bj19_jay

Upload: rigoberto-zm

Post on 14-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/29/2019 BJ19_Jay

    1/7

    44 | The Berlin Journal | Number Nineteen | Fall 2010

    imAgeCourtesyoftheArtist

    ouTcasT eyesThe medieval philosophy of nominalism has rippled through the centuries and into

    our ways of making meaning out of what we see.

    By Martin Jay

    dan GluiBizzi, jr.,i-lines[B], 2009, waterColor on paper, 20 x 16 inChes

  • 7/29/2019 BJ19_Jay

    2/7

    Fall 2010 | Number Nineteen | The Berlin Journal|45

    Ever since its inv ention, in

    the 1830s, photography has posed a

    daunting challenge to the legion of

    theorists who have sought to make sense

    of its revolutionary implications. Variously

    a tool of scientic inquiry, artistic cre-

    ation, and social memory, it has exploded

    conventional wisdom about visual experi-

    ence, testing our sense of what an image

    is, how mimetic representation duplicates

    the world, and even how time itself can be

    frozen in a perpetual instant or captured in

    the ow of its movement. With the recent

    development of digital technologies, which

    seem to undermine the photographs func-

    tion as a reliable recorder of an actual event

    or object in the world, many of these issues

    have been raised anew with no consensus

    yet arriv ing about their possible resolution.

    Sometimes it is useful to return to past

    moments in the history of thought to helpus deal with present questions. In the case

    of photography, one possible yet rareed

    resource is a tradition that emerged in

    medieval philosophy and that has had a lin-

    gering impact ever since: Nominalism.

    Beginning with the fourteenth-century

    Franciscan friar William of Ockham,

    whose celebrated razor was wielded to cut

    away imagined entities unnecessary to

    explain the world of exper ience, nominal-

    ism has been understood as promoting

    a principle of parsimony or economy. It

    sought to purify philosophy, in particular

    the reigning Scholastic orthodoxy of the

    medieval Church, of its excessive conceptu-

    al baggage, freeing it to confront the world

    as it existed in all its motley particularity.

    The nominalists favorite target was

    the alleged existence of supra-individual

    universals abstractions wrongly taken

    to be more real than the particulars that

    embodied them. Because it did so, nomi-

    nalism has been understood as deeply

    anti-realist in its hostility to the essentialist

    Aristotelian ontology of the Scholastic tra-dition. For abstract universals it substituted

    the conventionalist linguistic name that we

    mere humans give to groupings of individ-

    ual entities in the world that seem to share

    attributes chairs, birds, oceans thus

    earning the designation of nominalism,

    from the Latin word for name, nomen.

    Ridding the mental universe of unnec-

    essary real universals and abstract objects,

    however, could open the door for some-

    thing else. For when doubts about knowl-

    edge or the sufciency of human reason

    were put forward, the way was opened for

    faith alone to be the sole source of certainty.

    We may lack the means to sense or know

    real universals or abstract objects, but we

    can still believe that they exist. For Ockham,

    revelation was the only access we have to

    such entities as the souls immortality or

    the inherent attributes of God, such as His

    unfettered sovereign will.

    When it came to mundane matters,

    nominalism cleared the way for a less exalt-

    ed source than Gods will. Nominalism

    says the categories we bestow upon the

    world are the product of human invention,

    an assumption which led to the self-asser-

    tion of the species in the face of a world

    that no longer could be read as a legible text

    lled with meanings written by God and

    available to human understanding the so-

    called Great Chain of Being. The sovereign

    will of God unconstrained by innate ratio-

    nal rules or essential forms is mimicked by

    the assertion of humankind producing an

    order that is lessfoundthan made. Modern

    science, for one, is indebted to this radical

    transformation: However much it pretends

    to passive discovery, its hidden corollary is

    the domination of pliant nature.

    As Ockhams razor sliced through the

    building blocks of dominant medieval

    optics, it hit the idea of the visible species,

    which allowed an object to appear mean-

    ingful to the eyes that beheld it. Sight, in

    medieval optics, worked through the trans-

    missions of these forms, from the object to

    the eye and vice versa. Extramission, as

    it was called, involved the sending out of

    species from the eye to meet those comingin through intromission. But Ockham

    rejected this idea as unnecessary, for it

    added an extraneous general concept,

    which he thought could be jettisoned in

    favor of understanding sight as simply an

    intuitive grasping of particular objects at a

    distance.

    Ockhams razor also severed the

    Scholastic concept of organic aesthetic

    form, which, as Aquinas held, was com-

    prised of an object s integrity, clarity, and

    proportion, qualities believed to be univer-

    sal norms. While subsequent efforts were

    made to rescue a generic metaphysics of

    beauty (neo-Platonism returned during the

    Renaissance and the eighteenth century;

    neo-Aristotelianism enjoyed a twentieth-

    century theoretical revival), the nominal-

    ist challenge remained. It contributed,

    for example, to the rise of the novel, that

    entirely anti-generic genre that dees vir-

    tually al l of the traditional rules of beauty

    and form; and in musical compositions, in

    the works of, for example, Gustav Mahler,

    who denied an ontology of pre-given musi-

    cal forms. In visual culture, nominalisms

    dominant exemplar has been photography,

    a medium that insists on capturing images

    of only specic things in the world. But

    photography has done so by instantiating a

    version of the nominalist impulse I want to

    call magical, with a nod to the novelists

    who have developed a similar doctrine of

    magical realism. To make my case, let me

    take a detour through the work of a gurein the visual arts who carried the nominal-

    ist impulse to its extreme, the French (anti-)

    artist Marcel Duchamp. In inventing the

    brilliant provocation that came to be called

    the readymade, an object from everyday

    life that was selected as art rather than

    made by the skill of the artist, he denied

    the very idea of organic formal beauty.

    Duchamp himself understood his work,

    to cite a lapidary and cryptic note from

    his White Boxin 1914, as a kind of picto-

    rial Nominalism, a term that appeared

    throughout Duchamps writings.

    How does Duchampian nomi-

    nalism t with our understanding

    of photography in nominalist

    terms? For one, whereas mainstream mod-

    ernist abstraction pursued the elusive goal

    of the essential purity of the medium as

    Clement Greenberg never tired of remind-

    ing us Duchamp performatively rejected

    that quest by giving up painting itself.

    Abandoning not only the mimetic task of

    painting copying what was on the otherside of a framed, t ransparent window onto

    the world Duchamp also rejected the

    claim that the at canvas was an opaque

    surface on which experiments in color,

    form, and a texture might be pursued.

    Instead, he decried all retinal art meant

    to provide pleasure to the eye, in favor of

    an art that was named as such by someone

    with the cultural capital to have his act of

    enunciation taken seriously. In other words,

    one meaning of pictorial nominalism was

    the idea that the intrinsic qualities of the

    object were less important than the act of

    naming it a work of art and gett ing fi

    in visual culTure,nominalisms dominanT

    exemplar has been

    phoTography, a medium ThaT

    insisTs on capTuring images

    of only specific Things

    in The world.

  • 7/29/2019 BJ19_Jay

    3/7

    46 | The Berlin Journal | Number Nineteen | Fall 2010

    the legitimating institutions museums,

    galleries, collectors, historians of art to

    accept the act as valid. Eschewing the

    older ideal of creative genius in which the

    gifted art ist somehow channeled the same

    innovative spirit that God has shown inwilling the world into being, miraculously

    making the invisible visible, Duchamp

    effaced himself, or at least his talent as a

    traditional art ist, and became the more

    modest designator the namer of found

    objects as readymade works worthy of dis-

    play in museums. In this sense, pictorial

    nominalism was a variation of the older

    impulse found in Ockham, which denied

    that inherent qualities existed in the world

    that could serve as standards of beauty. It

    was a radical conventionalism in which the

    decision of the enunciator the one who

    can get away with saying this bottle rack or

    this urinal is a work of art and should be in

    a museum trumped any intrinsic rules of

    formal beauty, such as proportion, organic

    wholeness, or integrity.

    There was, however, another sense in

    which pictorial nominalism moved beyondthis conventionalist usage and gestured

    towards a kind of nominalism that was

    no longer understandable solely in terms

    of denial and disenchantment. It is this

    second kind that I want to call magical

    nominalism.

    Duchamp wanted to reduce words to

    their non-communicative status, express-

    ing nothing of the intention of the mind

    that might speak them or descr iptive of

    an external world to which they might

    refer. Ideally spoken by no one, they defy

    both interpretation into something else

    and their subsumption under a generic

    concept. If words are to be understood as

    names, it is not in the sense of a linguistic

    sign but rather that of the proper name,

    which does nothing to describe the char-

    acteristics of the person to whom it refers

    or to subsume him under a concept, but

    rather rigidly designates him or her as a

    unique entity.

    Magical nominalism has to be differ-

    entiated from its conventionalist cousin in

    its relative de-emphasis of the enunciative

    function of the art ist, that moment of self-

    assertion ex nihilo, a critical implication of

    the Ockhamist critique of real universals.

    Duchamp sensed that it was only by diving

    into the nostalgic past that he could carry

    out his nominalist function. The ready-

    made is something given by history, not

    created by the artist in the present, and is

    then re-named an art object not a paint-

    ing or a sculpture, but simply art object.As such, it means nothing aside from that

    name, no longer an object of use, not an

    object of formal beauty within a generic

    tradition. Its value, we might say, lies solely

    in what it is now designated.

    To understand the implications of

    all this for photography wil l require

    a quick glance at the writings of two

    critics, who at one time or another had

    illuminating things to say about art in gen-

    eral and photography in particular: Walter

    Benjamin and Rosalind Krauss.

    In Benjamins seminal 1916 essay On

    Language as Such and On the Language

    of Man, he adopted what has been called

    an Adamic view of languages: the Fall

    into a Babel of dif ferent tongues was pre-

    ceded by an Ursprache, an original pure

    language. He began by expanding the word

    language beyond a tool of human com-

    munication or mental expression to include

    everything in animate and inanimate

    nature.

    Whereas conventional notions of lan-guage privilege communication between

    humans about a world of objects, the more

    expansive notion knows no means, no

    object, and no addressee of communication.

    It means: in the name, the mental being of

    man communicates itself to God. Although

    only God possesses the perfect language

    in which name is equivalent to thing, man

    approximates it through the giving of prop-

    er names: The theory of proper names is

    the theory of the frontier between nite

    and innite language.

    Language in this expanded sense is

    therefore more than mere signs, more

    dan GluiBizzi, jr., mWi-lines , 2009. aCryliC on Canvas, 20 x 16 inChes

    imAgeCourtesyoftheArtist

  • 7/29/2019 BJ19_Jay

    4/7

    Fall 2010 | Number Nineteen | The Berlin Journal|47

    than arbitrary conventions invented to

    communicate abstract ideas or enact inter-

    subjective performatives. After the Fall

    into Babel, however, the project of regain-

    ing the perfect language was thwarted

    by what Benjamin calls overnaming,

    which produces the melancholy of a dis-

    enchanted natural world no longer at one

    with its original names. For Benjamin it

    is the act of translation that offers hope of

    reunication: it aims at getting beyond the

    inadequacies of individual languages and

    approaching the Ursprache beneath them.

    Here, in Benjamin, we have a nominal-

    ism that fully earns the adjective magicalin the sense that it rejects both abstract

    universals in the Scholastic tradition and

    conventional names in its Ockhamist

    nominalist opponent. Instead it posits the

    possibility of regaining original names,

    true names, as designating, indeed being

    at one with, the specic, qualitatively

    unique things to which they had been

    equivalent before the Fall into Babel and

    conventionalist pluralism of dif ferent

    human languages. But like Duchamps

    pictorial nominal ism, Benjamins sought-

    after restoration also dislocates objects

    from their functional contexts of use and

    resituates them in a new realm in which

    they are without any communicative

    meaning beyond their existence as qualita-

    tively distinct things.

    We are, to be sure, still a far cry from

    photography. And here Rosalind Krausss

    inuential essay of 1977, Notes on the

    Index, comes briey to our aid. In thecontext of an explanation of Duchamps

    rejection of painting and his overcom-

    ing of self-depiction, she turned to the

    importance of the photographs indexical

    relationship or factual trace, like tracks

    in the snow or handprints on a wall to the

    world. Drawing on C.S. Peirces distinction

    of icon, symbol, and index, Krauss argued

    that the photograph heralds a disruption

    in the autonomy of the sign. A meaning-

    lessness surrounds it which can only be

    lled by the addition of a text. She then

    audaciously linked Duchampss ready-

    mades with the photograph, writing that it

    was not surprising that Duchamp should

    have described the readymade in just these

    terms. It was to be a snapshot to which

    there was attached a tremendous arbitrari-

    ness with regard to meaning, a breakdown

    of the relatedness of the linguistic sign.

    There was a parallel between the way ready-

    mades and photographs were produced:

    both were uncoded events that extracted

    signs from their contexts.

    W

    ith these points in mind,

    let us return to our point of

    departure: William of Ockhamsnominalism may have denied the intrinsic

    intelligibility of the world in terms of real

    universals, but, as noted, it opened the door

    for faith. Magical nominalism can perhaps

    be understood as one variant of that faith,

    which is revived in visual terms most pow-

    erfully in the case of the photograph. fi

    Autumn sales 25 27 November 2010 in Berlin

    Villa Grisebach Auktionen Fasanenstrae 25 D-10719 Berlin Phone +49-30-885 915-0 www.villa-grisebach.de

    Every time I come here,it lifts my spirit.

    Eric Kandel, New York

    There was a parallel beTween The way readymades and

    phoTographs were produced: boTh were uncoded evenTs

    ThaT exTracTed signs from Their conTexTs.

  • 7/29/2019 BJ19_Jay

    5/7

    48 | The Berlin Journal | Number Nineteen | Fall 2010

    What precisely is the object of that faith?

    Why do photographs grab us and demand

    our attention, telling us to stop the ow of

    time and pause in our rush into the future?

    Here, of course, we can only conjecture. But

    if we agree that they do not afrm a world

    of inherent ontological universals, or even

    an aesthetic canon of conventional forms,

    we can say that photographs somehow

    want to be understood as the visual equiva-

    lents of the Adamic names the true

    names Benjamin hoped to rescue from

    the overnaming of linguist ic conven-

    tionalism. They want to remain stubbornly

    meaningless in the sense that they resist

    being paraphrased in terms that reduce

    their singularity to an exemplar or case of

    a larger category or even as a metaphor of

    something else. More precisely, despite

    all efforts to saturate them with meaning,

    photographs insist that they always containa measure of excess that dees paraphrastic

    reduction.

    As Roland Barthes classic Camera

    Lucida observes, photography stresses

    the melancholy implication of its image

    as memento mori, a mark of the inevitably

    passing of time, implying our nitude.

    But if we see the photograph instead as a

    miraculous freezing of a single ephemeral

    moment, a moment that is utterly irre-

    ducible to what came before or after, an

    uncanny moment that somehow is present

    when the image is later viewed despite its

    absence, then perhaps it can be understood

    to betoken something magical. Like a

    fetish, wrested out of the contextual ow of

    linear time, the conventional time of his-

    torical narrative, it resists being absorbedinto a cultural whole. Like a proper name,

    it refers only to one singular object at one

    instant of its existence. And as such, it lim-

    its the sovereign power of the constitutive

    subject.

    Although we know that photographs,

    even before the age of digitalization, are

    amalgams of the instant of their being

    taken and the subsequent work on them

    in the developing, printing, and dis-

    playing processes, that instant is never

    entirely absorbed into those posterior

    interventions.

    The photograph, in short, is a reminder

    that the world is more than human pro-

    jection or construction, more than the

    categories we impose on it, more than the

    meanings we impute to it. Rather than the

    humanist self-assertion that some have

    seen as a consequence of conventionalist

    nominalism, it implies what we might

    call the counter-assertion of the world, a

    world more readymade than the product

    of human will, a world that somehow

    stubbornly thwarts all of our most valiant

    efforts to disenchant it.

    Martin Jay is the Sidney HellmanEhrman Professor of History at the

    University of California, Berkeley, and

    the fall 2010 Ellen Maria Gorrissen

    Fellow at the American Academy.

    PfizerDeutschlandGmbH

    Pfizer researches to develop the medicinesof today and tomorrow

    Life is full of exciting discoveries. And what we do is all

    about seeking new insights. For more than 160 years,

    Pfizer has researched and developed innovative pre-

    parations and treatments in all medical disciplines,

    with 13,000 researchers around the world. We do this

    with great perseverance because developing a new

    drug may take as long as 15 years. Whats more, we

    constantly strive to refine proven medication, for

    example, to achieve a more specific effect or better

    dosing. Every day, this is what we do to realize our

    vision of Working Together for a Healthier World.

    www.pfizer.de

    Because lifeasks the biggestquestions

    The phoTograph, in shorT, is

    a reminder ThaT The world is

    more Than human projecTion

    or consTrucTion, more Than

    The caTegories we impose

    on iT, more Than The meanings

    we impuTe To iT.

  • 7/29/2019 BJ19_Jay

    6/7

  • 7/29/2019 BJ19_Jay

    7/7

    New Yorks newest attractions

    are built by us.Its not just the tourists who are pleased about the new sights in the Big Apple. So are

    the passengers. Thats because the urban buses from our Orion brand are equipped with

    low-consumption hybrid drive, meaning that they make an important contribution towards

    climate protection. There are more than 3,000 of these innovative buses on the road in

    major US cities, including San Francisco and Los Angeles. Another milestone on our

    Road to Emission-free Mobility.

    www.daimler.com

    www.daimler.mobi