brien - rethinking marxisism

Upload: olgacanessa

Post on 07-Aug-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    1/16

    This article was downloaded by: [88.8.89.195]On: 29 October 2014, At: 02:38Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH,UK

    Rethinking Marxism: A Journal

    of Economics, Culture & SocietyPublication details, including instructions for authors

    and subscription information:

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rrmx20

    Rethinking Marx and the

    SpiritualKevin M. Brien

    Published online: 02 Dec 2008.

    To cite this article: Kevin M. Brien (2009) Rethinking Marx and the Spiritual,Rethinking Marxism: A Journal of Economics, Culture & Society, 21:1, 103-116, DOI:

    10.1080/08935690802542473

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08935690802542473

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all theinformation (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform.However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make norepresentations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, orsuitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressedin this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not theviews of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content shouldnot be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sourcesof information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions,

    claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilitieswhatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connectionwith, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes.Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rrmx20http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08935690802542473http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/08935690802542473http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rrmx20

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    2/16

    forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

    http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    3/16

    Rethinking Marx and the Spiritual

    Kevin M. Brien

    dedicated to Robert S. Cohen

    This essay explores the ‘‘the spiritual’’ in Marx’s thought and, in so doing, interpretsthat thought as an integral whole. A metalevel characterization of the spiritual,

    oriented toward a broad spectrum of specific modes of the spiritual, is given. Various

    citations from Marx’s texts open up, in a preliminary way, a vista on a humanistic

    Marxist mode of the spiritual. Feuerbach’s views on religion are examined, followed 

    by Marx’s critical appropriation of them, that construes religion as an alienated form

    of the spiritual that tears it away from its this-worldly home in the secular domain.

     An analysis of Marx’s religion in ‘‘the opium of the people’’ passage is given */with

    special concern for the meanings of ‘‘imaginary flowers’’ and the ‘‘living flower.’’ The

    essay argues that implicit in this passage is Marx’s recognition of an array of 

     fundamental existential needs that all people have. Finally, an exposition of how 

    each of these needs would be manifested in the specific mode of the spiritual at play in Marx’s thought concretely brings it into focus.

    Key Words:   Ludwig Feuerbach, Karl Marx, Religion

    My explorations concerning Marx and ‘‘the spiritual’’ in this essay presuppose that

    there is not  a sharp conceptual break between the early and late Marx. The argument

    that could plausibly establish such a case is much too long and complex to be given

    here but, in my judgment, the strongest case for holding that Marx’s life work actually

    is an integral whole involves bringing into play Marx’s mature method of dialectical

    explanation that moves from the abstract to the concrete  to show the interconnec-

    tion between the early and late Marx.1 In what follows I adapt this method to my

    explorations of the spiritual in Marx.

    To orient my readers let me give the following characterization of the ‘‘spiritual’’

    at a metalevel that abstracts from the specific contents of any particular mode of the

    spiritual. At such a level I project the spiritual as that  domain of the human psyche

    having to do with the lived experience of existential meaning and value, of wholeness

    and love, of creative agency, and of interconnection with other humans, nature, and

    reality at large. I interpret this formulation as being intentionally oriented toward a

    ISSN 0893-5696 print/1475-8059 online/09/010103-14

    – 2009 Association for Economic and Social Analysis

    DOI: 10.1080/08935690802542473

    1. For those interested, I refer them to my book where I present a sustained case (Brien 2006).

    RETHINKING MARXISM VOLUME 21 NUMBER 1 (JANUARY 2009)

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    4/16

    very wide spectrum of specific modes of the spiritual that could be elaborated on

    more concrete levels of analysis.

    Furthermore, I hold that the specific modes of the spiritual at one end of such a

    spectrum would mostly be oriented toward  ‘‘inner realms’’ that have little to do witheveryday outward practice, while at the other end of the spectrum would be modes of

    the spiritual having the potential of fully suffusing everyday human practice in the

    world. In my view, the degree to which any specific mode of the spiritual would

    suffuse ordinary everyday practice in the world (or fail to do so, as the case may be)

    would depend entirely on the specific mode considered. It will come out in what

    follows that the mode of the spiritual I associate with Marx is one that can fully

    suffuse everyday human practice.

    My discussion begins on quite an abstract level, where I explain Marx’s distinction

    between ‘‘spiritual forces’’ and the ‘‘religious form’’ they so often assume. Moving to

    a less abstract level, I cite pasages where Marx uses phrases like  ‘‘spiritual life’’ (das

     geistege Leben) that suggestively point toward his own positive notion of   ‘‘the

    spiritual.’’   Moving to a still less abstract level, I turn to a brief exploration of

    Feuerbach’s view of religion, which influenced Marx so significantly. In this context I

    draw from Marx’s  ‘‘Theses on Feuerbach’’  to clarify the specific way Marx disagreed

    with Feuerbach’s view of religious self-alienation. I argue that Marx interprets the

    alienation of   ‘‘spiritual forces,’’   that for him have their proper home within the

    secular basis, in terms of the   secular basis becoming alienated from itself;  and that

    he also points to the practical necessity of transforming the secular basis in a way that

    involves   ‘‘spiritualizing’’   the secular basis itself. I next discuss the   ‘‘opium of the

    people’’  passage where Marx speaks of religion as  ‘‘people’s illusory happiness’’  and

    holds that criticism of religion ‘‘has plucked the imaginary flowers from the chain   . . .

    [so that people] will throw it off and pluck the living flower’’ (1997, 250). Going to an

    even less abstract level, I give an exposition of what Marx likely means by  ‘‘imaginary

    flowers’’  and the  ‘‘living flower,’’  arguing that these metaphors point toward Marx’s

    own positive understanding of the spiritual.

    Following this I argue that implicit in the  ‘‘opium of the people’’  passage is Marx’s

    recognition of an array of fundamental needs all people have, which I interpret as

    existential needs. On a still more concrete level, I specify the particular way in whicheach of these needs would be manifested in the specific mode of the spiritual at play

    in Marx’s philosophical paradigm. However, I do not mean to imply the spiritual can be

    reduced to such needs, especially when seen abstractly. Rather, I construe Marx’s

    positive notion of the spiritual in terms of the specific concrete form these needs

    should take as they suffuse associated modes of human practice and are dialectically

    shaped by such practice. Finally I argue that suffusing a revolutionary praxis with such

    a this-worldly mode of the spiritual would, on a wide-enough scale, have some real

    hope of transforming the secular basis in the direction of social justice and a more

    human future.Before proceeding, however, a rationale for addressing the spiritual in connection

    with Marx is appropriate. Why is it important? What is the benefit? In my view, a

    pandemic crisis of the human person pervades much of planet earth: a crisis of the

    human spirit manifesting itself in so many diverse ways, a spiritual crisis! Not

    altogether a new crisis, though, for Nietzsche explored the existential breakdown of

    104 BRIEN

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    5/16

    traditional Western modes of the spiritual (but without addressing the role of

    capitalism in generating this breakdown) and codified it in his projection of the

    ‘‘advent of nihilism.’’   Unfortunately, the crisis of the human person has greatly

    intensified in many ways and spread very widely in the past hundred years, largely dueto the ongoing impact of capitalist systems on peoples throughout the world. In the

    United States itself, the capitalist system has so warped the human psyche that a

    looming meaninglessness now hangs over much of the country. Yes, it is blunted and

    masked somewhat by the torrential gush of consumer goods and services that the

    system spews out to mollify the people */the contemporary opiate for many of the

    people. But the system also systematically generates increasing alienation as a very

    significant dimension of its gross national product. The notion of the spiritual that I

    associate with humanistic Marxism has the potential not only to address the

    intensifying crisis of the human person, but also to help in generating a revolutionary

    agency that could transfigure the system. So far as I am aware, this paper constitutes

    a creative breakthrough in thinking about the spiritual in relation to Marx.

    The Spiritual in Marx

    What meanings do the terms   ‘‘religion’’  and   ‘‘the spiritual’’  have for Marx? Do they

    have basically the same meaning, or is there a fundamental difference for him

    between his notion of religion and his notion of the spiritual? Here let me first refer to

    a section of  Capital  where Marx is talking about the historical necessity of material

    production developing through an alienated and antagonistic transitional phase in

    which the human subject is transformed into an object. In this connection he writes,

    ‘‘It is necessary [for material production] to go through this antagonistic form, just as

    it is necessary at first to give man’s spiritual forces  [die geistigen Krä   fte] a religious

    form by erecting them into autonomous power over against him’’   (1977, 509;

    emphasis added). It seems quite clear that Marx is here making a distinction between

    the ‘‘spiritual forces’’ of human beings, on the one hand, and what he takes to be the

    alienated   ‘‘religious form’’   that these forces can have when they involve the

    projection of an  ‘‘independent realm in the clouds’’  from which they seem to standover human beings as an alien and autonomous power. In using the phrase  ‘‘religious

    form’’   in this way, Marx seems to be suggesting that religion itself, in the sense in

    which he means it, carries with it the connotation of an associated alienation of the

    spiritual forces of the human being and of the spiritual dimension itself. What positive

    view of the spiritual might Marx embrace, then, and what would constitute an

    unalienated expression of the spiritual forces for him?

    To open some conceptual space, let me first say that there is no philosophically

    justifiable reason to rigidly limit the term ‘‘spiritual’’ to the relatively narrow ways it

    is often used in traditional Western settings *

    /especially ways that see spirituality andthe spiritual as necessarily involving beliefs in a creator god, a soul, and a

    supernatural world. I contend that the general term   ‘‘spiritual’’   must be seen as

    orienting one to a very wide spectrum of specific modes of the spiritual that manifest

    ‘‘family resemblances’’ with one another, rather than some common quality or set of

    qualities that can be captured via an abstract universal or some Platonic-like essence

    MARX AND THE SPIRITUAL 105

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    6/16

    (Wittgenstein 1953, sec. 67). I mean a spectrum that includes not only theist and

    dualist modes, but also nontheist, nondualist, naturalist, animist, and even atheistic

    modes of the spiritual.

    Considering the following passages, let us reflect upon what Marx himself mightmean by   ‘‘the spiritual’’   and whether he embraces some positive notion of the

    spiritual. Here, though, it is important to note a caveat concerning the term

    ‘‘spiritual’’ (whether in English translation or in the original German). The term itself

    does not really matter for a rose by any other name is still a rose. I take the term

    ‘‘spiritual’’   to abstractly connote a domain of the psyche having to do with certain

    sorts of lived experience, and I take the passages that follow as Marx’s   pointers

    toward   his way of concretely elaborating the   particular mode of the spiritual   he

    embraces. So then, some of Marx’s formulations.

    Man lives by nature. This means that nature is his body with which he mustremain in perpetual process in order not to die. That the physical and

    spiritual life  [das geistige Leben] of man is tied up with nature is another

    way of saying that nature is linked to itself, for man is a part of nature.

    (1997, 293; emphasis altered)

    [Alienated labor] alienates his  spiritual nature   [sein geistiges Wesen], hishuman essence, from his own body and likewise from nature outside him.

    (295; emphasis altered)

    For not only the five senses but also the so-called   spiritual   [die geistigen

    Sinne] and moral  senses   (will, love, etc.), in a word, human sense and the

    humanity of the senses come into being only through the existence of their

    object through nature humanized. (309; emphasis altered)

    These passages make explicit references to  ‘‘spiritual life,’’ ‘‘spiritual nature,’’  and

    ‘‘spiritual senses,’’  and they do so without any implication for Marx that spirituality

    and religion are synonymous or that his use of the term  ‘‘spiritual’’  in these contexts

    suggests anything like a creator god, a soul substance, or a supernatural world.

    Moreover, far from being a rejection of the spiritual, these passages seem to point towhat Marx believes to be an unalienated expression of this very dimension. To develop

    this, let me next explore some of the views of Ludwig Feuerbach who had such a

    significant influence on Marx, especially concerning religion.

    In   The Essence of Christianity,   Feuerbach argues that the notion of God is an

    external projection of man’s inner nature, and that the humanly projected aspects of

    God correspond to human needs. According to his account of the origin of belief in a

    transcendent God, our early Judaeo-Christian forebears noticed in themselves certain

    qualities that they regarded as very special */qualities like reason, will, and love.

    What then is the nature of man, of which he is conscious, or what constitutesthe specific distinction, the proper humanity of man? Reason, Will,

    Affection. To a complete man belong the power of thought, the power of

    will, the power of affection. The power of thought is the light of the

    intellect, the power of will is the energy of character, the power of affection

    is love   . . .  Reason, Will, Love, are not powers which man possesses, for he is

    106 BRIEN

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    7/16

    nothing without them,   he is what he is only by them;   they are the

    constituent elements of his nature. (Feuerbach 1957, 3; emphasis added)

    As Feuerbach sees things, our early forebears abstracted these qualities in their

    imagination from their own situation and, after removing in thought the limitationssuch qualities had in their own case, they projected the notion of an all-knowing

    reason, an all-powerful will, and an infinite love. They then projected a metaphysical

    subject to which they attached these projected qualities, and the name they gave to

    the resulting complex made in their own image was  ‘‘God.’’ The various attributes of

    this   ‘‘divine being’’   were all attributes of human beings, but with the human

    attributes   ‘‘purified’’  and their limitations transcended. Other projected attributes

    included God   ‘‘as a being of the understanding’’   and   ‘‘as a moral being’’   (33  /49).

    Moreover, for Feuerbach all these attributes corresponded to various needs in human

    nature. All this is the   ‘‘true or anthropological essence of religion’’   for Feuerbach:‘‘The divine being is nothing else than the human being, or rather, the human nature

    purified, freed from the limits of the individual man, made objective */i.e.,

    contemplated and revered as another, a distinct being. All the attributes of the

    divine nature are, therefore, attributes of the human nature’’  (14).

    Feuerbach also construes God as the alienated personification of the powers of

    human beings standing over them as an external threatening force: their own

    ‘‘rejected nature’’ now purified, objectified, hovering over them in a menacing way,

    calling for submission, and promising retribution if submission is not forthcoming. ‘‘As

    the action of the arteries drives the blood into the extremities, and the action of theveins brings it back again, as life in general consists in a perpetual systole and

    diastole; so it is in religion. In the religious systole man propels his own nature from

    himself, he throws it outward; in the religious diastole he receives the rejected

    nature into his heart again’’   (31). Feuerbach’s remedy for this alienated situation

    goes something like this. Recognize that humans have created God in their own

    image; do away with the imaginary metaphysical subject that humans have

    projected; draw back into the human context the powers that they had attached

    to this metaphysical subject; recognize and embrace the limited nature of these

    powers in the human context; and then redefine ‘‘God’’ in reference to the context of

    human relations. Consider, for example, Feuerbach’s attitude toward God and Love.

    Who then is our Saviour and Redeemer? God or Love? Love; for God as God

    has not saved us, but Love, which transcends the difference between the

    divine and human personality. As god has renounced himself out of love, so

    we, out of love, should renounce God; for if we do not sacrifice God to love,

    we sacrifice love to God, and in spite of the predicate of love, we have the

    God */the evil being */of religious fanaticism. (53)

    For Feuerbach, God is not an ontologically real, transcendent being; rather, God is the

    love that is at play in human relations when these relations are really human.Moreover, for him the I-Thou relationship is confined exclusively to the human

    community so he redefines   ‘‘God’’   as something like the unity of I and Thou, you

    flowing into me and me flowing back into you. Moreover, what is really special,

    sacred, and holy for him   is love itself:   not love as an abstract ideal, but love as a

    concrete reality. This is what is sabotaged when God is made into a transcendent,

    MARX AND THE SPIRITUAL 107

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    8/16

    threatening force standing over humans. And this, for him, is the vital heart of

    Christianity, hence Feuerbach’s paradoxical stance that atheism is the essence of

    Christianity.

    Turning back to Marx, I draw from his famous ‘‘Theses on Feuerbach’’  for some ofhis critical stances on positions that Feuerbach adopted. Marx writes:

    Feuerbach starts out from the fact of religious self-alienation, the duplica-

    tion of the world into a religious and secular world. His work consists in

    resolving the religious world into its secular basis. But the fact that   thesecular basis becomes separate from itself   and establishes an independent

    realm in the clouds   can only be explained by the cleavage and self-

    contradictoriness of the secular basis.   Thus  the latter  must itself be both

    understood in its contradiction and   revolutionized in practice. (1997, 401;

    emphasis added)

    Marx would fully agree with Feuerbach that religious self-alienation involves the

    duplication of the world into an otherworldly religious world and a this-worldly

    secular world. Presumably Marx also would agree that the humanly projected

    attributes of God are linked to human needs that find some kind of compensatory

    fulfillment in the belief in an imaginary divine being. But Marx does  not  agree with

    Feuerbach that alienation is caused  by religious self-alienation. Rather, religious self-

    alienation for Marx is a symptom of concrete, historically conditioned circumstances

    in which human beings are enmeshed in very secular class conflicts that cause human

    beings to be alienated from one another.Here let’s look carefully at Marx’s formulation from the above citation:   ‘‘the

    secular basis becomes separate from itself and establishes an independent realm in

    the clouds.’’  What is it  within  the secular basis that could possibly become separate

    from itself (i.e., the secular basis) and establish an independent realm in the clouds?

    There seems to me to be only one plausible answer to this question: namely, that the

    spiritual dimension of human being, as Marx understands this dimension, is in reality a

    dimension of the secular basis. However, this dimension undergoes an alienated

    orientation away from the secular basis, which is its ontologically real home, and

    toward an imagined otherworldly reality that is projected by the religious imagina-tion.

    Remember that Marx sees the human being as a natural being. Thus, ontologically

    speaking, man is  a secular being for Marx: a this-worldly being interacting with other

    human beings and with the nonhuman natural world. The alienated orientation of the

    spiritual dimension away from the secular basis presumably occurs when the secular

    basis is so riven with class, ethnic, and sectarian conflicts that it cannot fully manifest

    and express itself in an unalienated way   within   the secular basis and therefore

    retreats to an imaginary religious world. Well, then, if Marx can indeed embrace some

    notion of the spiritual, just how is the spiritual dimension to be construed within

    Marx’s philosophical framework? What is its content? I begin by citing the famous

    passage where Marx writes:

    The struggle against religion is   . . .  indirectly the struggle against that world

    whose spiritual aroma is religion.  Religious suffering is the expression of real

    suffering and at the same time the protest against real suffering. Religion is

    108 BRIEN

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    9/16

    the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, as it is the

    spirit of spiritless conditions. It is the  opium of the people. The abolition of

    religion as people’s   illusory    happiness is the demand for their   real

    happiness. The demand to abandon illusions about their condition is a

    demand to abandon a condition which requires illusions  . . .

      Criticism has

    plucked the imaginary flowers from the chain, not so that man will wear the

    chain that is without fantasy or consolation but so that he will throw it off

    and pluck the living flower. (1997, 250)

    Why would Marx speak in such ways if he did not believe that human needs of some

    sort are at play in the human construction of religion? I suggest that at play in these

    striking formulations (and in many others) is an implicit recognition by Marx of an

    array of human needs that are, in his sense of the term, spiritual in character, and

    that call for fulfillment from the very depths of the human being.2 Moreover, I suggest

    it is spiritual needs that are at play in the  ‘‘spiritual forces’’ that assume a  ‘‘religious

    form’’ in historical conditions of a sort that prevent the full, many-sided, unalienated

    expression of human powers. Marx is critical of religion because, in his view, what

    usually counts as religion constitutes merely a compensatory  ‘‘fantastic realization’’

    of spiritual needs that, while giving people some kind of consolation in the context of

    oppressive social conditions, also functions like blinders that prevent people from

    recognizing the real possibility of the unalienated fulfillment of these needs in

    concrete social life.

    Next let’s consider Marx’s formulation that criticism   ‘‘has plucked the imaginary

    flowers from the chain, not so that man will wear the chain that is without fantasy or

    consolation but so that he will throw it off and pluck the living flower.’’ What are the

    imaginary flowers Marx has in mind here, and what is the living flower?

    Above we saw Feuerbach argue that God is  ‘‘human nature purified, freed from the

    limits of the individual man, made objective */i.e., contemplated and revered as

    another, a distinct being.’’   In Feuerbach’s view, our early human forebears, faced

    with all the terrors of existence and aware of such terrors once full self-consciousness

    had developed, projected a divine being with unlimited Reason, Will, and Love, a

    divine being on whom they could depend in the face of the trials and tribulations of

    life and in whom they could find comfort and consolation. What did belief in such adivine being, with all its other associated attributes (a moral being, etc.) and its

    assorted metaphysical attachments (substantial soul, afterlife, divine justice, etc.),

    provide to human beings? Among other things it provided an orienting belief system:

    an orienting perspective within which humans could view themselves and try to

    understand themselves in relation to nature, to other human beings, and to the Divine

    Being of religious belief, and it provided them some kind of value orientation as well,

    some kind of  ‘‘moral’’  guidance.

    Furthermore, however fragile human existence might be, such a belief system

    provided a divine ground on which these special attributes of humankind, now‘‘purified,’’ would stand forever secure against the ravages of time, beasts, and other

    humans. If one’s particular historical circumstances were cruel, unjust, and lacking in

    2. Many formulations with similar import are concentrated in Marx’s early writings (see

    especially Marx 1997, 265  /336).

    MARX AND THE SPIRITUAL 109

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    10/16

    any genuine community, any I-Thou feeling, one could nonetheless be sure of God’s

    love and of having community and interconnection with God. One could also be sure

    that God would in the long run mete out divine justice to all human beings who ever

    lived so that everyone got their just deserts. Furthermore, if one’s individualhistorical and social conditions allowed one no, or very little, opportunity for

    manifesting creative agency, one could nonetheless be sure that the urge to free

    agency would be forever sanctified via God’s all-powerful creative will sustaining all

    of creation in existence without let or hindrance.

    If these are some of the   ‘‘imaginary flowers’’   to which Marx most likely made

    implicit reference, what did he mean by the phrase that the criticism of religion

    would prepare the soil so that one could  ‘‘pluck the living flower’’? What is the living

    flower that Marx means here? I believe that the   ‘‘living flower’’  Marx had first and

    foremost in mind is what he calls  ‘‘free conscious activity,’’ which he takes to be  ‘‘the

    species character of human beings’’  (1997, 294). Importantly, such activity must be

    construed not simply as   ‘‘inner consciousness,’’   but rather, as the dialectical

    interface between consciousness and human practice.

    There are many formulations throughout Marx’s work that point toward the same

    ‘‘living flower.’’  Consider these, for example.

    [Free activity is] the creative manifestation of life arising from the free

    development of all abilities, of the   ‘whole fellow’. (Marx and Engels 1968,

    246)

    [Socialism is] a higher form of society, a society in which the full and freedevelopment of every individual forms the ruling principle. (Marx 1967,

    2:592)

    Free individuality   . . .  is founded on the universal development of individuals.

    (1972, 67)

    The rich man [in a socialist context] is simultaneously one who   needs   a

    totality of human manifestations of life and in whom his own realization

    exists as inner necessity, as  need . (1997, 312)

    If ‘‘free conscious activity’’ is the primary  ‘‘living flower’’  Marx had in mind when hespoke of plucking the living flower, what, then, about other, associated   ‘‘living

    flowers’’ */or perhaps various aspects of the primary living flower? Let me point to

    what I believe are perhaps the most significant of these other living flowers: (a)

    genuine community with other people, as opposed to various sorts of segmental

    relations to others */what Marx called   ‘‘the illusory community in which individuals

    have come together up till now’’ (1997, 457); (b) the felt need to be related to other

    human beings as a human being; (c) a many-sided, all-round development of one’s

    potentials; (d ) experiencing the development of one’s energies as an end in itself; (e)

    the experience of joy and spontaneity in one’s practice; and ( f ) an experience ofwholeness. The brief excerpts from Marx’s text that follow are but a few sample

    formulations of Marx’s thoughts along these lines, taken from a pool of countless

    companion formulations one might cull from Marx’s writings. (Allow me to continue

    with the flower metaphor.) If one takes the above factors (a) through ( f ) as

    symbolizing the stems of flowers, and then takes the citations from Marx below as

    110 BRIEN

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    11/16

    symbolizing the blossoms of these flowers, one might then take the whole flowers

    from stem to blossom as symbolizing Marx’s notion of a humanized and spiritualized 

    secularism.

    Only in community do the means exist for every individual to cultivate his

    talents in all directions. Only in the community is personal freedom possible.

    (1997, 457)

    In this relationship [of man to woman] is also apparent the extent to which

    man’s  need  has become  human,  thus the extent to which the  other  human

    being, as human being, has become a need for him, the extent to which he in

    his most individual existence is at the same time a social being. (303)

    Man appropriates to himself his manifold essence in an all-sided way, thus as

    a whole man. Every one of his   human   relations to the world *

    /seeing,hearing, smelling, tasting, feeling, thinking, perceiving, sensing, wishing,

    acting, loving */in short all the organs of his individuality   . . .   are an

    appropriation of the object in their  objective   relation or their  relation   to

    it. (307)

    Beyond it [the realm of necessity] begins that development of human energy

    which is an end in itself, the true realm of freedom, which, however, can

    blossom forth only with the realm of necessity as its basis. (1967, 3:820)

    Now that I have given some sense of what I consider Marx to mean by   ‘‘imaginary

    flowers’’   and   ‘‘living flower,’’   I want to suggest that these metaphors point toward

    Marx’s recommended way of addressing fundamental spiritual needs  that all humans

    have, and I wish to refer to such needs as  existential needs. The existential needs I

    have in mind include the following: the need for some kind of orienting world-view,

    the need for some kind of value perspective to guide one’s actions, the need for

    existential meaning, the need for interconnection with nature, the need for

    community with others, the need for creative expression of potentials, and the need

    for wholeness.

    But why call these existential needs? Why not just psychological needs? I respond

    that such needs are a special class of psychic needs associated with the peculiarexistential situation of human beings that is, in turn, based on the particular kind of

    biological organisms humans happen to be. Humans are the sort of biological

    organisms whose distinctively human physical and mental practices are  not  narrowly

    programmed by determinate instincts. Rather, humans have reflective self-con-

    sciousness and the underlying biological potential for   ‘‘making themselves’’   in an

    enormously vast spectrum of different ways of being human, all associated with

    different modes of the spiritual, depending on the concrete historical conditions

    which obtain in a given situation at a given time. This means that the   spiritual

    dimension is itself historically variable   in some important ways (see Brien 1996,222  /59).

    But, then, how to understand  the particular form of the spiritual,   the particular

    manifestation of the spiritual forces, that humanistic Marxism would associate with

    the sort of revolutionary practice that would have some real possibility of

    revolutionizing the secular basis, and of cultivating a cultural transition in the

    MARX AND THE SPIRITUAL 111

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    12/16

    direction of a genuine, humanistic socialism? Inasmuch as I view the spiritual as the

    domain of the psyche having to do with the  lived experience of the various existential

    needs indicated above, I go on now to present a sketch of some of the main contours

    of a humanistic-Marxist spiritual mode in accordance with Marx’s own recommendedway of addressing the various existential needs he distinguished. It will be seen that

    this mode of the spiritual has the potential of   fully suffusing everyday human

     practice in the world   for this mode of the spiritual cannot be reduced to   ‘‘inner

    consciousness,’’ but must be interpreted as the dialectical interface between human

    activity and consciousness. I now turn to a sketch of the specific ways of addressing

    the various existential needs that, in Marx’s view, would not be alienated. I ask my

    readers to bear in mind, though, that since such needs are not discrete atomic needs,

    there will necessarily be some overlaps in the vignettes that follow.

    The existential needs for some kind of   orienting world-view   and for   inter-

    connection with nature   would be expressed in a humanistic-Marxist spiritual mode

    via an experiential recognition that the human being is a being of nature

    interacting with other human beings and with nature,   ‘‘not an abstract being

    squatting outside the world’’   (Marx 1997, 250) but essentially a natural being

    immersed in the world. By acting in and upon the natural and social environments

    in specific ways, human beings make themselves in specific ways and constitute

    their powers as real objective powers. Thus, there are ontological bonds among

    human subjects as well as between them and the natural world. Moreover,

    naturally given resources are shaped by human beings into a vast multiplicity of

    objects, which become thereby the repositories of human powers and energies. In

    the spiritual mode under discussion, all these ontological interconnections would

    be experienced in ways that are life affirming rather than life negating. Thus,

    individuals interrelating with one another via the mediation of objects would be

    respectful of them as embodiments of the energies of social individuals   (see Marx

    1967, 1:41  /6; 1997, 325  /7), and would reciprocally affirm each other as they

    interrelate (see Marx 1997, 281).

    For Marx, the existential need for community with others  would be manifest in an

    active interrelation between people such that there is an experiential recognition of

    human individuals as social individuals *

    /both the recognition that individuals becomethe particular kind of social individuals they are by virtue of the particular ways they

    interact with each other and the recognition that the most positive development of

    human individuals is dynamically bound up with the most positive development of

    their social relationships (see Marx 1997, 457). Such a manifestation of the need for

    community does not see the connection with others as a hindrance to individual

    development, but rather, as a pathway toward full human development. It is a need

    for reciprocal, many-sided, life-affirming relations on the part of individuals with

    many-sided, life-affirming counterparts in order that everyone may become fully

    human.In a humanistic-Marxist practice, the existential need for  creative expression of 

     potentials  would be manifested in a many-sided, freely flowing, creative unfolding

    of individual powers. This, of course, is not to be understood as anything like the

    typical egotism of Western culture for it is qualified by the practical recognition of

    oneself and others as social individuals and by the recognition that the freedom of

    112 BRIEN

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    13/16

    each is bound up with the freedom of all. Thus the many-sided, creative unfolding

    of individual powers is an unfolding that does not seek to dominate the other, but

    does not let itself be dominated by the other, either. Nor is Marx’s affirmation of

    individual powers to be understood as an affirmation of the kind of possessiveindividualism that has been so dominant for so long */with all its emphasis on

    having and on possessing (money, things, property, etc.). Marx’s concern is not

    with having much, but with being much (see Marx 1997, 307  /9).

    The existential need for meaning would be addressed by adopting modes of

    activity that are experienced as meaningful rather than as an onerous means to

    some end that is to be realized by the activity */that is, some wished-for goal that

    lies outside the activity itself. Such activity is experienced as an end in itself,

    even if it may also be activity that is a means to something in fact (see Marx 1997,

    294  

    /5). Thus it is experienced as intrinsically meaningful, as spontaneouslycreative, and as joyful. As Marx puts it, such activity is   ‘‘a free manifestation

    of life and an enjoyment of life’’   (281). The need for meaning is also manifested

    and concretely expressed in direct personal relations when people relate to each

    other as whole human beings and treat each other as ends. Marx highlights the

    existential importance of such meaningful relations among people when he writes,

    ‘‘Not only the wealth but also the poverty of man equally acquire */under the

    premise of socialism */a human and thus social meaning. It is the passive bond

    which lets man experience the greatest wealth, the other human being, as need’’

    (312).Some of the ways a humanistic-Marxist spiritual awareness would address the

    existential   need for wholeness  have already been suggested in the remarks above

    concerning the need for a totality of human manifestations of life and a many-

    sided, all-round development. But it would also be manifested in the need for a

    transformation of the various dimensions of the human psyche */cognition,

    conation, sensuousness, intuition, sensation */as they obtain in alienated modes

    of consciousness, and their subsequent harmonious integration in more holistic

    modes (308  /10). It also includes the need to experientially integrate the spiritual

    with nature in a holistic way, and to overcome the alienated separation of thespiritual dimension from the body that has been characteristic of much of the

    Western cultural tradition (295).

    The existential need for some kind of   value perspective   would be manifested in

    a humanistic-Marxist practice that is committed to freely and fully developing

    one’s potential. This connotes an active freedom that involves a need for a many-

    sided creative activity that constitutes a totality of human manifestations of life,

    including, of course, the need to be related to the other as a whole human being

    in concrete practice. In such activity one treats others, and oneself also, as whole

    human beings, a practice that involves the recognition that the fully developedfreedom of each is tied up with the fully developed freedom of all. A corollary of

    this is   ‘‘the categorical imperative to overthrow all conditions   in which man is a

    degraded, enslaved, contemptible, [exploited, dehumanized] being’’   (257  /8). Thus,

    it is the sort of activity that does not imply or involve the denial or repression of

    the other as it affirms itself.

    MARX AND THE SPIRITUAL 113

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    14/16

    Conclusion

    Following this sketch, I now address apprehensions that might be felt by those who

    are uncomfortable with the term   ‘‘spiritual’’   in connection with Marx. Earlier Imentioned the strong association the term   ‘‘spiritual’’   has with theistic religion in

    Western cultures, but I brought out that there is not an exclusive association of the

    term  ‘‘spiritual’’ with theism and that Marx used the term  ‘‘spiritual’’  many times in

    his earlier writings in very positive ways, with no connotation of any otherworldly

    reality. It is true that Marx used the term   ‘‘spiritual’’   much less often in his later

    writings than he did earlier, but I suggest that Marx had reasons for this that for him

    were compelling. Here I have in mind positions that Marx and Engels vehemently

    criticized in The German Ideology, which used the term  ‘‘spirit’’ and  ‘‘spiritual’’ with

    Hegelian connotations from which Marx and Engels wanted to dissociate themselves(Marx and Engels 1968, 157  /74). I contend, however, that Marx never dropped the

    concept  of the spiritual at play in his early writings, even though he used the term

    ‘‘spiritual’’   [ geistige] much less frequently.

    Let me also mention another consideration that might make it easier to embrace

    the secularized form of the spiritual I have outlined above in association with Marx. In

    view of the strong association of the term   ‘‘spiritual’’   with theistic religions in

    Western cultures and a consequent reluctance to associate the term  ‘‘spiritual’’ with

    atheism,   it might be well to take the following cue from Marx, when he says that

    ‘‘atheism no longer makes sense.’’

     Atheism as the denial of this unreality [an alien divine being beyond man and

    nature] no longer makes sense because it is a  negation of God   and through

    this negation asserts the  existence of man. But socialism as such no longer

    needs such mediation. It begins with the sensuous perception, theoretically and practically,  of man and nature as   essential beings. It is man’s  positive

    self-consciousness,   no longer attained through the overcoming of religion.

    (1997, 314)

    I believe it is culturally important for our time not only to go beyond traditional

    interpretations of theism, and also beyond atheism, but even beyond secularhumanism as it is commonly understood and to adopt what might be called a

    spiritualized and humanized secularism  for which the question of atheism no longer

    arises in an existential way. The solution to the problem that   ‘‘the secular basis

    becomes separate from itself and establishes an independent realm in the clouds’’ is,

    for Marx, not a complete suppression of the spiritual (Marx 1997, 401), but rather, a

    revolutionary practice that successfully transforms the secular basis so that the

    spiritual dimension can be fulfilled in a this-worldly way that does not require

    recourse to an imaginary being.

    Let us remember that, in Marx’s view, one of the most essential practicalprerequisites for a successful transition to genuine socialism is   ‘‘the formation of a

    revolutionary mass   . . .  a mass which revolts not only against particular conditions of

    the prevailing society but against the prevailing  ‘production of life’  itself, the  ‘total

    activity’ on which it was based’’ (432). But such a revolutionary mass doesn’t drop out

    of the sky like a   deus ex machina.   Rather, it comes to be on the basis of a new

    114 BRIEN

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    15/16

    practice */a new praxis   guided by right understanding of the real possibilities of a

    humanistic socialism, and committed to right effort to cultivate a transition to such a

    socialism. As Marx says, it is necessary  ‘‘to expose the old world to full daylight and to

    shape the new along positive lines’’ (211). In order for this to happen, it is necessaryfor theory to grip the masses:  ‘‘The weapon of criticism obviously cannot replace the

    criticism of weapons. Material force must be overthrown by material force. But

    theory also becomes a material force once it has gripped the masses. Theory is

    capable of gripping the masses when it demonstrates   ad hominem, and it

    demonstrates ad hominem  when it becomes radical. To be radical is to grasp things

    by the root’’  (257).

    I suggest that, for Marx, the   root of the spiritual   is not to be found in some

    otherworldly reality. Rather, it is to be found in this world. Our era is one of those

    momentous historical junctures during which the shifting tectonic plates of world

    history can induce enormous and unpredictable changes. To emerge from this

    historical juncture without degenerating into something like international fascism,

    I believe it is practically imperative for the peoples of our era to embrace the spiritual

    anew and   reclaim   it from the clutches of authoritarian, dogmatic, and fanatic

    fundamentalist theists, and most especially from extremist and violent religious

    fundamentalists */whether Christian, Hindu, Muslim, Jewish, or whatever.

    Our era represents the time to radically transform the secular basis. Moreover, I

    believe a growing understanding of how humanistic Marxism can accommodate the

    spiritual dimension could go a long way toward nurturing such a development,

    especially in the case of that vast number of people for whom traditional modes of

    the spiritual are not viable. Our era is the time to suffuse a revolutionary praxis with a

    this-worldly mode of the spiritual that has some real hope of transforming the secular

    basis in the direction of social justice as all of humanity faces the daunting crises that

    loom throughout planet earth. Our era is the time to  humanize the spiritual, and to

    spiritualize the secular. Our era is the time for the peoples of the world to unite! Let

    the living flowers bloom!

     Acknowledgments

    I want to gratefully acknowledge Jacinda Swanson and Cecilia Rio for their very 

    helpful criticisms of earlier drafts of this paper.

    References

    Brien, K. M. 1996. Marx and the spiritual dimension.  Topoi: An International Review of 

    Philosophy  15: 211  /23.

     */

     */ *

    /. 2006.  Marx, reason, and the art of freedom. 2d ed. Amherst, N.Y.: HumanityBooks.

     */ */ */. 2007. Marx’s dialectical-empirical method of explanation.   Utopı́a y Praxis

    Latinoamericana 39: 9  /32.

    Feuerbach, L. 1957. The essence of Christianity. Trans. G. Eliot. New York: Harper and

    Brothers.

    MARX AND THE SPIRITUAL 115

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4

  • 8/20/2019 Brien - Rethinking Marxisism

    16/16

    Marx, K. 1967.  Capital.  3 vols. Ed. F. Engels. New York: International Publishers.

     */ */ */. 1972.  The Grundrisse.  Trans. and ed. D. McLellan. New York: Harper and Row.

     */ */ */. 1973.  Grundrisse.  Trans. M. Nicolaus. Middlesex: Penguin.

     */ */ */. 1977.   Karl Marx: Selected writings.   Ed. D. McLellan. New York: Oxford

    University Press.

     */ */ */. 1997.  Writings of the young Marx on philosophy and society.  Trans. and ed. L.

    Easton and K. Guddat. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Marx, K., and F. Engels. 1968.   The German ideology . Trans. and ed. S. Ryazanskaya.

    Moscow: Progress.

    Wittgenstein, L. 1953.  Philosophical investigations. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. New

    York: Macmillan.

    116 BRIEN

       D

      o  w  n   l  o  a   d  e   d   b  y   [   8   8 .   8 .   8

       9 .   1

       9   5

       ]  a   t   0   2  :   3   8   2   9   O  c   t  o   b  e  r   2   0   1   4