstand why some juries may be given thisinformation. If it is a relevant factor, it is equallyhard to understand why other juries are not. And ifit is a relevant factor, the inevitable consequenceof presenting the information, for no explicablereason, to some but not all capital sentencingjuries, is that consistency in decisionmaking isimpossible. * * *

* * *

* * * Although the Due Process Clause does notforbid a State from imposing “a differentpunishment for the same offence * * * underparticular circumstances,” it does command thatpunishment be “dealt out to all alike who aresimilarly situated.” * * *

* * *

B* * *

I find [the California] procedure likewisedefective under the Due Process Clause. * * *

First. * * * Like Ohio, California fails to provideany means whereby the fundamental questions ofstate policy with regard to capital sentencing maybe authoritatively resolved. * * * Nothingwhatsoever anywhere in the process gives anyassurance that one defendant will be sentencedupon notions of California penological policy even

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 11 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 12: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

vaguely resembling those applied to the next.

Second. * * * The Due Process Clausecommands us * * * to make certain that no Statetakes one man’s life for reasons that it would notapply to another. * * * [The sentencing power isexercised] without guideline or check, withoutreview, without any explanation of reasons orfindings of fact, without any opportunity forultimate legislative acceptance or rejection of thepolicies applied. * * *

* * * Third. Like its Ohio counterpart, theCalifornia procedure before us inevitably operatesto frustrate the institution of federal judicialreview. We do not and cannot know what facts thejury relied upon in determining that petitionerMcGautha should be killed, or the reasons uponwhich it based that decision.

C* * * [E]ven if I thought these procedures

adequate to try a welfare claim – which they arenot, Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254, 255 (1970)– I would have little hesitation in finding theminadequate where life itself is at stake. For wehave long recognized that the degree of proceduralregularity required by the Due Process Clauseincreases with the importance of the interests atstake.

IV* * *

* * * I cannot help concluding that the Court’sopinion, at its core, rests upon nothing more solidthan its inability to imagine any regime of capitalsentencing other than that which presently exists.I cannot assent to such a basis for decision. “If wewould guide by the light of reason, we must let ourminds be bold.” New State Ice Co. v. Liebmann,285 U.S. 262, 311 (1932) (Brandeis, J.,dissenting).

THE EIGHTH AMENDMENT

Excessive bail shall not be required, norexcessive fines imposed, nor cruel andunusual punishments inflicted.

- Eighth Amendment, U.S. Constitution

Wallace Wilkerson’sChallenge to the Firing Squad

Wallace Wilkerson, convicted of murder in theterritory of Utah, was sentenced to “be publicallyshot until you are dead.” Wilkerson challenged thismethod of carrying out the death penalty beforethe Supreme Court.

In rejecting his challenge, the Court said that“[d]ifficulty would attend the effort to define withexactness the extent of the constitutional provisionwhich provides that cruel and unusual punishmentshall not be inflicted,” but, after noting the use ofpunishments such as public dissection, burningalive, drawing and quartering, the Court said, “it issafe to affirm that punishments of torture such asthose mentioned . . . and all others in the same lineof unnecessary cruelty, are forbidden by thatamendment to the Constitution.” Wilkerson v.Utah, 99 U.S. 130, 135-36 (1878). However, theCourt held that the amendment did not prohibitshooting:.

Cruel and unusual punishments are forbiddenby the Constitution, but . . . shooting as a modeof executing the death penalty for the crime ofmurder in the first degree is not included in thatcategory . . . . Soldiers convicted of desertion orother capital offenses are in the great majorityof cases sentenced to be shot, and the ceremonyfor such occasions is given in great fullness bythe writers upon the subject of courts-martial.

Following the decision,

Wilkerson was let into a jailyard where hedeclined to be blindfolded. A sheriff gave thecommand to fire and Wilkerson braced for thebarrage. He moved just enough for the bulletsto strike his arm and torso but not his heart.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 12 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 13: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

“My God!” Wilkerson shrieked. “My God!They have missed!” More than 27 minutespassed as Wilkerson bled to death in front ofastonished witnesses and a helpless doctor.1

William Kemmler’s Challenge to the Electric Chair

In 1885, in his annual message to thelegislature, the governor of New York stated: “Thepresent mode of executing criminals by hanginghas come down to us from the dark ages, and itmay well be questioned whether the science of thepresent day cannot provide a means for taking thelife of such as are condemned to die in a lessbarbarous manner. I commend this suggestion tothe consideration of the legislature.” Too manyhangings – which were then carried out in public– had been botched. A short drop did not alwayssnap the condemned prisoner’s neck, so somegagged and died a gruesome death. A long dropsometimes took the condemned’s head off entirely.

In 1886, the legislature chose a three-membercommission to investigate “the most humane andpractical method known to modern science” forcarrying out executions. The commission soonfocused on electricity as the best alternative. And,since one of the three commissioners was a dentistby profession, the panel recommended anelectrified chair. Electrocution was consideredamid intense competition between ThomasEdison’s direct current and GeorgeWestinghouse’s alternating current. Althoughalternating current had lower transmission costs,there was concern that it was considerably moredangerous than direct current. Edison, who waslosing the marketing battle to Westinghouse,recommended that alternating current be used forelectrocutions in hope that the link between deathand alternating current would diminish consumers’use of AC in their homes. The commission2

adopted this recommendation, and the legislatureenacted a law providing that,

The punishment of death must, in every case,be inflicted by causing to pass through the bodyof the convict a current of electricity ofsufficient intensity to cause death, and theapplication of such current must be continueduntil such convict is dead.

One of Edison’s associates suggested“westinghouse” as an appropriate noun for thedevice and a handy verb to describe the process inwhich it would be employed. Just as Frenchcriminals were guillotined, he reasoned, Americancriminals could be “westinghoused.”

William Kemmler, sentenced to death byelectrocution for the murder of his lover in a fit ofdrunken and jealous rage over her relationshipwith another man, challenged the new method ofexecution. Westinghouse secretly hire lawyers todefend William Kemmler, arguing that the electricchair constituted cruel and unusual punishment.Although the Eighth Amendment had not beenheld applicable to the states, the Court found thatthe Fourteenth Amendment prohibitedpunishments that were “manifestly cruel andunusual as burning at the stake, crucifixion,breaking on the wheel and the like,” but, afterreferring to Wilkerson, concluded:

Punishments are cruel when they involvetorture or a lingering death; but the punishmentof death is not cruel within the meaning of thatword as used in the constitution. It impliesthere something inhuman and barbarous, –something more than the mere extinguishmentof life.

The courts of New York held that the modeadopted in this instance might be said to beunusual because it was new, but that it couldnot be assumed to be cruel in the light of thatcommon knowledge which has stamped certainpunishments as such; that it was for thelegislature to say in what manner sentences ofdeath should be executed; that this act waspassed in the effort to devise a more humanemethod of reaching the result; that the courtswere bound to presume that the legislature waspossessed of the facts upon which it tookaction; and that by evidence taken * * * thatpresumption could not be overthrown.

1. Gilbert King, Cruel and Unusual History,

N.Y.T IM ES (op-ed), April 23, 2008.

2. See Deborah W. Denno, Is Electrocution an

Unconstitutional Method of Execution? The

Engineering of Death over the Century, 35 W M &

MARY L. REV. 551 (1994).

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 13 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 14: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

In re Kemler, 136 U.S. 436, 447 (1890).

In 1890, after Westinghouse soughtunsuccessfully to restrain the state from using itsdynamos for the purpose of the execution, WilliamKemmler became the first person to die in theelectric chair. A historian described the executionas follows:

After a thousand volts of current struckKemmler on Aug. 6, 1890, the smell of burntflesh permeated the room. He was stillbreathing. Saliva dripped from his mouth anddown his beard as he gasped for air. Nauseatedwitnesses and a tearful sheriff fled the room asKemmler’s coat burst into flames.

Another surge was applied, but minutespassed as the current built to a lethal voltage.Some witnesses thought Kemmler was about toregain consciousness, but eight long minuteslater, he was pronounced dead. 3

The three doctors who conducted the autopsyconcluded that Kemmler became “instantlyunconscious” by the first jolt and that his deathwas “painless.” Westinghouse insisted that “[t]heycould have done better with an ax.”

PAUL A. WEEMS v.

UNITED STATES

United States Supreme Court217 U.S. 349 (1909)

[Paul A. Weems was convicted of falsificationby a public official of a public and officialdocument. No fraud, intent to defraud, intent ofpersonal gain or injury was necessary forconviction. Weems was sentenced to 12 yearsimprisonment in chains at “hard and painfullabor,” followed by perpetual surveillance withoutthe right to vote or hold office. He challenged hissentence under the “cruel and unusual” clause ofthe Phillipine Bill of Rights. Basing its decision on

interpretations of the Eight Amendment, theSupreme Court stated:]

What constitutes a cruel and unusualpunishment has not been exactly decided. It hasbeen said that ordinarily the terms implysomething inhuman and barbarous, – torture andthe like. * * * The court, however * * * concededthe possibility “that punishment in the state prisonfor a long term of years might be sodisproportionate to the offense as to constitute acruel and unusual punishment.” * * *

The provision received very little debate inCongress. * * *

* * *

No case has occurred in this court which hascalled for an exhaustive definition.

* * *

* * * [From the debates regarding adoption ofthe Bill of Rights] [i]t appears that [some framers]felt sure that the spirit of liberty could be trusted,and that its ideals would be represented, notdebased, by legislation. [Patrick] Henry and thosewho believed as he did would take no chances.Their predominant political impulse was distrustof power, and they insisted on constitutionallimitations against its abuse. But surely theyintended more than to register a fear of the formsof abuse that went out of practice with the Stuarts[in England]. Surely, their jealousy of power hada saner justification than that. They were men ofaction, practical and sagacious, not beset with vainimagining, and it must have come to them thatthere could be exercises of cruelty by laws otherthan those which inflicted bodily pain ormutilation. With power in a legislature great, if notunlimited, to give criminal character to the actionsof men, with power unlimited to fix terms ofimprisonment with what accompaniments theymight, what more potent instrument of crueltycould be put into the hands of power? And it wasbelieved that power might be tempted to cruelty.This was the motive of the clause, and if we are toattribute an intelligent providence to its advocateswe cannot think that it was intended to prohibitonly practices like the Stuarts’, or to prevent only 3. Gilbert King, Cruel and Unusual History,

N.Y.T IM ES (op-ed), April 23, 2008.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 14 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 15: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

an exact repetition of history. We cannot think thatthe possibility of a coercive cruelty beingexercised through punishment was overlooked. ** *

Legislation, both statutory and constitutional, isenacted, it is true, from an experience of evils butits general language should not, therefore, benecessarily confined to the form that evil hadtheretofore taken. Time works changes, brings intoexistence new conditions and purposes. Thereforea principle, to be vital, must be capable of widerapplication than the mischief which gave it birth.This is peculiarly true of constitutions. They arenot ephemeral enactments, designed to meetpassing occasions. They are, to use the words ofChief Justice Marshall, “designed to approachimmortality as nearly as human institutions canapproach it.” The future is their care, andprovision for events of good and bad tendencies ofwhich no prophecy can be made. In the applicationof a constitution, therefore, our contemplationcannot be only of what has been, but of what maybe. Under any other rule a constitution wouldindeed be as easy of application as it would bedeficient in efficacy and power. * * *

* * *

* * * The clause of the Constitution, in theopinion of the learned commentators, may betherefore progressive, and is not fastened to theobsolete, but may acquire meaning as publicopinion becomes enlightened by a humane justice.* * *

* * * There are degrees of homicide that are notpunished so severely, nor are the following crimes:misprision of treason, inciting rebellion,conspiracy to destroy the government by force,recruiting soldiers in the United States to fightagainst the United States, forgery of letters patent,forgery of bonds and other instruments for thepurpose of defrauding the United States, robbery,larceny, and other crimes. * * * If we turn to thelegislation of the Philippine Commission we findthat * * * the highest punishment possible for acrime which may cause the loss of many thousandof dollars * * * is not greater than that which maybe imposed for falsifying a single item of a publicaccount. And this contrast shows more than

different exercises of legislative judgment. It isgreater than that. It condemns the sentence in thiscase as cruel and unusual. It exhibits a differencebetween unrestrained power and that which isexercised under the spirit of constitutionallimitations formed to establish justice. The statethereby suffers nothing and loses no power. Thepurpose of punishment is fulfilled, crime isrepressed by penalties of just, not tormenting,severity, its repetition is prevented, and hope isgiven for the reformation of the criminal.

* * *

Louisiana’s Efforts toExecute Willie Francis

Willie Francis, a stuttering 17-year-old blackyouth sought to prevent Louisiana from attemptingto electrocute him a second time after the firstattempt at the jail in St. Martinville, La., wasunsuccessful. He walked away from the electricchair known as “Gruesome Gertie” in 1946 aftertwo executioners (an inmate and a guard) from thestate penitentiary at Angola botched the wiring ofthe chair.

Reverend Maurice L. Rousseve described thefirst attempt to execute Frances as follows:

After he was strapped to the chair the Sheriffof St. Martin Parish asked him if he hadanything to say about anything and he saidnothing. Then the hood was placed before hiseyes. Then the officials in charge of theelectrocution were adjusting the mechanismsand when the needle of the meter registered toa certain point on the dial, the electrocutionerpulled down on the switch and at the same timesaid: “Goodby Willie”. At that very moment,Willie Francis’ lips puffer out and his bodysquirmed and tensed and he jumped so that thechair rocked on the floor. Then the condemnedman said: “Take it off. Let me breathe.” Thenthe switch was turned off. Then some of themen left and a few minutes after the Sheriff ofSt. Martin Parish, Mr. E. L. Resweber, came inand announced that the governor had grantedthe condemned man a reprieve.1

1. Louisiana ex rel. Francis v. Resweber, 329 U.S.

459, 480 n. 2 (Burton, J., dissenting) (1947).

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 15 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 16: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

Those in charge of the electrical equipmentinsisted that no electric current reached Francis.

Gov. Jimmie Davis ordered Francis returned tothe chair six days later. However, Francis’ lawyersobtained a stay and eventually presented hisarguments to the Supreme Court. A plurality of2

the Supreme Court analyzed the issue before it inLouisiana ex rel. Francis v. Resweber, 329 U.S.459 (1947), as follows:

As nothing has been brought to our attentionto suggest the contrary, we must and do assumethat the state officials carried out their dutiesunder the death warrant in a careful andhumane manner. Accidents happen for whichno man is to blame. We turn to the question asto whether the proposed enforcement of thecriminal law of the state is offensive to anyconstitutional requirements to which referencehas been made.

329 U.S. at 462. It rejected Francis’ claim:

We find nothing in what took place herewhich amounts to cruel and unusual punishmentin the constitutional sense. The case before usdoes not call for an examination into anypunishments except that of death. The traditionalhumanity of modern Anglo-American lawforbids the infliction of unnecessary pain in theexecution of the death sentence. * * *

Petitioner’s suggestion is that because heonce underwent the psychological strain ofpreparation for electrocution, now to require himto undergo this preparation again subjects him toa lingering or cruel and unusual punishment.Even the fact that petitioner has already beensubjected to a current of electricity does not

make his subsequent execution any more cruel inthe constitutional sense than any otherexecution. The cruelty against which theConstitution protects a convicted man is crueltyinherent in the method of punishment, not thenecessary suffering involved in any methodemployed to extinguish life humanely. The factthat an unforeseeable accident prevented theprompt consummation of the sentence cannot, itseems to us, add an element of cruelty to asubsequent execution. There is no purpose toinflict unnecessary pain nor any unnecessarypain involved in the proposed execution. Thesituation of the unfortunate victim of thisaccident is just as though he had suffered theidentical amount of mental anguish and physicalpain in any other occurrence, such as, forexample, a fire in the cell block. We cannotagree that the hardship imposed upon thepetitioner rises to that level of hardshipdenounced as denial of due process because ofcruelty.

329 U.S. at 463-64. The Court also rejected theother grounds asserted by Francis for preventing asecond attempt to execute him.

Justices Burton, Douglas, Murphy and Rutledgedissented. In an opinion by Justice Burton, theynoted that the Louisiana courts had not conductedany hearing to resolve the disputed question ofwhether a current of electricity had actually passedthrough the body of Francis, and expressed theview that the case should be remanded for adetermination of material facts.

The dissenters had no doubt that if Francis’“allegation that the official electrocutioner ‘turnedon the switch and a current of electricity wascaused to pass through [his] body,’” was true, asecond attempt to execute him would constitute“cruel and unusual punishment violative of dueprocess of law. It exceeds any punishmentprescribed by law. There is no precedent for it.What then is it, if it be not cruel, unusual andunlawful?” 379 U.S. at 479.

The dissenters were not persuaded by the otherjustices’ focus on lack of intent. They responded:“Lack of intent that the first application be lessthan fatal is not material. The intent of the

2. Francis was represented in the United States

Supreme Court by J. Skelly Wright of New Orleans,

who was later appointed United States District Judge

and enforced the Supreme Court’s decision in Brown v.

Board of Education in desegregating the public schools

in New Orleans. He was later appointed by President

Kennedy to the United States Court of Appeals for the

District of Columbia Circuit. See Arthur S. Miller, A

CAPACITY FOR OUTRAGE: THE B IOGRAPHY OF JUDGE J.

SKELLY WRIGHT (Greenwood Press 1984).

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 16 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 17: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

executioner cannot lessen the torture or excuse theresult. It was the statutory duty of the stateofficials to make sure that there was no failure.”329 U.S. at 477. Justice Burton framed the issue asfollows:

In determining whether the proposed procedureis unconstitutional, we must measure it againsta lawful electrocution. The contrast is thatbetween instantaneous death and death byinstallments – caused by electric shocksadministered after one or more interveningperiods of complete consciousness of the victim.Electrocution, when instantaneous, can beinflicted by a state in conformity with dueprocess of law. * * *

* * *

[The Louisiana death penalty law] does notprovide for electrocution by interrupted orrepeated applications of electric current atintervals of several days or even minutes. It doesnot provide for the application of electric currentof an intensity less than that sufficient to causedeath. It prescribes expressly and solely for theapplication of a current of sufficient intensity tocause death and for the continuance of thatapplication until death results. Prescribingcapital punishment, it should be construedstrictly. There can be no implied provision for asecond, third or multiple application of thecurrent. * * *

329 U.S. at 474-75.

Justice Frankfurter cast the deciding fifth voterejecting Francis’ claim. In a concurring opinion,he characterized the teenager’s ordeal as an“innocent misadventure” which did not violate theConstitution:

I cannot bring myself to believe that forLouisiana to leave to executive clemency, ratherthan to require, mitigation of a sentence of deathduly pronounced upon conviction for murderbecause a first attempt to carry it out was aninnocent misadventure, offends a principle ofjustice “Rooted in the traditions and conscienceof our people”. Short of the compulsion of sucha principle, this Court must abstain from

interference with State action no matter howstrong one’s personal feeling of revulsionagainst a State’s insistence on its pound of flesh.* * * Strongly drawn as I am to some of thesentiments expressed by [the dissent], I cannotrid myself of the conviction that were I to holdthat Louisiana would transgress the Due ProcessClause if the State were allowed, in the precisecircumstances before us, to carry out the deathsentence, I would be enforcing my private viewrather than that consensus of society’s opinionwhich, for purposes of due process, is thestandard enjoined by the Constitution.

329 U.S. at 470-71.

After the Court rendered its decision, JusticeFrankfurter made an extraordinary and virtuallyunprecedented effort to have Francis’ deathsentence commuted to life imprisonment. He wroteto a friend who was a prominent member of theLouisiana bar asking him to seek clemency forFrancis. Although his friend did so, Francis was3

denied clemency.

Right before the second attempt to executeFrancis, his lawyers discovered that the twoexecutioners who had botched the first attempt toexecute him were “so drunk it would have beenimpossible for them to have known what they weredoing.” After unsuccessful efforts to obtain a stay4

in the state courts, lawyers for Francis tried againto bring the case before the Supreme Court,reaching the Court only 24 hours before Franciswas to be executed. After conferring, the Courtdenied the petition for habeas corpus.

On May 9, 1947, Willie Francis, wearingpinstriped slacks, black dress shoes and a whiteshirt with dark stripes and unshackled, walked outof the jail in New Iberia with the sheriff anddeputies, got in a car and was taken nine miles tothe jail in St. Martinsville. “I’m wearing mySunday pants and my Sunday heart to the chair,”Francis said. “Ain’t going to wear no beat-up pantsto see the Lord. Been busy talking my way into

3. Gilbert King, THE EXECUTION OF W ILLIE FRANCIS:

RACE, MURDER AND THE SEARCH FOR JUSTICE IN THE

AM ERICAN SOUTH 233-37 (2008).

4. Id. at 239-40.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 17 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 18: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

heaven for this past year. Them folks expecting meto come in style.”

He was taken to a cell on second floor. After visits with his family, his lawyer and his priest, hewalked 13 steps to the same electric chair he hadbeen in before. He died upon receiving 2,500 voltsof current. He was 18 years old.5

Both Chief Justice John Roberts and JusticeClarence Thomas relied on decision in Francis’case in their opinions rejecting challenges to lethalinjection in Baze v. Rees, 128 S.Ct. 1520 (2008).

Albert L. TROPv.

John Foster DULLES, as Secretary of State and United States Department of State.

United States Supreme Court356 U.S. 86 (1958)

[Albert L. Trop, a private in the U.S. Army, wasconvicted of desertion from a military stockade atCasablanca in 1944, and sentenced to three yearsat hard labor, forfeiture of all pay and allowancesand a dishonorable discharge. When he applied fora passport in 1952, he learned that a federal statutehad stripped him of his citizenship by reason of hisconviction and dishonorable discharge for wartimedesertion.

[In response to Trop’s argument that forfeitureof citizenship was cruel and unusual, the SupremeCourt, in a plurality opinion by Chief JusticeWarren, writing for four justices, framed the issuesas follows:]

Since wartime desertion is punishable by death,there can be no argument that the penalty ofdenationalization is excessive in relation to thegravity of the crime. The question is whether thispenalty subjects the individual to a fate forbiddenby the principle of civilized treatment guaranteedby the Eighth Amendment.

[The Chief Justice continued:]

At the outset, let us put to one side the deathpenalty as an index of the constitutional limit onpunishment. Whatever the arguments may beagainst capital punishment, both on moral groundsand in terms of accomplishing the purposes ofpunishment – and they are forceful – the deathpenalty has been employed throughout our history,and, in a day when it is still widely accepted, itcannot be said to violate the constitutional conceptof cruelty. But it is equally plain that the existenceof the death penalty is not a license to theGovernment to devise any punishment short ofdeath within the limit of its imagination.

* * *

The basic concept underlying the EighthAmendment is nothing less than the dignity ofman. While the State has the power to punish, theAmendment stands to assure that this power beexercised within the limits of civilized standards.Fines, imprisonment and even execution may beimposed depending upon the enormity of thecrime, but any technique outside the bounds ofthese traditional penalties is constitutionallysuspect. * * * The Court recognized in [Weems]that the words of the Amendment are not precise,and that their scope is not static. The Amendmentmust draw its meaning from the evolving standardsof decency that mark the progress of a maturingsociety.

[The Chief Justice observed in footnote 32, that“[w]hether the word ‘unusual’ has any qualitativemeaning different from ‘cruel’ is not clear,” butstated “[i]f the word ‘unusual’ is to have anymeaning apart from the word ‘cruel,’ however, themeaning should be the ordinary one, signifyingsomething different from that which is generallydone. Denationalization as a punishment certainlymeets this test. It was never explicitly santioned bythis Government until 1940 and never testedagainst the Constitution until this day.”]

* * *

There may be involved no physicalmistreatment, no primitive torture. There is insteadthe total destruction of the individual’s status inorganized society. It is a form of punishment moreprimitive than torture, for it destroys for the 5. Id. at 244-249, 278.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 18 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 19: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

individual the political existence that was centuriesin the development. The punishment strips thecitizen of his status in the national andinternational political community. His veryexistence is at the sufferance of the country inwhich he happens to find himself. While any onecountry may accord him some rights, andpresumably as long as he remained in this countryhe would enjoy the limited rights of an alien, nocountry need do so because he is stateless.Furthermore, his enjoyment of even the limitedrights of an alien might be subject to terminationat any time by reason of deportation. In short, theexpatriate has lost the right to have rights.

This punishment is offensive to cardinalprinciples for which the Constitution stands. Itsubjects the individual to a fate of ever-increasingfear and distress. He knows not whatdiscriminations may be established against him,what proscriptions may be directed against him,and when and for what cause his existence in hisnative land may be terminated. He may be subjectto banishment, a fate universally decried bycivilized people. He is stateless, a conditiondeplored in the international community ofdemocracies.

* * *

The civilized nations of the world are in virtualunanimity that statelessness is not to be imposedas punishment for crime. It is true that severalcountries prescribe expatriation in the event thattheir nationals engage in conduct in derogation ofnative allegiance. Even statutes of this sort aregenerally applicable primarily to naturalizedcitizens. But use of denationalization aspunishment for crime is an entirely differentmatter. The United Nations’ survey of thenationality laws of 84 nations of the world revealsthat only two countries, the Philippines andTurkey, impose denationalization as a penalty fordesertion. In this country the Eighth Amendmentforbids that to be done.

[Justice Brennan, concurring, framed thequestion as follows: “we must inquire whetherthere exists a relevant connection between theparticular legislative enactment and the powergranted to Congress by the Constitution.” He

found expatriation to be a severe, uncertainpunishment without justification of achievingrehabilitation or specific deterrence. “Clearly theseverity of the penalty, in the case of a seriousoffense, is not enough to invalidate it where thenature of the penalty is rationally directed toachieve the legitimate ends of punishment,”Brennan wrote, but he found the relation betweenthe punishment of expatriation was too tenuous torationally achieve the governmental purpose ofaugmenting Congress’s war powers.]

Note – Robinson v. California The Court held that the Cruel and Unusual

Punishments Clause applies to the States throughthe operation of the Fourteenth Amendment inRobinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660 (1962). TheCourt held that imprisonment for the crime ofbeing a drug addict was cruel and unusual.Because drug addiction is an illness which may becontracted involuntarily, the Court said that“imprisonment for ninety days is not, in theabstract, a punishment which is either cruel orunusual. But the question cannot be considered inthe abstract. Even one day in prison would be acruel and unusual punishment for the ‘crime’ ofhaving a common cold.” Id.

The Court Re-ExaminesThe Death Penalty in 1972 –

Furman v. Georgia

As we have read, the Supreme Court rejected achallenged to the death penalty under the dueprocess clause of the Fourteenth Amendment inMcGautha v. California in 1971, holding that:

In light of history, experience, and the presentlimitations of human knowledge, we find it quiteimpossible to say that committing to theuntrammeled discretion of the jury the power topronounce life or death in capital cases isoffensive to anything in the Constitution.

Nevertheless, the Court considered an EighthAmendment challenge to the death penalty just ayear after McGautha in Furman v. Georgia. Theauthor of the McGautha opinion, John MarshallHarlan II retired from the Court in 1971 and was

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 19 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 20: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

replaced by William Rehnquist. Hugo Black, whowrote a concurring opinion in McGautha, alsoretired from the Court in 1971 and was replaced byLewis F. Powell, Jr. Both were appointed byPresident Richard M. Nixon. The other membersof the McGautha Court continued to serve in 1972.

When the Court decided Furman, it included two other Nixon appointees, Chief Justice WarrenBurger and Associate Justice Harry Blackmun.The other members of the Court were William O.Douglas, appointed by President Franklin D.Roosevelt; William Brennan, Jr. and PotterStewart, both appointed by President Dwight D.Eisenhower; Byron White, appointed by PresidentJohn F. Kennedy; and Thurgood Marshall,appointed by President Lyndon B. Johnson.

For consideration and discussion

As you read Furman v. Georgia, identify howeach of the nine justices interprets the EighthAmendment’s prohibition of “cruel and unusualpunishment.” That is, what were the coreprinciples of the Eighth Amendment identified bythe different justices and how do they apply them?

Even though the five justices in the majorityeach wrote separately, are there any areas ofoverlap or agreement? What are the areas ofagreement among the dissenting justices?

What are the main concerns of each of theJustices in the majority? I.e., what constitutionaldefects do they see in the way the death penalty isbeing carried out? Could those defects becorrected and, if so, how?

What justices in the majority leave open thepossibility of a death penalty statute that satisfiestheir Eighth Amendment analysis?

Does the meaning of the “cruel and unusual”clause change as society “matures” and “becomesmore enlightened” or does that even occur?

Assuming that it does, what is yourunderstanding from the different opinions abouthow the Court is to assess the “evolving standardsof decency” of society? Is this a proper role for theCourt?

How do the different justices see the role of thepurposes of sentencing – deterrence, retribution,incapacitation, rehabilitation, etc. – in the EighthAmendment analysis?

What is the most fundamental differencebetween the five who found the death penaltyunconstitutional and the four who did not?

Assuming that you were drafting a death penaltystatute that would satisfy the concerns in Furman,what approach would you take?

William Henry FURMAN, v.

State of GEORGIA.

Lucious JACKSON, Jr., v.

State of GEORGIA.

Elmer BRANCH, v.

State of TEXAS.

Supreme Court of the United States408 U.S. 238, 92 S.Ct. 2726, 33 L.Ed.2d 346 (1972)

PER CURIAM.

[William Henry Furman] was convicted ofmurder in Georgia and was sentenced to death. ** * [Lucious Jackson] was convicted of rape inGeorgia and was sentenced to death. * * * [ElmerBranch] was convicted of rape in Texas and wassentenced to death. * * * Certiorari was grantedlimited to the following question: “Does theimposition and carrying out of the death penalty in[these cases] constitute cruel and unusualpunishment in violation of the Eighth andFourteenth Amendments?” The Court holds thatthe imposition and carrying out of the deathpenalty in these cases constitute cruel and unusualpunishment in violation of the Eighth andFourteenth Amendments. The judgment in eachcase is therefore reversed insofar as it leavesundisturbed the death sentence imposed, and thecases are remanded for further proceedings. Soordered.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 20 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 21: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

Mr. Justice DOUGLAS, concurring.

In these three cases the death penalty wasimposed, one of them for murder, and two forrape. In each the determination of whether thepenalty should be death or a lighter punishmentwas left by the State to the discretion of the judgeor of the jury. In each of the three cases the trialwas to a jury. They are here on petitions forcertiorari which we granted limited to the questionwhether the imposition and execution of the deathpenalty constitute “cruel and unusual punishment”within the meaning of the Eighth Amendment asapplied to the States by the Fourteenth. I vote tovacate each judgment, believing that the exactionof the death penalty does violate the Eighth andFourteenth Amendments.

* * *

It has been assumed in our decisions thatpunishment by death is not cruel, unless themanner of execution can be said to be inhumanand barbarous. It is also said in our opinions thatthe proscription of cruel and unusual punishments“is not fastened to the obsolete, but may acquiremeaning as public opinion becomes enlightened bya humane justice.” Weems v. United States, 217U.S. at 378. A like statement was made in Trop v.Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101, that the EighthAmendment “must draw its meaning from theevolving standards of decency that mark theprogress of a maturing society.”

The generality of a law inflicting capitalpunishment is one thing. What may be said of thevalidity of a law on the books and what may bedone with the law in its application do, or may,lead to quite different conclusions.

It would seem to be incontestable that the deathpenalty inflicted on one defendant is “unusual” ifit discriminates against him by reason of his race,religion, wealth, social position, or class, or if it isimposed under a procedure that gives room for theplay of such prejudices.

* * *

There is increasing recognition of the fact thatthe basic theme of equal protection is implicit in“cruel and unusual” punishments. “A penalty . . .should be considered `unusually’ imposed if it is

administered arbitrarily or discriminatorily.” The12

same authors add that “[t]he extreme rarity withwhich applicable death penalty provisions are putto use raises a strong inference of arbitrariness.”The President’s Commission on Law Enforcementand Administration of Justice recently concluded:

Finally there is evidence that the imposition ofthe death sentence and the exercise of dispensingpower by the courts and the executive followdiscriminatory patterns. The death sentence isdisproportionately imposed and carried out onthe poor, the Negro, and the members ofunpopular groups.

A study of capital cases in Texas from 1924 to1968 reached the following conclusions:

Application of the death penalty is unequal:most of those executed were poor, young, andignorant. * * *

Seventy-five of the 460 cases involvedcodefendants, who, under Texas law, were givenseparate trials. In several instances where awhite and a Negro were co-defendants, the whitewas sentenced to life imprisonment or a term ofyears, and the Negro was given the deathpenalty.

Another ethnic disparity is found in the typeof sentence imposed for rape. The Negroconvicted of rape is far more likely to get thedeath penalty than a term sentence, whereaswhites and Latins are far more likely to get aterm sentence than the death penalty.

Warden Lewis E. Lawes of Sing Sing said:

* * * It is an unequal punishment in the wayit is applied to the rich and to the poor. Thedefendant of wealth and position never goes tothe electric chair or to the gallows. Juries do notintentionally favour the rich, the law istheoretically impartial, but the defendant withample means is able to have his case presentedwith every favourable aspect, while the poordefendant often has a lawyer assigned by the

12. Goldberg & Dershowitz, Declaring the Death

Penalty Unconstitutional, 83 Harv.L.Rev. 1773, 1790.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 21 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 22: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

court. Sometimes such assignment is consideredpart of political patronage; usually the lawyerassigned has had no experience whatever in acapital case.

Former Attorney General Ramsey Clark hassaid, “It is the poor, the sick, the ignorant, thepowerless and the hated who are executed.” One17

searches our chronicles in vain for the execution ofany member of the affluent strata of this society.The Leopolds and Loebs are given prison terms,not sentenced to death.

Jackson, a black, convicted of the rape of awhite woman, was 21 years old. A court-appointedpsychiatrist said that Jackson was of averageeducation and average intelligence, that he was notan imbecile, or schizophrenic, or phychotic, thathis traits were the product of environmentalinfluences, and that he was competent to standtrial. Jackson had entered the house after thehusband left for work. He held scissors against theneck of the wife, demanding money. She couldfind none and a struggle ensued for the scissors, abattle which she lost; and she was then raped,Jackson keeping the scissors pressed against herneck. * * * Jackson was a convict who hadescaped from a work gang in the area, a result of athree-year sentence for auto theft. He was at largefor three days and during that time had committedseveral other offenses – burglary, auto theft, andassault and battery.

Furman, a black, killed a householder whileseeking to enter the home at night. Furman shotthe deceased through a closed door. He was 26years old and had finished the sixth grade inschool. Pending trial, he was committed to theGeorgia Central State Hospital for a psychiatricexamination on his plea of insanity tendered bycourt-appointed counsel. The superintendentreported that a unanimous staff diagnosticconference had concluded “that this patient shouldretain his present diagnosis of Mental Deficiency,Mild to Moderate, with Psychotic Episodesassociated with Convulsive Disorder.” Thephysicians agreed that “at present the patient is notpsychotic, but he is not capable of cooperating

with his counsel in the preparation of his defense;”and the staff believed “that he is in need of furtherpsychiatric hospitalization and treatment.”

Later, the superintendent reported that the staffdiagnosis was Mental Deficiency, Mild toModerate, with Psychotic Episodes associatedwith Convulsive Disorder. He concluded,however, that Furman was “not psychotic atpresent, knows right from wrong and is able tocooperate with his counsel in preparing hisdefense.”

Branch, a black, entered the rural home of a65-year-old widow, a white, while she slept andraped her, holding his arm against her throat.Thereupon he demanded money and for 30minutes or more the widow searched for money,finding little. As he left, Jackson said if the widowtold anyone what happened, he would return andkill her. * * *

He had previously been convicted of felony theftand found to be a borderline mental deficient andwell below the average IQ of Texas prisoninmates. He had the equivalent of five and a halfyears of grade school education. He had a “dullintelligence” and was in the lowest fourthpercentile of his class.

We cannot say from facts disclosed in theserecords that these defendants were sentenced todeath because they were black. Yet our task is notrestricted to an effort to divine what motivesimpelled these death penalties. Rather, we dealwith a system of law and of justice that leaves tothe uncontrolled discretion of judges or juries thedetermination whether defendants committingthese crimes should die or be imprisoned. Underthese laws no standards govern the selection of thepenalty. People live or die, dependent on the whimof one man or of 12.

* * *

Those who wrote the Eighth Amendment knewwhat price their forebears had paid for a systembased, not on equal justice, but on discrimination.In those days the target was not the blacks or thepoor, but the dissenters, those who opposedabsolutism in government, who struggled for aparliamentary regime, and who opposed

17. CRIM E IN AM ERICA 335 (1970).

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 22 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 23: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

governments’ recurring efforts to foist a particularreligion on the people. But the tool of capitalpunishment was used with vengeance against theopposition and those unpopular with the regime.One cannot read this history without realizing thatthe desire for equality was reflected in the banagainst “cruel and unusual punishments” containedin the Eighth Amendment.

In a Nation committed to equal protection of thelaws there is no permissible “caste” aspect of lawenforcement. Yet we know that the discretion ofjudges and juries in imposing the death penaltyenables the penalty to be selectively applied,feeding prejudices against the accused if he is poorand despised, and lacking political clout, or if he isa member of a suspect or unpopular minority, andsaving those who by social position may be in amore protected position. In ancient Hindu law aBrahman was exempt from capital punishment,and under that law, “[g]enerally, in the law books,punishment increased in severity as social statusdiminished.” We have, I fear, taken in practice thesame position, partially as a result of making thedeath penalty discretionary and partially as a resultof the ability of the rich to purchase the services ofthe most respected and most resourceful legaltalent in the Nation.

The high service rendered by the “cruel andunusual” punishment clause of the EighthAmendment is to require legislatures to writepenal laws that are evenhanded, nonselective, andnonarbitrary, and to require judges to see to it thatgeneral laws are not applied sparsely, selectively,and spottily to unpopular groups.

A law that stated that anyone making more than$50,000 would be exempt from the death penaltywould plainly fall, as would a law that in termssaid that blacks, those who never went beyond thefifth grade in school, those who made less than$3,000 a year, or those who were unpopular orunstable should be the only people executed. Alaw which in the overall view reaches that result inpractice has no more sanctity than a law which interms provides the same.21

Thus, these discretionary statutes areunconstitutional in their operation. They arepregnant with discrimination and discrimination isan ingredient not compatible with the idea of equalprotection of the laws that is implicit in the ban on“cruel and unusual” punishments.

* * *

Mr. Justice BRENNAN, concurring. * * *

I* * *

Several conclusions thus emerge from the histo-ry of the adoption of the [Cruel and Unusual]Clause [of the Eighth Amendment]. We know thatthe Framers’ concern was directed specifically atthe exercise of legislative power. They included inthe Bill of Rights a prohibition upon “cruel andunusual punishments” precisely because thelegislature would otherwise have had theunfettered power to prescribe punishments forcrimes. Yet we cannot now know exactly what theFramers thought “cruel and unusual punishments”were. Certainly they intended to ban torturouspunishments, but the available evidence does notsupport the further conclusion that only torturouspunishments were to be outlawed. The Framers

21. Cf. B. Prettyman, Jr., DEATH AND THE SUPREM E

COURT 296-297 (1961).

The disparity of representation in capital cases raises

doubts about capital punishment itself, which has

been abolished in only nine states. If a James Avery

(345 U.S. 559) can be saved from electrocution

because his attorney made timely objection to the

selection of a jury by the use of yellow and white

tickets, while an Aubry Williams (349 U.S. 375) can

be sent to his death by a jury selected in precisely the

same manner, we are imposing our most extreme

penalty in an uneven fashion.

* * *

And it is not only a matter of ability. An attorney

must be found who is prepared to spend precious

hours – the basic commodity he has to sell – on a

case that seldom fully compensates him and often

brings him no fee at all. The public has no concep-

tion of the time and effort devoted by attorneys to

indigent cases. And in a first-degree case, the added

responsibility of having a man’s life depend upon the

outcome exacts a heavy toll.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 23 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 24: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

were well aware that the reach of the Clause wasnot limited to the proscription of unspeakableatrocities. Nor did they intend simply to forbidpunishments considered “cruel and unusual” at thetime. The “import” of the Clause is, indeed,“indefinite,” and for good reason. A constitutionalprovision “is enacted, it is true, from an experienceof evils, but its general language should not,therefore, be necessarily confined to the form thatevil had theretofore taken. Time works changes,brings into existence new conditions and purposes.Therefore a principle, to be vital, must be capableof wider application than the mischief which gaveit birth.” Weems v. United States, 217 U.S., at 373

* * *

* * * If the judicial conclusion that a punishmentis “cruel and unusual” “depend[ed] upon virtuallyunanimous condemnation of the penalty at issue,”then, “[l]ike no other constitutional provision, [theClause’s] only function would be to legitimizeadvances already made by the other departmentsand opinions already the conventional wisdom.”We know that the Framers did not envision “sonarrow a role for this basic guaranty of humanrights.” The right to be free of cruel and unusualpunishments, like the other guarantees of the Billof Rights, “may not be submitted to vote; [it]depend[s] on the outcome of no elections.” “Thevery purpose of a Bill of Rights was to withdrawcertain subjects from the vicissitudes of politicalcontroversy, to place them beyond the reach ofmajorities and officials and to establish them aslegal principles to be applied by the courts.”

* * *

IIOurs would indeed be a simple task were we

required merely to measure a challengedpunishment against those that history has longcondemned. * * * Our task today is more complex.We know “that the words of the [Clause] are notprecise, and that their scope is not static.” Weknow, therefore, that the Clause “must draw itsmeaning from the evolving standards of decencythat mark the progress of a maturing society.” Thatknowledge, of course, is but the beginning of theinquiry. * * *

[E]ven though “[t]his Court has had little occa-sion to give precise content to the [Clause],” thereare principles recognized in our cases and inherentin the Clause sufficient to permit a judicialdetermination whether a challenged punishmentcomports with human dignity.

The primary principle is that a punishment mustnot be so severe as to be degrading to the dignityof human beings. * * *

More than the presence of pain, however, iscomprehended in the judgment that the extremeseverity of a punishment makes it degrading to thedignity of human beings. * * *

* * * Finally, of course, a punishment may bedegrading simply by reason of its enormity. Aprime example is expatriation, a “punishment moreprimitive than torture,” Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. at101, for it necessarily involves a denial by societyof the individual’s existence as a member of thehuman community.

In determining whether a punishment comportswith human dignity, we are aided also by a secondprinciple inherent in the Clause – that the Statemust not arbitrarily inflict a severe punishment.This principle derives from the notion that theState does not respect human dignity when,without reason, it inflicts upon some people asevere punishment that it does not inflict uponothers. Indeed, the very words “cruel and unusualpunishments” imply condemnation of the arbitraryinfliction of severe punishments. And, as we nowknow, the English history of the Clause reveals aparticular concern with the establishment of asafeguard against arbitrary punishments.

* * *

A third principle inherent in the Clause is that asevere punishment must not be unacceptable tocontemporary society. Rejection by society, ofcourse, is a strong indication that a severepunishment does not comport with human dignity.In applying this principle, however, we must makecertain that the judicial determination is asobjective as possible.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 24 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 25: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

The question under this principle, then, iswhether there are objective indicators from whicha court can conclude that contemporary societyconsiders a severe punishment unacceptable.Accordingly, the judicial task is to review thehistory of a challenged punishment and to examinesociety’s present practices with respect to its use.Legislative authorization, of course, does notestablish acceptance. The acceptability of a severepunishment is measured, not by its availability, forit might become so offensive to society as never tobe inflicted, but by its use.

The final principle inherent in the Clause is thata severe punishment must not be excessive. Apunishment is excessive under this principle if it isunnecessary: The infliction of a severe punishmentby the State cannot comport with human dignitywhen it is nothing more than the pointlessinfliction of suffering. If there is a significantlyless severe punishment adequate to achieve thepurposes for which the punishment is inflicted, thepunishment inflicted is unnecessary and thereforeexcessive. * * * Although the determination that asevere punishment is excessive may be groundedin a judgment that it is disproportionate to thecrime, the more significant basis is that thepunishment serves no penal purpose moreeffectively than a less severe punishment.

* * *

* * * The test, then, will ordinarily be acumulative one: If a punishment is unusuallysevere, if there is a strong probability that it isinflicted arbitrarily, if it is substantially rejected bycontemporary society, and if there is no reason tobelieve that it serves any penal purpose moreeffectively than some less severe punishment, thenthe continued infliction of that punishment violatesthe command of the Clause that the State may notinflict inhuman and uncivilized punishments uponthose convicted of crimes.

IIIThe punishment challenged in these cases is

death. * * *

* * * I will analyze the punishment of death interms of the principles set out above and thecumulative test to which they lead: It is a denial of

human dignity for the State arbitrarily to subject aperson to an unusually severe punishment thatsociety has indicated it does not regard asacceptable, and that cannot be shown to serve anypenal purpose more effectively than a significantlyless drastic punishment. * * *

Death is a unique punishment in the UnitedStates. In a society that so strongly affirms thesanctity of life, not surprisingly the common viewis that death is the ultimate sanction. * * *

The only explanation for the uniqueness of deathis its extreme severity. Death is today an unusuallysevere punishment, unusual in its pain, in itsfinality, and in its enormity. No other existingpunishment is comparable to death in terms ofphysical and mental suffering. * * * Since thediscontinuance of flogging as a constitutionallypermissible punishment, death remains as the onlypunishment that may involve the consciousinfliction of physical pain. In addition, we knowthat mental pain is an inseparable part of ourpractice of punishing criminals by death, for theprospect of pending execution exacts a frightfultoll during the inevitable long wait between theimposition of sentence and the actual infliction ofdeath. As the California Supreme Court pointedout, “the process of carrying out a verdict of deathis often so degrading and brutalizing to the humanspirit as to constitute psychological torture.” * * *

The unusual severity of death is manifested mostclearly in its finality and enormity. Death, in theserespects, is in a class by itself. * * *

* * * The calculated killing of a human being bythe State involves, by its very nature, a denial ofthe executed person’s humanity. * * *

In comparison to all other punishments today,then, the deliberate extinguishment of human lifeby the State is uniquely degrading to humandignity. I would not hesitate to hold, on thatground alone, that death is today a “cruel andunusual” punishment, were it not that death is apunishment of longstanding usage and acceptancein this country. I therefore turn to the secondprinciple – that the State may not arbitrarily inflictan unusually severe punishment.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 25 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 26: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

The outstanding characteristic of our presentpractice of punishing criminals by death is theinfrequency with which we resort to it. Theevidence is conclusive that death is not theordinary punishment for any crime.

There has been a steady decline in the inflictionof this punishment in every decade since the1930’s, the earliest period for which accuratestatistics are available. In the 1930’s, executionsaveraged 167 per year; in the 1940’s, the averagewas 128; in the 1950’s, it was 72; and in the years1960-1962, it was 48. There have been a total of46 executions since then, 36 of them in 1963-1964.* * * The contemporary rarity of the infliction ofthis punishment is thus the end result of along-continued decline. That rarity is plainlyrevealed by an examination of the years 1961-1970, the last 10-year period for which statisticsare available. During that time, an average of 106death sentences was imposed each year. * * *[E]xecutions totaled only 42 in 1961 and 47 in1962, an average of less than one per week; thenumber dwindled to 21 in 1963, to 15 in 1964, andto seven in 1965; in 1966, there was oneexecution, and in 1967, there were two.

When a country of over 200 million peopleinflicts an unusually severe punishment no morethan 50 times a year, the inference is strong thatthe punishment is not being regularly and fairlyapplied. To dispel it would indeed require a clearshowing of nonarbitrary infliction.

Although there are no exact figures available, weknow that thousands of murders and rapes arecommitted annually in States where death is anauthorized punishment for those crimes. * * * [I]twould take the purest sophistry to deny that deathis inflicted in only a minute fraction of these cases.How much rarer, after all, could the infliction ofdeath be?

When the punishment of death is inflicted in atrivial number of the cases in which it is legallyavailable, the conclusion is virtually inescapablethat it is being inflicted arbitrarily. Indeed, itsmacks of little more than a lottery system. * * *

* * * The probability of arbitrariness issufficiently substantial that it can be relied upon,

in combination with the other principles, in reach-ing a judgment on the constitutionality of thispunishment.

* * * I turn * * * to the third principle. Anexamination of the history and present operation ofthe American practice of punishing criminals bydeath reveals that this punishment has been almosttotally rejected by contemporary society. * * *

The progressive decline in, and the current rarityof, the infliction of death demonstrate that oursociety seriously questions the appropriateness ofthis punishment today. The States point out thatmany legislatures authorize death as the punish-ment for certain crimes and that substantialsegments of the public, as reflected in opinionpolls and referendum votes, continue to support it.Yet the availability of this punishment throughstatutory authorization, as well as the polls andreferenda, which amount simply to approval ofthat authorization, simply underscores the extent towhich our society has in fact rejected this punish-ment. When an unusually severe punishment isauthorized for wide-scale application but not,because of society’s refusal, inflicted save in a fewinstances, the inference is compelling that there isa deep-seated reluctance to inflict it. Indeed, thelikelihood is great that the punishment is toleratedonly because of its disuse. The objective indicatorof society’s view of an unusually severepunishment is what society does with it, and todaysociety will inflict death upon only a small sampleof the eligible criminals. Rejection could hardly bemore complete without becoming absolute. At thevery least, I must conclude that contemporarysociety views this punishment with substantialdoubt.

The final principle to be considered is that anunusually severe and degrading punishment maynot be excessive in view of the purposes for whichit is inflicted. This principle, too, is related to theothers. When there is a strong probability that theState is arbitrarily inflicting an unusually severepunishment that is subject to grave societal doubts,it is likely also that the punishment cannot beshown to be serving any penal purpose that couldnot be served equally well by some less severepunishment.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 26 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 27: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

* * * We are not presented with the theoreticalquestion whether under any imaginablecircumstances the threat of death might be agreater deterrent to the commission of capitalcrimes than the threat of imprisonment. We areconcerned with the practice of punishing criminalsby death as it exists in the United States today.Proponents of this argument necessarily admit thatits validity depends upon the existence of a systemin which the punishment of death is invariably andswiftly imposed. Our system, of course, satisfiesneither condition. A rational person contemplatinga murder or rape is confronted, not with thecertainty of a speedy death, but with the slightestpossibility that he will be executed in the distantfuture. The risk of death is remote and improbable;in contrast, the risk of long-term imprisonment isnear and great. In short, whatever the speculativevalidity of the assumption that the threat of deathis a superior deterrent, there is no reason to believethat as currently administerd the punishment ofdeath is necessary to deter the commission ofcapital crimes. * * *

* * *

There is, then, no substantial reason to believethat the punishment of death, as currentlyadministered, is necessary for the protection ofsociety. The only other purpose suggested, onethat is independent of protection for society, isretribution. Shortly stated, retribution in thiscontext means that criminals are put to death be-cause they deserve it.

* * * As administered today, however, thepunishment of death cannot be justified as anecessary means of exacting retribution fromcriminals. When the overwhelming number ofcriminals who commit capital crimes go to prison,it cannot be concluded that death serves thepurpose of retribution more effectively thanimprisonment. * * * As the history of thepunishment of death in this country shows, oursociety wishes to prevent crime; we have no desireto kill criminals simply to get even with them.

In sum, the punishment of death is inconsistentwith all four principles: * * * The function of theseprinciples is to enable a court to determinewhether a punishment comports with humandignity. Death, quite simply, does not.

IVWhen this country was founded, memories of the

Stuart horrors were fresh and severe corporalpunishments were common. Death was not then aunique punishment. The practice of punishingcriminals by death, moreover, was widespread andby and large acceptable to society. Indeed, withoutdeveloped prison systems, there was frequently noworkable alternative. Since that time successiverestrictions, imposed against the background of acontinuing moral controversy, have drasticallycurtailed the use of this punishment. Today deathis a uniquely and unusually severe punishment.When examined by the principles applicable underthe Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause, deathstands condemned as fatally offensive to humandignity. The punishment of death is therefore“cruel and unusual,” and the States may no longerinflict it as a punishment for crimes. Rather thankill an arbitrary handful of criminals each year, theStates will confine them in prison. “The statethereby suffers nothing and loses no power. Thepurpose of punishment is fulfilled, crime isrepressed by penalties of just, not tormenting,severity, its repetition is prevented, and hope isgiven for the reformation of the criminal.” Weemsv. United States, 217 U.S., at 381.

Mr. Justice STEWART, concurring.

The penalty of death differs from all other formsof criminal punishment, not in degree but in kind.It is unique in its total irrevocability. It is unique inits rejection of rehabilitation of the convict as abasic purpose of criminal justice. And it is unique,finally, in its absolute renunciation of all that isembodied in our concept of humanity.

For these and other reasons, at least two of myBrothers have concluded that the infliction of thedeath penalty is constitutionally impermissible inall circumstances under the Eight and FourteenthAmendments. Their case is a strong one. But I findit unnecessary to reach the ultimate question theywould decide.

* * *

Legislatures – state and federal – have some-times specified that the penalty of death shall bethe mandatory punishment for every person

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 27 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 28: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

convicted of engaging in certain designatedcriminal conduct. Congress, for example, hasprovided that anyone convicted of acting as a spyfor the enemy in time of war shall be put to death. * * *

If we were reviewing death sentences imposedunder these or similar laws, we would be facedwith the need to decide whether capitalpunishment is unconstitutional for all crimes andunder all circumstances. We would need to decidewhether a legislature – state or federal – couldconstitutionally determine that certain criminalconduct is so atrocious that society’s interest indeterrence and retribution wholly outweighs anyconsiderations of reform or rehabilitation of theperpetrator, and that, despite the inconclusiveempirical evidence, only the automatic penalty ofdeath will provide maximum deterrence.

On that score I would say only that I cannotagree that retribution is a constitutionallyimpermissible ingredient in the imposition ofpunishment. The instinct for retribution is part ofthe nature of man, and channeling that instinct inthe administration of criminal justice serves animportant purpose in promoting the stability of asociety governed by law. When people begin tobelieve that organized society is unwilling orunable to impose upon criminal offenders thepunishment they “deserve,” then there are sownthe seeds of anarchy – of self-help, vigilantejustice, and lynch law.

The constitutionality of capital punishment inthe abstract is not, however, before us in thesecases. For the Georgia and Texas Legislatureshave not provided that the death penalty shall beimposed upon all those who are found guilty of

forcible rape. And the Georgia Legislature has not8

ordained that death shall be the automaticpunishment for murder. In a word, neither State9

has made a legislative determination that forciblerape and murder can be deterred only by imposingthe penalty of death upon all who perpetrate thoseoffenses. As Mr. Justice White so tellingly puts it,the “legislative will is not frustrated if the penaltyis never imposed.”

Instead, the death sentences now before us arethe product of a legal system that brings them, Ibelieve, within the very core of the EighthAmendment’s guarantee against cruel and unusualpunishments. In the first place, it is clear that thesesentences are “cruel” in the sense that they exces-sively go beyond, not in degree but in kind, thepunishments that the state legislatures havedetermined to be necessary. In the second place, itis equally clear that these sentences are “unusual”in the sense that the penalty of death isinfrequently imposed for murder, and that itsimposition for rape is extraordinarily rare. But I donot rest by conclusion upon these two propositionsalone.

These death sentences are cruel and unusual inthe same way that being struck by lightning iscruel and unusual. For, of all the people convictedof rapes and murders in 1967 and 1968, many justas reprehensible as these, the petitioners areamong a capriciously selected random handfulupon whom the sentence of death has in fact beenimposed. My concurring Brothers have dem-onstrated that, if any basis can be discerned for the

8. Georgia law, at the time of the conviction and

sentencing of [Jackson] left the jury a choice between

the death penalty, life imprisonment, or “imprisonment

and labor in the penitentiary for not less than one year

nor more than 20 years.” The current Georgia provision

for the punishment of forcible rape continues to leave

the same broad sentencing leeway. Texas law, under

which [Branch] was sentenced, provides that a “person

guilty of rape shall be punished by death or by confine-

ment in the penitentiary for life, or for any term of years

not less than five.”

9. Georgia law, under which [Furman] was sentenced,

left the jury a choice between the death penalty and life

imprisonment. Current Georgia law provides for similar

sentencing leeway.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 28 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 29: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

selection of these few to be sentenced to die, it isthe constitutionally impermissible basis of race.But racial discrimination has not been proved, andI put it to one side. I simply conclude that theEighth and Fourteenth Amendments cannottolerate the infliction of a sentence of death underlegal systems that permit this unique penalty to beso wantonly and so freakishly imposed.

* * *

Mr. Justice WHITE, concurring.

The facial constitutionality of statutes requiringthe imposition of the death penalty for first-degreemurder, for more narrowly defined categories ofmurder, or for rape would present quite differentissues under the Eighth Amendment than are posedby the cases before us. In joining the Court’sjudgments, therefore, I do not at all intimate thatthe death penalty is unconstitutional per se or thatthere is no system of capital punishment thatwould comport with the Eighth Amendment. * * *

The narrower question to which I address myselfconcerns the constitutionality of capital punish-ment statutes under which (1) the legislatureauthorizes the imposition of the death penalty formurder or rape; (2) the legislature does not itselfmandate the penalty in any particular class or kindof case (that is, legislative will is not frustrated ifthe penalty is never imposed), but delegates tojudges or juries the decisions as to those cases, ifany, in which the penalty will be utilized; and (3)judges and juries have ordered the death penaltywith such infrequency that the odds are now verymuch against imposition and execution of thepenalty with respect to any convicted murderer orrapist. It is in this context that we must considerwhether the execution of these petitioners wouldviolate the Eighth Amendment.

I begin with what I consider a near truism: thatthe death penalty could so seldom be imposed thatit would cease to be a credible deterrent ormeasurably to contribute to any other end ofpunishment in the criminal justice system. It isperhaps true that no matter how infrequently thoseconvicted of rape or murder are executed, thepenalty so imposed is not disproportionate to thecrime and those executed may deserve exactly

what they received. It would also be clear thatexecuted defendants are finally and completelyincapacitated from again committing rape ormurder or any other crime. But when imposition ofthe penalty reaches a certain degree ofinfrequency, it would be very doubtful that anyexisting general need for retribution would bemeasurably satisfied. Nor could it be said withconfidence that society’s need for specificdeterrence justifies death for so few when for somany in like circumstances life imprisonment orshorter prison terms are judged sufficient, or thatcommunity values are measurably reinforced byauthorizing a penalty so rarely invoked.

Most important, a major goal of the criminal law– to deter others by punishing the convictedcriminal – would not be substantially served wherethe penalty is so seldom invoked that it ceases tobe the credible threat essential to influence theconduct of others. * * * [C]ommon sense andexperience tell us that seldom-enforced lawsbecome ineffective measures for controllinghuman conduct and that the death penalty, unlessimposed with sufficient frequency, will make littlecontribution to deterring those crimes for which itmay be exacted.

The imposition and execution of the deathpenalty are obviously cruel in the dictionary sense.But the penalty has not been considered cruel andunusual punishment in the constitutional sensebecause it was thought justified by the social endsit was deemed to serve. At the moment that itceases realistically to further these purposes,however, the emerging question is whether itsimposition in such circumstances would violate theEighth Amendment. It is my view that it would, forits imposition would then be the pointless andneedless extinction of life with only marginalcontributions to any discernible social or publicpurposes. A penalty with such negligible returns tothe State would be patently excessive and crueland unusual punishment violative of the EighthAmendment.

It is also my judgment that this point has beenreached with respect to capital punishment as it ispresently administered under the statutes involvedin these cases. * * * I cannot avoid the conclusionthat as the statutes before us are now administered,

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 29 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 30: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

the penalty is so infrequently imposed that thethreat of execution is too attenuated to be ofsubstantial service to criminal justice.

* * * I can do no more than state a conclusionbased on 10 years of almost daily exposure to thefacts and circumstances of hundreds and hundredsof federal and state criminal cases involvingcrimes for which death is the authorized penalty.That conclusion, as I have said, is that the deathpenalty is exacted with great infrequency even forthe most atrocious crimes and that there is nomeaningful basis for distinguishing the few casesin which it is imposed from the many cases inwhich it is not. The short of it is that the policy ofvesting sentencing authority primarily in juries –a decision largely motivated by the desire tomitigate the harshness of the law and to bringcommunity judgment to bear on the sentence aswell as guilt or innocence – has so effectivelyachieved its aims that capital punishment withinthe confines of the statutes now before us has forall practical purposes run its course.

* * *

In this respect, I add only that past and presentlegislative judgment with respect to the deathpenalty loses much of its force when viewed inlight of the recurring practice of delegatingsentencing authority to the jury and the fact that ajury, in its own discretion and without violating itstrust or any statutory policy, may refuse to imposethe death penalty no matter what the circumstancesof the crime. Legislative “policy” is thus necessar-ily defined not by what is legislatively authorizedbut by what juries and judges do in exercising thediscretion so regularly conferred upon them. In myjudgment what was done in these cases violatedthe Eighth Amendment.

Mr. Justice MARSHALL, concurring.

* * *

The criminal acts with which we are confrontedare ugly, vicious, reprehensible acts. Their sheerbrutality cannot and should not be minimized. But,we are not called upon to condone the penalizedconduct; we are asked only to examine the penaltyimposed on each of the petitioners and to

determine whether or not it violates the EighthAmendment. The question then is not whether wecondone rape or murder, for surely we do not; it iswhether capital punishment is “a punishment nolonger consistent with our own self-respect” and,therefore, violative of the Eighth Amendment.

* * *

* * * I am not oblivious to the fact that this istruly a matter of life and death. Not only does itinvolve the lives of these three petitioners, butthose of the almost 600 other condemned men andwomen in this country currently awaitingexecution. While this fact cannot affect ourultimate decision, it necessitates that the decisionbe free from any possibility of error.

* * *

* * * It has often been noted that Americancitizens know almost nothing about capital punish-ment. Some of the conclusions arrived at * * * andthe supporting evidence would be critical to aninformed judgment on the morality of the deathpenalty: e.g., that the death penalty is no moreeffective a deterrent than life imprisonment, thatconvicted murderers are rarely executed, but areusually sentenced to a term in prison; thatconvicted murderers usually are model prisoners,and that they almost always become lawabidingcitizens upon their release from prison; that thecosts of executing a capital offender exceed thecosts of imprisoning him for life; that while inprison, a convict under sentence of death performsnone of the useful functions that life prisonersperform; that no attempt is made in the sentencingprocess to ferret out likely recidivists forexecution; and that the death penalty may actuallystimulate criminal activity.

This information would almost surely convincethe average citizen that the death penalty wasunwise, but a problem arises as to whether itwould convince him that the penalty was morallyreprehensible. This problem arises from the factthat the public’s desire for retribution, even thoughthis is a goal that the legislature cannotconstitutionally pursue as its sole justification forcapital punishment, might influence the citizenry’sview of the morality of capital punishment. The

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 30 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 31: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

solution to the problem lies in the fact that no onehas ever seriously advanced retribution as alegitimate goal of our society. Defenses of capitalpunishment are always mounted on deterrent orother similar theories. This should not besurprising. It is the people of this country whohave urged in the past that prisons rehabilitate aswell as isolate offenders, and it is the people whohave injected a sense of purpose into ourpenology. I cannot believe that at this stage in ourhistory, the American people would everknowingly support purposeless vengeance. Thus,I believe that the great mass of citizens wouldconclude on the basis of the material alreadyconsidered that the death penalty is immoral andtherefore unconstitutional.

But, if this information needs supplementing, Ibelieve that the following facts would serve toconvince even the most hesitant of citizens tocondemn death as a sanction: capital punishmentis imposed discriminatorily against certainidentifiable classes of people; there is evidencethat innocent people have been executed beforetheir innocence can be proved; and the deathpenalty wreaks havoc with our entire criminaljustice system. Each of these facts is consideredbriefly below.

Regarding discrimination, it has been said that“[i]t is usually the poor, the illiterate, theunderprivileged, the member of the minority group– the man who, because he is without means, andis defended by a court-appointed attorney – whobecomes society’s sacrificial lamb . . ..” Indeed, alook at the bare statistics regarding executions isenough to betray much of the discrimination. Atotal of 3,859 persons have been executed since1930, of whom 1,751 were white and 2,066 wereNegro. Of the executions, 3,334 were for murder;1,664 of the executed murderers were white and1,630 were Negro; 455 persons, including 48whites and 405 Negroes, were executed for rape.It is immediately apparent that Negroes wereexecuted far more often than whites in proportionto their percentage of the population. Studiesindicate that while the higher rate of executionamong Negroes is partially due to a higher rate ofcrime, there is evidence of racial discrimination.Racial or other discriminations should not besurprising. In McGautha v. California, this Court

held “that committing to the untrammeleddiscretion of the jury the power to pronounce lifeor death in capital cases is [not] offensive toanything in the Constitution.” This was an openinvitation to discrimination.

* * *

It also is evident that the burden of capitalpunishment falls upon the poor, the ignorant, andthe under privileged members of society. It is thepoor, and the members of minority groups who areleast able to voice their complaints against capitalpunishment. Their impotence leaves them victimsof a sanction that the wealthier, better-represented,just-as-guilty person can escape. So long as thecapital sanction is used only against the forlorn,easily forgotten members of society, legislators arecontent to maintain the status quo, because changewould draw attention to the problem and concernmight develop. Ignorance is perpetuated andapathy soon becomes its mate, and we havetoday’s situation. * * *

Just as Americans know little about who isexecuted and why, they are unaware of thepotential dangers of executing an innocent man.Our “beyond a reasonable doubt” burden of proofin criminal cases is intended to protect theinnocent, but we know it is not foolproof. * * *

Proving one’s innocense after a jury finding ofguilt is almost impossible. While reviewing courtsare willing to entertain all kinds of collateralattacks where a sentence of death is involved, theyvery rarely dispute the jury’s interpretation of theevidence. This is, perhaps, as it should be. But, ifan innocent man has been found guilty, he mustthen depend on the good faith of the prosecutor'soffice to help him establish his innocence. There isevidence, however, that prosecutors do notwelcome the idea of having convictions, whichthey labored hard to secure, overturned, and thattheir cooperation is highly unlikely.

No matter how careful courts are, the possibilityof perjured testimony, mistaken honest testimony,and human error remain all too real. * * *

* * *

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 31 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 32: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

To arrive at the conclusion that the death penaltyviolates the Eighth Amendment, we have had toengage in a long and tedious journey. * * *

At a time in our history when the streets of theNation’s cities inspire fear and despair, rather thanpride and hope, it is difficult to maintainobjectivity and concern for our fellow citizens.But, the measure of a country’s greatness is itsability to retain compassion in time of crisis. Nonation in the recorded history of man has a greatertradition of revering justice and fair treatment forall its citizens in times of turmoil, confusion, andtension than ours. This is a country which standstallest in troubled times, a country that clings tofundamental principles, cherishes its constitutionalheritage, and rejects simple solutions thatcompromise the values that lie at the roots of ourdemocratic system.

In striking down capital punishment, this Courtdoes not malign our system of government. On thecontrary, it pays homage to it. Only in a freesociety could right triumph in difficult times, andcould civilization record its magnificentadvancement. In recognizing the humanity of ourfellow beings, we pay ourselves the highesttribute. We achieve “a major milestone in the longroad up from barbarism” and join theapproximately 70 other jurisdictions in the worldwhich celebrate their regard for civilization andhumanity by shunning capital punishment.

Justice Marshall appended to his opinionvarious documents about states which hadrepealed the death penalty, homicide rates andnumber of executions. See 408 U.S. at 372.

Mr. Chief Justice BURGER, with whom Mr.Justice BLACKMUN, Mr. Justice POWELL, andMr. Justice REHNQUIST join, dissenting.

* * *

IIt we were possessed of legislative power, I

would either join with Mr. Justice BRENNAN andMr. Justice MARSHALL or, at the very least,restrict the use of capital punishment to a smallcategory of the most heinous crimes. Ourconstitutional inquiry, however, must be divorced

from personal feelings as to the morality andefficacy of the death penalty, and be confined tothe meaning and applicability of the uncertainlanguage of the Eighth Amendment. There is nonovelty in being called upon to interpret a constitu-tional provision that is less than self-defining, but,of all our fundamental guarantees, the ban on“cruel and unusual punishments” is one of themost difficult to translate into judicially man-ageable terms. The widely divergent views of theAmendment expressed in today’s opinions revealthe haze that surrounds this constitutionalcommand. Yet it is essential to our role as a courtthat we not seize upon the enigmatic character ofthe guarantee as an invitation to enact our personalpredilections into law.

Although the Eighth Amendment literally readsas prohibiting only those punishments that are both“cruel” and “unusual,” history compels theconclusion that the Constitution prohibits allpunishments of extreme and barbarous cruelty,regardless of how frequently or infrequentlyimposed.

* * *

IICounsel for petitioners properly concede that

capital punishment was not impermissibly cruel atthe time of the adoption of the Eighth Amendment.Not only do the records of the debates indicate thatthe Founding Fathers were limited in their concernto the prevention of torture, but it is also clearfrom the language of the Constitution itself thatthere was no thought whatever of the eliminationof capital punishment. The opening sentence of theFifth Amendment is a guarantee that the deathpenalty not be imposed “unless on a presentmentor indictment of a Grand Jury.” The DoubleJeopardy Clause of the Fifth Amendment is aprohibition against being “twice put in jeopardy oflife” for the same offense. Similarly, the DueProcess Clause commands “due process of law”before an accused can be “deprived of life, liberty,or property.” Thus, the explicit language of theConstitution affirmatively acknowledges the legalpower to impose capital punishment. * * *

In the 181 years since the enactment of theEighth Amendment, not a single decision of this

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 32 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 33: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

Court has cast the slightest shadow of a doubt onthe constitutionality of capital punishment. * * *

* * *

I do not suggest that the validity of legislativelyauthorized punishments presents no justiciableissue under the Eighth Amendment, but, rather,that the primacy of the legislative role narrowlyconfines the scope of judicial inquiry. Whether ornot provable, and whether or not true at all times,in a democracy the legislative judgment ispresumed to embody the basic standards ofdecency prevailing in the society. Thispresumption can only be negated by unambiguousand compelling evidence of legislative default.

IIIThere are no obvious indications that capital

punishment offends the conscience of society tosuch a degree that our traditional deference to thelegislative judgment must be abandoned. It is nota punishment such as burning at the stake thateveryone would ineffably find to be repugnant toall civilized standards. Nor is it a punishment soroundly condemned that only a few aberrantlegislatures have retained it on the statute books.Capital punishment is authorized by statute in 40States, the District of Columbia, and in the federalcourts for the commission of certain crimes. Onfour occasions in the last 11 years Congress hasadded to the list of federal crimes punishable bydeath. In looking for reliable indicia ofcontemporary attitude, none more trustworthy hasbeen advanced.

* * * Without assessing the reliability of [publicopinion] polls, or intimating that any judicialreliance could ever be placed on them, it need onlybe noted that the reported results have shownnothing approximating the universal condemnationof capital punishment that might lead us to suspectthat the legislatures in general have lost touch withcurrent social values.

Counsel for petitioners rely on a different bodyof empirical evidence. They argue, in effect, thatthe number of cases in which the death penalty isimposed, as compared with the number of cases inwhich it is statutorily available, reflects a generalrevulsion toward the penalty that would lead to its

repeal if only it were more generally and widelyenforced. * * *

It is argued that in those capital cases wherejuries have recommended mercy, they have givenexpression to civilized values and effectivelyrenounced the legislative authorization for capitalpunishment. At the same time it is argued thatwhere juries have made the awesome decision tosend men to their deaths, they have actedarbitrarily and without sensitivity to prevailingstandards of decency.

* * *

* * * The selectivity of juries in imposing thepunishment of death is properly viewed as arefinement on, rather than a repudiation of, thestatutory authorization for that penalty.Legislatures prescribe the categories of crimes forwhich the death penalty should be available, and,acting as “the conscience of the community,”juries are entrusted to determine in individualcases that the ultimate punishment is warranted.Juries are undoubtedly influenced in this judgmentby myriad factors. * * * Given the generalawareness that death is no longer a routinepunishment for the crimes for which it is madeavailable, it is hardly surprising that juries havebeen increasingly meticulous in their imposition ofthe penalty. But to assume from the mere fact ofrelative infrequency that only a random assortmentof pariahs are sentenced to death, is to cast gravedoubt on the basic integrity of our jury system.

It would, of course, be unrealistic to assume thatjuries have been perfectly consistent in choosingthe cases where the death penalty is to be imposed,for no human institution performs with perfectconsistency. There are doubtless prisoners ondeath row who would not be there had they beentried before a different jury or in a different State.In this sense their fate has been controlled by afortuitous circumstance. However, this element offortuity does not stand as an indictment either ofthe general functioning of juries in capital cases orof the integrity of jury decisions in individualcases. There is no empirical basis for concludingthat juries have generally failed to discharge ingood faith the[ir] responsibility – that of choosing

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 33 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 34: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

between life and death in individual cases ac-cording to the dictates of community values.

* * * [I]f selective imposition evidences arejection of capital punishment in those caseswhere it is not imposed, it surely evidences acorrelative affirmation of the penalty in thosecases where it is imposed.

* * *

IVCapital punishment has also been attacked as

violative of the Eighth Amendment on the groundthat it is not needed to achieve legitimate penalaims and is thus “unnecessarily cruel.” As a purepolicy matter, this approach has much torecommend it, but it seeks to give a dimension tothe Eighth Amendment that it was never intendedto have and promotes a line of inquiry that thisCourt has never before pursued.

* * *

Apart from these isolated uses of the word“unnecessary,” nothing in the cases suggests thatit is for the courts to make a determination of theefficacy of punishments. * * *

* * * Two of the several aims of punishment aregenerally associated with capital punishment –retribution and deterrence. * * * There is noauthority suggesting that the Eighth Amendmentwas intended to purge the law of its retributiveelements, and the Court has consistently assumedthat retribution is a legitimate dimension of thepunishment of crimes.

The less esoteric but no less controversial ques-tion is whether the death penalty acts as a superiordeterrent. Those favoring abolition find noevidence that it does. Those favoring retentionstart from the intuitive notion that capitalpunishment should act as the most effectivedeterrent and note that there is no convincingevidence that it does not. Escape from thisempirical stalemate is sought by placing theburden of proof on the States and concluding thatthey have failed to demonstrate that capitalpunishment is a more effective deterrent than lifeimprisonment. * * * If it were proper to put the

States to the test of demonstrating the deterrentvalue of capital punishment, we could just as wellask them to prove the need for life imprisonmentor any other punishment. Yet I know of no con-vincing evidence that life imprisonment is a moreeffective deterrent than 20 years’ imprisonment, oreven that a $10 parking ticket is a more effectivedeterrent than a $5 parking ticket. In fact, there aresome who go so far as to challenge the notion thatany punishments deter crime. If the States areunable to adduce convincing proof rebutting suchassertions, does it then follow that all punishmentsare suspect as being “cruel and unusual” within themeaning of the Constitution? On the contrary, Isubmit that the questions raised by the necessityapproach are beyond the pale of judicial inquiryunder the Eighth Amendment.

V* * *

To be sure, there is a recitation cast in EighthAmendment terms: petitioners’ sentences are“cruel” because they exceed that which thelegislatures have deemed necessary for all cases;petitioners’ sentences are “unusual” because theyexceed that which is imposed in most cases. Thisapplication of the words of the Eighth Amendmentsuggests that capital punishment can be made tosatisfy Eighth Amendment values if its rate ofimposition is somehow multiplied; it seeminglyfollows that the flexible sentencing system createdby the legislatures, and carried out by juries andjudges, has yielded more mercy than the EighthAmendment can stand. The implications of thisapproach are mildly ironical. * * * * * * The decisive grievance of the [concurring]opinions – not translated into Eighth Amendmentterms – is that the present system of discretionarysentencing in capital cases has failed to produceevenhanded justice; the problem is not that too fewhave been sentenced to die, but that the selectionprocess has followed no rational pattern. Thisclaim of arbitrariness is not only lacking inempirical support, but also it manifestly fails toestablish that the death penalty is a “cruel andunusual” punishment. * * * The approach of theseconcurring opinions has no antecedent in theEighth Amendment cases. It is essentially and

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 34 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 35: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

exclusively a procedural due process argument. ** *

* * * [I]t would be disingenuous to suggest thattoday’s ruling has done anything less than overruleMcGautha in the guise of an Eighth Amendmentadjudication. * * *

Real change could clearly be brought about iflegislatures provided mandatory death sentences insuch a way as to deny juries the opportunity tobring in a verdict on a lesser charge; under such asystem, the death sentence could only be avoidedby a verdict of acquittal. If this is the onlyalternative that the legislatures can safely pursueunder today’s ruling, I would have preferred thatthe Court opt for total abolition.

It seems remarkable to me that with our basictrust in lay jurors as the keystone in our system ofcriminal justice, it should now be suggested thatwe take the most sensitive and important of alldecisions away from them. I could more easily bepersuaded that mandatory sentences of death,without the intervening and ameliorating impact oflay jurors, are so arbitrary and doctrinaire that theyviolate the Constitution. The very infrequency ofdeath penalties imposed by jurors attests theircautious and discriminating reservation of thatpenalty for the most extreme cases. * * *

VISince there is no majority of the Court on the

ultimate issue presented in these cases, the futureof capital punishment in this country has been leftin an uncertain limbo. Rather than providing afinal and unambiguous answer on the basicconstitutional question, the collective impact ofthe majority’s ruling is to demand an undeter-mined measure of change from the various statelegislatures and the Congress. * * * I am not alto-gether displeased that legislative bodies have beengiven the opportunity, and indeed unavoidableresponsibility, to make a thorough re-evaluation ofthe entire subject of capital punishment. If today’sopinions demonstrate nothing else, they starklyshow that this is an area where legislatures can actfar more effectively than courts.

* * *

The highest judicial duty is to recognize thelimits on judicial power and to permit thedemocratic processes to deal with matters fallingoutside of those limits. * * *

Mr. Justice BLACKMUN, dissenting.

1. Cases such as these provide for me an excru-ciating agony of the spirit. I yield to no one in thedepth of my distaste, antipathy, and, indeed,abhorrence, for the death penalty, with all itsaspects of physical distress and fear and of moraljudgment exercised by finite minds. That distasteis buttressed by a belief that capital punishmentserves no useful purpose that can be demonstrated.For me, it violates childhood’s training and life’sexperiences, and is not compatible with the philo-sophical convictions I have been able to develop.It is antagonistic to any sense of “reverence forlife.” Were I a legislator, I would vote against thedeath penalty for the policy reasons argued bycounsel for the respective petitioners andexpressed and adopted in the several opinions filedby the Justices who vote to reverse thesejudgments.

2. Having lived for many years in a State thatdoes not have the death penalty [Minnesota], thateffectively abolished it in 1911, and that carriedout its last execution on February 13, 1906 capitalpunishment had never been a part of life for me. Inmy State, it just did not exist. So far as I candetermine, the State, purely from a statisticaldeterrence point of view, was neither the worsenor the better for its abolition, for, as the concur-ring opinions observe, the statistics prove little, ifanything. But the State and its citizens acceptedthe fact that the death penalty was not to be in thearsenal of possible punishments for any crime.

* * *

5. To reverse the judgments in these cases is, ofcourse, the easy choice. It is easier to strike thebalance in favor of life and against death. It iscomforting to relax in the thoughts – perhaps therationalizations – that this is the compassionatedecision for a maturing society; that this is themoral and the “right” thing to do; that thereby weconvince ourselves that we are moving down theroad toward human decency; that we value life

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 35 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 36: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

even though that life has taken another or others orhas grievously scarred another or others and theirfamilies; and that we are less barbaric than wewere in 1879, or in 1890, or in 1910, or in 1947, orin 1958, or in 1963, or a year ago, in 1971 * * *

This, for me, is good argument, and it makessome sense. But it is good argument and it makessense only in a legislative and executive way andnot as a judicial expedient. As I have said above,were I a legislator, I would do all I could tosponsor and to vote for legislation abolishing thedeath penalty. And were I the chief executive of asovereign State, I would be sorely tempted toexercise executive clemency * * *. There – on theLegislative Branch of the State or FederalGovernment, and secondarily, on the ExecutiveBranch – is where the authority and responsibilityfor this kind of action lies. The authority shouldnot be taken over by the judiciary in the modernguise of an Eighth Amendment issue. * * *

* * *

Although personally I may rejoice at the Court’sresult, I find it difficult to accept or to justify as amatter of history, of law, or of constitutionalpronouncement. I fear the Court has overstepped.It has sought and has achieved an end.

Mr. Justice POWELL, with whom THECHIEF JUSTICE, Mr. Justice BLACKMUN, andMr. Justice REHNQUIST join, dissenting.

* * *

Any attempt to discern contemporary standardsof decency through the review of objective factorsmust take into account several overridingconsiderations which petitioners choose todiscount or ignore. In a democracy the firstindicator of the public’s attitude must always befound in the legislative judgments of the people’schosen representatives. * * *

The second and even more direct source ofinformation reflecting the public’s attitude towardcapital punishment is the jury. * * *

* * * During the 1960’s juries returned in excessof a thousand death sentences, a rate of approxi-

mately two per week. Whether it is true that deathsentences were returned in less than 10% of thecases as petitioners estimate or whether somehigher percentage is more accurate, these totalssimply do not support petitioners’ assertion at oralargument that “the death penalty is virtuallyunanimously repudiated and condemned by theconscience of contemporary society.” * * *

One must conclude, contrary to petitioners’submission, that the indicators most likely toreflect the public’s view – legislative bodies, statereferenda and the juries which have the actualresponsibility – do not support the contention thatevolving standards of decency require totalabolition of capital punishment. * * *

Petitioners seek to salvage their thesis by argu-ing that the infrequency and discriminatory natureof the actual resort to the ultimate penalty tend todiffuse public opposition. We are told that thepenalty is imposed exclusively on uninfluentialminorities – “the poor and powerless, personallyugly and socially unacceptable.” It is urged thatthis pattern of application assures that largesegments of the public will be either uninformedor unconcerned and will have no reason tomeasure the punishment against prevailing moralstandards.

* * *

Apart from the impermissibility of basing aconstitutional judgment of this magnitude on suchspeculative assumptions, the argument suffersfrom other defects. If, as petitioners urge, we are toengage in speculation, it is not at all certain thatthe public would experience deep-felt revulsion ifthe States were to execute as many sentencedcapital offenders this year as they executed in themid-1930’s. It seems more likely that publicreaction, rather than being characterized by undif-ferentiated rejection, would depend upon the factsand circumstances surrounding each particularcase.

* * *

* * * Much also is made of the undeniable factthat the death penalty has a greater impact on thelower economic strata of society, which include a

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 36 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 37: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

relatively higher percentage of persons of minorityracial and ethnic group backgrounds. * * *

Certainly the claim is justified that this criminalsanction falls more heavily on the relativelyimpoverished and underprivileged elements ofsociety. The “have-nots” in every society alwayshave been subject to greater pressure to commitcrimes and to fewer constraints than their moreaffluent fellow citizens. This is, indeed, a tragicbyproduct of social and economic deprivation, butit is not an argument of constitutional proportionsunder the Eighth or Fourteenth Amendment. Thesame discriminatory impact argument could bemade with equal force and logic with respect tothose sentenced to prison terms. The Due ProcessClause admits of no distinction between thedeprivation of “life” and the deprivation of“liberty.” If discriminatory impact renders capitalpunishment cruel and unusual, it likewise rendersinvalid most of the prescribed penalties for crimesof violence. The root causes of the higherincidence of criminal penalties on “minorities andthe poor” will not be cured by abolishing thesystem of penalties. Nor, indeed, could any societyhave a viable system of criminal justice ifsanctions were abolished or ameliorated becausemost of those who commit crimes happen to beunderprivileged. The basic problem results notfrom the penalties imposed for criminal conductbut from social and economic factors that haveplagued humanity since the beginning of recordedhistory, frustrating all efforts to create in anycountry at any time the perfect society in whichthere are no “poor,” no “minorities” and no“underprivileged.” The causes underlying thisproblem are unrelated to the constitutional issuebefore the Court.

Although not presented by any of the petitionerstoday, a different argument, premised on the EqualProtection Clause, might well be made. If a Negrodefendant, for instance, could demonstrate thatmembers of his race were being singled out formore severe punishment than others charged withthe same offense, a constitutional violation mightbe established. * * *

[D]iscriminatory application of the death penaltyin the past, admittedly indefensible, is nojustification for holding today that capital

punishment is invalid in all cases in whichsentences were handed out to members of the classdiscriminated against. * * *

* * * The possibility of racial bias in the trialand sentencing process has diminished in recentyears. The segregation of our society in decadespast, which contributed substantially to theseverity of punishment for interracial crimes, isnow no longer prevalent in this country. Likewise,the day is past when juries do not represent theminority group elements of the community. Theassurance of fair trials for all citizens is greatertoday than at any previous time in our history.Because standards of criminal justice have“evolved” in a manner favorable to the accused,discriminatory imposition of capital punishment isfar less likely today than in the past.

* * *

I find no support – in the language of theConstitution, in its history, or in the cases arisingunder it – for the view that this Court mayinvalidate a category of penalties because we deemless severe penalties adequate to serve the ends ofpenology. While the cases affirm our authority toprohibit punishments that are cruelly inhumane,and punishments that are cruelly excessive in thatthey are disproportionate to particular crimes, theprecedents of this Court afford no basis forstriking down a particular form of punishmentbecause we may be persuaded that means lessstringent would be equally efficacious.

Secondly, if we were free to question the justifi-cations for the use of capital punishment, a heavyburden would rest on those who attack thelegislatures’ judgments to prove the lack ofrational justifications. This Court has long heldthat legislative decisions in this area, which liewithin the special competency of that branch, areentitled to a presumption of validity.

I come now to consider, subject to the reserva-tions above expressed, the two justifications mostoften cited for the retention of capital punishment.The concept of retribution – though popular forcenturies – is now criticized as unworthy of acivilized people. Yet this Court has acknowledgedthe existence of a retributive element in criminal

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 37 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 38: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

sanctions and has never heretofore found itimpermissible. * * *

* * *

Deterrence is a more appealing justification,although opinions again differ widely. * * *

* * *

In two of the cases before us today juries im-posed sentences of death after convictions forrape. In these cases we are urged to hold that evenif capital punishment is permissible for somecrimes, it is a cruel and unusual punishment forthis crime. * * *

* * * [I]n Weems v. United States, * * * [t]hedefendant, charged with falsifying Governmentdocuments, had been sentenced to serve 15 yearsin cadena temporal, a punishment which includedcarrying chains at the wrists and ankles and theperpetual loss of the right to vote and hold office.Finding the sentence grossly excessive in lengthand condition of imprisonment, the Court struck itdown. This notion of disproportionality – thatparticular sentences may be cruelly excessive forparticular crimes – has been cited with approval inmore recent decisions of this Court.

These cases, while providing a rationale forgauging the constitutionality of capital sentencesimposed for rape, also indicate the existence ofnecessary limitations on the judicial function. Theuse of limiting terms in the various expressions ofthis test found in the opinions – grossly excessive,greatly disproportionate – emphasizes that theCourt’s power to strike down punishments asexcessive must be exercised with the greatestcircumspection. * * *

Operating within these narrow limits, I find itquite impossible to declare the death sentencegrossly excessive for all rapes. Rape is widelyrecognized as among the most serious of violentcrimes, as witnessed by the very fact that it ispunishable by death in 16 States and by lifeimprisonment in most other States. The severalreasons why rape stands so high on the list ofserious crimes are well known: It is widely viewedas the most atrocious of intrusions upon the

privacy and dignity of the victim; never is thecrime committed accidentally; rarely can it be saidto be unpremeditated; often the victim suffers seri-ous physical injury; the psychological impact canoften be as great as the physical consequences; ina real sense, the threat of both types of injury isalways present. * * *

The argument that the death penalty for rapelacks rational justification because less severepunishments might be viewed as accomplishingthe proper goals of penology is as inapposite hereas it was in considering per se abolition. * * *

* * *

With deference and respect for the views of theJustices who differ, it seems to me * * * as amatter of policy and precedent, this is a classiccase for the exercise of our oft-announcedallegiance to judicial restraint. I know of no casein which greater gravity and delicacy haveattached to the duty that this Court is called on toperform whenever legislation – state or federal – ischallenged on constitutional grounds. It seems tome that the sweeping judicial action undertakentoday reflects a basic lack of faith and confidencein the democratic process. Many may regret, as Ido, the failure of some legislative bodies toaddress the capital punishment issue with greaterfrankness or effectiveness. Many might decry theirfailure either to abolish the penalty entirely orselectively, or to establish standards for itsenforcement. But impatience with the slowness,and even the unresponsiveness, of legislatures isno justification for judicial intrusion upon theirhistoric powers. * * *

Mr. Justice REHNQUIST, with whom THECHIEF JUSTICE, Mr. Justice BLACKMUN, andMr. Justice POWELL join, dissenting.

The Court’s judgments today strike down apenalty that our Nation’s legislators have thoughtnecessary since our country was founded. * * *Whatever its precise rationale, today’s holdingnecessarily brings into sharp relief thefundamental question of the role of judicial reviewin a democratic society. How can government bythe elected representatives of the people co-existwith the power of the federal judiciary, whose

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 38 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 39: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

members are constitutionally insulated fromresponsiveness to the popular will, to declareinvalid laws duly enacted by the popular branchesof government?

The answer, of course, is found in Hamilton’sFederalist Paper No. 78 and in Chief JusticeMarshall’s classic opinion in Marbury v. Madison.An oft-told story since then, it bearssummarization once more. Sovereignty residesultimately in the people as a whole and, byadopting through their States a writtenConstitution for the Nation and subsequentlyadding amendments to that instrument, they haveboth granted certain powers to the NationalGovernment, and denied other powers to theNational and the State Governments. Courts areexercising no more than the judicial functionconferred upon them by Art. III of the Constitutionwhen they assess, in a case before them, whetheror not a particular legislative enactment is withinthe authority granted by the Constitution to theenacting body, and whether it runs afoul of somelimitation placed by the Constitution on theauthority of that body. For the theory is that thepeople themselves have spoken in theConstitution, and therefore its commands aresuperior to the commands of the legislature, whichis merely an agent of the people.

The Founding Fathers thus wisely sought to havethe best of both worlds, the undeniable benefits ofboth democratic self-government and individualrights protected against possible excesses of thatform of government.

The courts in cases properly before them havebeen entrusted under the Constitution with the lastword, short of constitutional amendment, as towhether a law passed by the legislature conformsto the Constitution. But just because courts ingeneral, and this Court in particular, do have thelast word, the admonition of Mr. Justice Stonedissenting in United States v. Butler must beconstantly borne in mind:

[W]hile unconstitutional exercise of power bythe executive and legislative branches of thegovernment is subject to judicial restraint, theonly check upon our own exercise of power isour own sense of self-restraint.

297 U.S. 1, 78-79 (1936).

Rigorous attention to the limits of this Court’sauthority is likewise enjoined because of thenatural desire that beguiles judges along with otherhuman beings into imposing their own views ofgoodness, truth, and justice upon others. Judgesdiffer only in that they have the power, if not theauthority, to enforce their desires. This isdoubtless why nearly two centuries of judicialprecedent from this Court counsel the sparing useof that power. The most expansive reading of theleading constitutional cases does not remotelysuggest that this Court has been granted a rovingcommission, either by the Founding Fathers or bythe framers of the Fourteenth Amendment, tostrike down laws that are based upon notions ofpolicy or morality suddenly found unacceptable bya majority of this Court. * * *

A separate reason for deference to the legislativejudgment is the consequence of human error on thepart of the judiciary with respect to theconstitutional issue before it. Human error there isbound to be, judges being men and women, andmen and women being what they are. But an errorin mistakenly sustaining the constitutionality of aparticular enactment, while wrongfully deprivingthe individual of a right secured to him by theConstitution, nonetheless does so by simply lettingstand a duly enacted law of a democraticallychosen legislative body. The error resulting froma mistaken upholding of an individual’sconstitutional claim against the validity of alegislative enactment is a good deal more serious.For the result in such a case is not to leavestanding a law duly enacted by a representativeassembly, but to impose upon the Nation thejudicial fiat of a majority of a court of judgeswhose connection with the popular will is remoteat best.

The task of judging constitutional cases imposedby Art. III cannot for this reason be avoided, but itmust surely be approached with the deepesthumility and genuine deference to legislativejudgment. Today’s decision to invalidate capitalpunishment is, I respectfully submit, significantlylacking in those attributes. * * *

* * *

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 39 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment

Page 40: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT: RACE, POVERTY & DISADVANTAGE · 1965 Exec 7 1966 1 1967 2 1968 0 1969 0 10 [There were no executions from 1968 through 1976.] Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics,

If there can be said to be one dominant theme inthe Constitution, perhaps more fully articulated inthe Federalist Papers than in the instrument itself,it is the notion of checks and balances. TheFramers were well aware of the natural desire ofoffice holders as well as others to seek to expandthe scope and authority of their particular office atthe expense of others. They sought to provideagainst success in such efforts by erectingadequate checks and balances in the form of grantsof authority to each branch of the government inorder to counteract and prevent usurpation on thepart of the others.

This philosophy of the Framers is best describedby one of the ablest and greatest of their number,James Madison, in Federalist No. 51:

In framing a government which is to beadministered by men over men, the greatdifficulty lies in this: You must first enable thegovernment to controul the governed; and in thenext place, oblige it to controul itself.

Madison’s observation applies to the JudicialBranch with at least as much force as to theLegislative and Executive Branches. Whileoverreaching by the Legislative and ExecutiveBranches may result in the sacrifice of individualprotections that the Constitution was designed tosecure against action of the State, judicialoverreaching may result in sacrifice of the equallyimportant right of the people to govern themselves.The Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses ofthe Fourteenth Amendment were “never intendedto destroy the States’ power to governthemselves.”

The very nature of judicial review, as pointedout by Justice Stone in his dissent in the Butlercase, makes the courts the least subject toMadisonian check in the event that they shall, forthe best of motives, expand judicial authoritybeyond the limits contemplated by the Framers. Itis for this reason that judicial self-restraint issurely an implied, if not an expressed, condition ofthe grant of authority of judicial review. TheCourt’s holding in these cases has been reached, Ibelieve, in complete disregard of that impliedcondition.

The impact of Furman

There were 589 inmates on death rows in 1972when Furman was decided. Five hundred and fivehad been sentenced to death for murder, 80 forrape, and four for armed robbery. Their sentenceswere reduced to life imprisonment.

The states paroled 322 of the 589. Of theparolees, 75 later were returned to prison fortechnical parole violations of the conditions oftheir parole or minor crimes, 32 committed moreserious crimes, and five committed murder. JoanM. Cheever, BACK FROM THE DEAD (2006).Approximately 250 of the parolees were still alivewhen Cheever began her book; she interviewedhalf of them.

William Henry Furman was paroled in 1984. Hewas arrested for burglaries in 2004, 2005 and2006. On October 4, 2006, Furman age 64, pleadedguilty to burglary and was sentenced to 20 years inprison.

Thirty-five states promptly redrafted their deathpenalty statutes to address the concerns expressedby the Justices in the majority in Furman about thearbitrary application of the death penalty andresumed having capital trials. The Supreme Courtreviewed the statutes of five of those states in1976.

Class Two Part One – McGautha-Furman 40 Prof. Bright - Capital Punishment