(bergson) time, creation, & the mirror of narcissus

45
7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 1/45 Time, Creation, and the Mirror of Narcissus Author(s): Lenn E. Goodman Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy East and West, Vol. 42, No. 1 (Jan., 1992), pp. 69-112 Published by: University of Hawai'i Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1399692 . Accessed: 24/11/2012 03:27 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy  East and West. http://www.jstor.org

Upload: lgibson03

Post on 03-Apr-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 1/45

Time, Creation, and the Mirror of NarcissusAuthor(s): Lenn E. Goodman

Reviewed work(s):Source: Philosophy East and West, Vol. 42, No. 1 (Jan., 1992), pp. 69-112Published by: University of Hawai'i Press

Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1399692 .

Accessed: 24/11/2012 03:27

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy

 East and West.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 2/45

TIME, CREATION, AND THE MIRROR OF NARCISSUS

"If Bergson believed anything," Charles Hartshorne writes, "it was the

asymmetry of time, the openness of the future and determinateness of

the past."' But Bergson, Hartshorne argues, too readily forgot that thedenial of determinism, so central to his project, rests on the denial of the

symmetry of time. Determinism, Hartshorne urges, following Peirce and

Bergson himself, takes an essentially symmetrical view of time. That is

why, on Laplace's model, one can as readily retrodict the past as predictthe future, given an adequate knowledge of the present state of the

world and its unchanging laws. The core of Bergson's message was that

the determinism that negates human freedom and closes the open fu-

ture arises in a false analogy between time and space: Space is an affair

of mutual exclusion of elements, "whereas time is an affair of mutual

inclusion."By preserving

a certainsymmetry in both space and time,Hartshorne argues, Bergson compromises the ultimate asymmetry of

time and falls into "The most glaring confusion in Time and Free Will."

The purpose of this essay is to examine the idea that there is a kind

of symmetry in time, the symmetry that Bergson described in terms of

the mutual inclusion of temporal moments. I want to appraise some of

the consequences of the denial of that claim. What I will argue is that

Bergson's idea of the mutual interpenetration of temporal moments

allows expansion of the idea of the specious present from a brief span of

subjective immediacy to the full duration needed in nature for the un-

foldingof an event. This

expandedview of duration will accommodate

actions sustained over long periods, including extended collaborations

by members of a community or a culture over history. I want to defend

the coherence of Bergson's thinking here by pointing out that time can

be asymmetrical in one respect and symmetrical in another: The inter-

penetration of temporal moments is not a denial of the unalterable

differentness of the future from the past. Rather, it is an affirmation of

continuity.But my motive in taking up this topic goes beyond the affirmation of

that simple fact. The idea that there is a certain symmetry among the

moments of time will prove critical in relatingtraditional ideas of creation

to Bergson's own emphasis on ongoing creativity. The attempt simply to

discard creation for more recently favored notions of process, by con-

trast, endangers many of the insights and values, both scientific and

moral, that Bergson sought to preserve within his broad conceptions of

creativity, duration, and the asymmetry of time. Following the thrust of

some of the more stridently eternalist recent readings of the outcome

of a debate that has continued since Western speculation about cosmol-

ogy began, we find a starkly scientistic outlook that seems to be insepa-

Professor f PhilosophyUniversity f Hawaii

PhilosophyEast&WestVolume42, Number1

January1992

69-112

? 1992

by University fHawaii Press

69

LennE.Goodman

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 3/45

rable from the endeavor to cut off the future from the past, whether in

human or in cosmic terms. Toward the end of this article, I will examine

the rhetoric and the consequences of this outlook, after first offeringsome counterarguments to its claims.

PhilosophyEast&West

i. Is There Symmetry in Time?Surely it is true that time is asymmetrical at a profound level. The

unlikeness of the future to the past is critical to its being future. Even if

Nietzsche, Plotinus,2and the Stoics are right about eternal recurrence,

recycled events are not the same as what they repeat, or there would be

no meaning to the claim that the same events recurred:there must be at

least the fact that this Socrates, Xanthippe, and Meletus are repetitionsof those. But are there some respects in which time is symmetrical, or is

it simply a confusion on Bergson's part to speak of interpenetration, the

mutual openness of temporal moments to one another?

In Matter andMemory, Bergson

discovers the sameinterpenetrationin space that he had earlier found in time and used to break down

the linearity of events. Zeno's paradoxes rest on the assumption that

time and events are either a Euclidean continuum or a Pythagorean

pointillistic series. But, in fact, Bergson argued, the moments of time are

neither the dimensionless knife edge that temporal analysis invokes as a

virtual limit, nor the static freeze-frames of a misplaced spatial analy-sis. On the contrary, each particular moment of change involves an

onwardness-what Plato called 'becoming', and Bergson 'duration'-

which no merely geometric model can capture and which static abstrac-

tionsonly

deaden, in fictive denial of the fact ofchange,

as anatomical

sections or microtomes arrest and thereby negate the processes of life

they are meant to reveal.3

Time itself is denied by the analysis that seeks to compose it in the

Augustinian way, of a vanished past, an unborn future, and an infinitely

diminishing present.4The present, Bergson saw, cannot be instantaneous

or atomic. It must have duration-both asymmetrical, melting into the

future even as it emerges from the past, and blurryedged, not bounded

sharply by dimensionless points, since the dimensionless point is a mere

fiction of geometry. The same is true of space: it is impossible to com-

pose what will have magnitude out of what has none, whether in spaceor time. So Bergson's real quarrel was not with space but with over-

reliance on a fiction most familiar from its use in the analysis of space:the fiction of discrete and frozen moments that are at once fully de-

terminate (thus fixed) in their character, yet somehow (paradoxically)determinative-each of the character of the rest and holding, without

omission, all that ever was or will be in all the rest. Bergson first ex-

pressed what was misleading about this fiction by saying that time is

not like space, but he came to see that space itself is not like space in

70

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 4/45

the sense that the economies and abstractions of geometry would have

it. The Cartesian project of geometrizing nature is as much an under-

representation of matter as it is of time.

To render time atomic is to render change impossible and, as Hume

saw clearly, to arrest causality. Thus Hume's cunning insistence that time

is a succession of infinitesimal instants:5 thestatic,

durationless instants

of Humean time prejudge the question of causality in favor of a kind of

logical atomism. But suppose (like true empiricists) we had begun from

the fact of change. Or suppose we were to understand change not in

terms of succession but in terms of the conditionedness of one moment

or event by another. Then causality would be a given,6 and the simplesensa of extreme empiricism would be recognized for what they are,

elaborate constructs, achievements of perceptual and cognitive synthe-sis and selection.

Only ifthe moments of time themselves have realduration is change

conceivable,7 and

only

in such duration is there the theater of action for

causality, which will not merely determine the future out of the given-ness of the past, but also allow actors to differentiate the future from

that givenness-allow genuine change, and indeed evolution, the emer-

gence of what is conditioned by the past (to use Spinoza's word), but

never pre-contained in it, or locked in place by what is already over and

done with. When Leibniz held that the past was great with the future,

and the future laden with the past,8 he knew better than to imaginesheer pre-formation: It was because mere geometric figures could not

explain the forces of cohesion or mutual exclusion among bodies that

Leibniz remedied the Cartesian reduction of bodies to extension, by

proposing intensive qualities that would allow the emergence of events

not yet present in their causes.9 SimilarlyBergson, in admiring the cos-

mogony of Lemaitre, settled on the fact that the primitive datum of

energy/mass from which the world emerges cannot, in the nature of the

case, contain or determine all that it will engender. As Lemaitre wrote,

"Clearlythe initialquantum could not conceal in itself the whole course

of evolution; but, according to the principle of indeterminacy, that is not

necessary. Our world is now understood to be a world where something

really happens; the whole story of the world need not have been written

down in the first quantum like a song on a phonograph record."10

Bergson's early arguments about time relied on the phenomenologyof felt duration. Hisdescriptions were of consciousness, and his paradigmcase of duration was our awareness of a melody. Bergson's father was a

musician, and the son knew well that our hearing of a melody cannot be

composed of durationless instants if we are ever to hear it as a melody,hear its notes in relation to one another, as parts in a whole, or even as

rhythmic or tonal contrasts to one another." The same, we must say, of

the rich complexity of an orchestral chord; the same, we now know, of Lenn E. Goodman

71

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 5/45

PhilosophyEast&West

our perception of colors: they are perceived relationally, against a con-

textual background, and the comparative process in which this is done

is, of course, a temporal act.12The ability to conceive (or even perceive!)a hitherto unknown particularshade of blue, which was such a mysteryfor Humean epistemology, is no mystery at all when we recognize that

there are no atomic sensa, but that even the "simplest" patches of colorare complexly constructed syntheses of very complex events.'3 Thus a

psychological dissolving of the conundrums of dogmatic empiricism was

a byproduct of Bergson's biological, indeed evolutionary epistemology,which saw perception as an act not only of synthesis but of abstraction,

filtration,and exclusion.'4

Because of its pioneering reliance on phenomenology, Bergson'sthe-

ory of time set up a sharp contrast between public or cosmic time and

subjective time. It relied heavily on James' idea of the specious present,the moment which is immediate for consciousness; and it seriously at-

temptedto measure that

present, markingit off

against publictime-

despite its recognition that spans of time are not strictly superposable.Values were assigned between a maximum of 12 seconds, the longest

span that James believed consciousness could hold together as a single

now, and a minimum of .002 seconds, the briefest event that seemed

accessible to sense perception.'5 Committed followers of Bergson still

take seriously this confounding of psychological temporality with real

duration. But Bergson himself came to see that public time, cosmic time,the time of natural events, must be structured in the same way as

phenomenal time: the dissolving of sugar in his coffee was a sequence of

natural events isometric with his ownimpatient expectation

of its out-

come.

Strictly speaking, Bergson's reference to subjective experience here

was quite unnecessary. Natural time no more requires anchoring in

phenomenal time than phenomenal time requires naturaltime to autho-

rize it. If the present is the locus of events, it will last as long as those

events require, and this will be denied only by those who bear a meta-

physical animus against the notion that events occur. Thus Bergson'scentral thesis about time is as true of physical as of psychological events,and no reliance on Kantian or post-Kantian phenomenology is needed

to validate it: time in nature, as in consciousness, has the character of

duration, and the asymmetry in it is not a matter of perception or

intuition but a fact of nature. Innature, as in thought, time is not a series

of atomic instants, whether dimensionless or instantly evanescent, but

the inexorable onwardness of change itself, the inevitable qualitativedifferentness of the future from the past, and the inevitable referentialityof the present to the future and the past. That reference is made by the

events themselves, and must be if they are to have unity as events.

Objective moments, then, interpenetrate as much as subjective ones do;

72

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 6/45

and the flow or stream of consciousness that loomed so large for Proust,or Joyce, or VirginiaWoolf, is just a special case of the nature of time at

large. For what Bergson first saw in terms of memory and anticipation is

equally true without the mediation of consciousness, for causes and

effects, preconditions and aftermaths.'6

The specious present, then, is misnamed not only on the ground thatCapek gives,17 that there is nothing false or illusory or even secondaryabout it, but also on the ground that there is nothing essentially subjec-tive about it: the thick temporal present necessary to the occurrence of

any event is the time the event requiresto unfold.18Bythat standard, the

present (like an Aristotelian place) is of any size, or many sizes, from a

duration much shorter than consciousness can capture to one that

spans the centuries. In the writingof a book or the birth of a volcano, the

event is a whole not because of any imagined discreteness from other

events, but because of the organic connectedness of its parts, the con-

ditioningof what comes later

bywhat went

before,and the

dependenceof the outcome as a whole upon what happens now. The present is not

over until all that can give determinacy to the whole has occurred. Then

and only then the present lapses into past, the imperfect becomes per-

fect; the indeterminate, determinate. Thus the events of a war or of

history in general, the subtle collaboration across the centuries between

Edward Fitzgerald and the many poets whose quatrains were gatheredunder the name of Omar Khayyam,19 he composition of a Bible or a

Talmud through an intricate dialogue or continuing discourse across the

generations, and the collusion or falling out of authors and their readers,

translators andinterpreters,

or of

painterswith those who view or scorn

their works, all reveal that the idea of a single definitive present (let alone

a rapidly passing one) is a sham. There are many presents of varyingdurations and with no more perfect discreteness than events themselves

possess.Time is thick because events are nested within one another, much as

places are. And Bergson's pedagogical explanation that time is unlike

space because in time there is no simultaneity of mutually excluding

parts is only a first approximation. For, as Capek makes clear, where

Bergson and his many critics were never perfectly clear, the real impactof relativity on Bergson's philosophy is to exclude the notion of instanta-

neous, universe-wide simultaneity. If so, the effect of Bergsonism on

relativity is not at all to wreck or seek to derail but to complete Einstein's

project of discovering the ultimate temporality of space itself.20Bergson's

philosophy achieves this end not by the Kantian expedient of arguingthat space can be apprehended only in a temporal tour by conscious-

ness through its parts and regions, but by the more properly Bergsonian

recognition that the parts of space make reference to one another and

can do so only through the medium of differentiated time. What follows LennE.Goodman

73

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 7/45

PhilosophyEast&West

is the recognition that despite all Eleaticwishes, time cannot be excluded

from the most fleeting snapshot of the universe-or rather, we should

say, from the universe itself.

The intuitive, naturalistic core of Bergson's insight about time rests in

the fact that time is not truly one-dimensional. Space allows an event to

occupy a durational present, beginning here in one respect before ithas begun otherwise elsewhere. Here and now, without reference to

Einsteinian relativity, in a single inertial frame and with middle-sized

objects that may or may not be observed, we find the thickness of

duration, the cross talk of referentiality-the lineardimension, or longeurof an event, but also, in the multifacetedness of the same event, its

largeur, which in turn involves the temporality of space, the need for

time in which the parts of an event or act come together as a whole

occurrence.

Bergson's brief was the overcoming of determinism. A false analogybetween time and

space,he

argued,led mechanists to

supposethat time

was a continuum of atomic instants, each one of which was ultimatelystatic and each one of which uniquely determined and was determined

by any of the rest. The result was the denial in effect of the fundamental

psychological, biological-indeed physical-asymmetry of duration and

the collapsing of time into a series of strata or slices whose relations of

mutual implication made them in principle undistinguishable from one

another-thus eliminating time altogether. To dissolve time in such a

fashion was a desideratum perhaps for Megarian or Stoic would-be mo-

nists of the stamp of Diodorus Cronus. But if achieved, it would prove a

disaster for those scientific or scientistic determinists whosetight grip

upon the twentieth century Bergson sought to relax. Bergson's strategywas to argue that time is not a discontinuous continuum of discrete

moments; the nows which represent the present are not isolated and

dimensionless instants but interpenetrating and persistent spans that

afford a platform to action and so to freedom. Where mechanism col-

lapses the present and thus time itself, since time is nothing if there is

no present, Bergson reclaims time, by the very expedient Proust would

adopt from Bergson's teaching, recapturing the past, through the recog-nition that consciousness and ultimately everything present makes itself

what it is through retention of the past: "There is no consciousness

without memory, no continuation of a state without the addition, to the

present feeling, of the memory of past moments. That is what duration

consists of."21Phenomenology or analogy, and ultimately the pure anal-

ysis of the anatomy of natural events, broadens the claim to a fact not

merely about consciousness but about the character of the cosmos: time

is "the indivisible and indestructible continuity of a melody where the

past enters into the present and forms with it an undivided whole which

remains undivided and even indivisiblein spite of what is added at everyinstant or rather thanks to what is added."22

74

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 8/45

The strength of Bergson's account is that it leaves room-he would

say time-for the emergence of the future. Because it allows actors to

differentiate the future from the past, it allows for creativity, a creativitythat is emergent-neither locked within the past, nor radically severed

from it. But this is not sufficient for Hartshorne. Objecting to any form of

symmetry between past and future, he denounces the notion of mutualinclusion as vociferously as the notion of mutual exclusion. There is, he

insists, nothing mutual in the case: "Nowhere does Bergson make clear

that symmetry, rather than dependence or its negative, is the mark of

space and asymmetry, of time." What Hartshorne objects to is Bergson'ssense of continuity, indeed community, between the future and the past.

Potentiality, he insists, is mere virtuality,no determinant at all, since it is

nothing actual. This Bergson saw but failed to follow up on: "It is absurd,

as Bergson sees, to imagine exact duplicates of actual particulars and

baptize them as antecedent possibilities (or group them as denisons [sic]

ofpossible

worlds).... Possibilities arealways

more or lessgeneral.

Be-

coming is creation of particularity, not its rebaptizing as 'actual,' what-

ever that could add if particularitywere already there."23There is a pro-found and important point here, of much relevance to modal logic in

general and the ontological argument in particular:a possible dollar is

not the same sort of thing in the least as the actual dollar that might

replace it. Indeed, a possible dollar,or a possible tiger, is not a thing at all

but a notion, an abstract generality, dependent on the suspension of

some but not all of the assumptions we characteristically make about the

world we live in. But Hartshorne overstates the implications of this in-

sight.It does not

implythat the

pasthas no

purchaseon the

presentor

that virtualities are found wholly in the future, somehow to be pluckedfrom there ad libitum, like apples from a tree. On the contrary, to

make that assumption would be to re-atomize time, to overcome the

atomization of mutual implication only to fall into a new atomization of

radical isolation and absolute indeterminism. Surely the future does not

create itself. Agents act in the present, against the background of con-

ditions they inherit from the past.Whitehead adopted and assiduously adapted Bergson's concept of

duration.24But he both departed from Bergson and in a way enshrined

what Bergson had taught by the special emphasis he gave to what

Aristotle had called 'passing away', and what Whitehead himself, follow-

ing Locke, called "perpetual perishing."Whitehead once claimed to have

tried to do for perishing what Aristotle had done for becoming, and he

argued that the very fixity of what is over and done with makes it an

inextricable element of the future, grounding the sense we may some-

times have "that what we are is of infinite importance."25It is this special

emphasis on perishing, a notion forecast in Plato and central in Philo-

ponus (for similar Christian reasons to those that move Whitehead-or

the cinemateurs of Places in the Heart) that Hartshorne wants faithfully LennE.Goodman

75

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 9/45

PhilosophyEast&West

to preserve when he castigates Bergson for overlooking the asymmetryof the future with the past: "Bergson shows no sign of realizing that a

definite pluralityof unit cases of becoming ... can be combined with em-

phatic acceptance of the unity of present with past. Itis only the unity of

past with present that must be rejected. Where in my childhood was

there any unity with my present state? I might have died long ago.Retrospective unity does not entail prospective unity."26Hartshorne,

evidently, does not agree that the child is father of the man, but he can

hardly fail to admit that the choices I make now contribute to what Iwill

be. They are registered in my character, and have been, ever since Iwas

a child. Ifthis be false, there is no such task as education, and no such

event as a life.27

The radical asymmetry of time that Bergson missed, Hartshorne

argues, is that while the past does influence the present the presentcannot affect the past: "Nothing we do will ever change the career of

Shakespearebetween his birth and his death."28This

seemingtruism is

meant to be as damaging to Bergson's conceptualization of time as

Hartshorne's telling comment about possible worlds is damaging in fact

to those members of the current Princeton school who imagine that

possibilities live somewhere else than this world, as the constituents of

(actual) possible worlds. It is true that efficient causes cannot touch the

past. But it is true as well that much that we call past is not past at all in

the sense of this precise asymmetry. It is true that "possibles" are not

ready-formed particulars lacking only some key of entry called actualityin order to emerge as real entities or events. The notion that they are was

causingtrouble

longbefore the time of Kant.29But that does not mean

that there is no mutuality between past and future. When the past is

active, in memory, or in causality, it is not as past but as present actualitythat it acts, and in playing a role in the formation of the future, even if

only as a springboard or dialectical antithesis, it becomes part of the

present and is distinctively affected, not in the sense that the facticity of

what is truly past is altered retroactively, but in the sense that the

significance of what is past, whether for consciousness or for nature, is

made other than what it was. Past events, as causes or as matter for

creativity, do not remain what they were, and indeed are not over, not

in the sense conveyed in natural languages by the use of the perfect

tense, over and done with, Carthago fuit, Carthago ruit. The continuing

presentness of what is in some senses and for some purposes past is the

very meaning of the idea of duration;and duration, as we have observed,can be much longer than Bergson supposed. What we call a past event

is in some of its aspects far more lasting than the event that in other

contexts we might identify by the same name. There are some places,and not in any mystic or subjective, or legalisticsense, where World War II

has not yet ended. Indeed, in some respects, there is nowhere in the

76

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 10/45

world where it is over fully; we still belong, as Yehuda Bauer rightly

argues, to the generation, to the same historic present, of those who

perpetrated and underwent the Holocaust. The War continues to exer-

cise its effects. And its outcome, for that very reason, continues to be

influenced and changed (thus its impact as a whole is changed) by the

responses of living subjects now.30Our actions affect the fulfillment of the hopes of our forebears in

many crucial ways. Insofar as we constitute a community with other

beings, past, present, or future, our actions affect the achievement of

their projects. It is certainly of consequence to the careers of Shakespeare,

Horace, and Thucydides whether their work continues to be read; and

to anyone who has made efforts or sacrifices for posterity, it is of mo-

ment whether those efforts fall on barren soil or are taken up and carried

forward. It is for this reason that it is relevant to late comers to determine

which if any of those projects deserve to be taken up, how, if at all, theyare to be carried

forward,and in what

respects.The

living present mayinvolve participants in a single action that endures over centuries. In

cultural or communal terms, individuals who are centuries apart may

participate in a single action, or a system of actions that constitute a

history, an economy, a progress or progression of culture or civilization.

The wise or ignorant choices, happy or unhappy turnings of later evolu-

tionary or cultural actors are as consequential to the success or failure of

their predecessors' efforts as the latter are to the former.31Such mutual-

ity or community in a project only inchoately given in its earlier stagesdoes not, of course, amount to strict or comprehensive symmetry of the

future with the past. Time, like many another sequence, is symmetrical in

some respects and asymmetrical in others. But the level at which there is

in fact a mutuality, say between those living now and their forebears,does show in just what sense the present time, like the present place in

Aristotle, is a relative notion capable of indefinite expansion: It is the

expansion characteristic of the ever-enlargeable conception of the we,and not merely of the subjective we, but also of the equally expansible

objective it.

Recognition of the interpenetration of the moments of time, their

cross-referentiality, and their nestedness in one another, within systemsof presentness defined only by the relevance of their components to a

given event, action, or concern, does damage a Whiteheadian dogma of

great centrality to Hartshorne, the dogma of the consequent nature of

God. For it means that the past is not merely antecedent to the future,but is its prologue, laying out conditions and parameters that can influ-

ence and indeed in their measure determine the future, as well as settingthe stage for creativity and the emergence of what is genuinely novel, yet

grounded in what has gone before.32God is more than an album for the

storage of past occasions, and God is anything but hampered by limited LennE.Goodman

77

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 11: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 11/45

PhilosophyEast&West

potency in the way that Whiteheadians of Hartshorne's school like to

claim. We see divine efficacy as much in the determination of the future

by the past as in the emergence of the genuinely novel. Both aspects

authentically represent divine creativity, and the miracle of that crea-

tivity is nowhere more evident than in the emergence of actuality out

of virtualityat every present moment. Thisis what we mean when we saythat God is present not only in all places but also at all times. It clearlydoes not imply that time is symmetrical in some all-engulfing sense. For

the moment has the determinacy of actuality only insofar as it is past.But what it does imply is that divine agency is apprehensible under dif-

ferent aspects in the acts of finite agents: both in the certitude of the

outcomes of proximate causes and in the creativity of emergence in

nature and in art.33Of course the future can influence the past only in a

very limited and retrospective way-only to the extent, in fact, that the

future is not yet future but is seized in the same present with the past, as

avirtuality

to beappropriated

and (here Hartshorne isquite right)givendefinition in the very act of being given actuality.

In referringto the present in which agents act, and by so doing take

up and appropriate the past and define the potentiality of the future

(whose limitations are indeed the parameters assigned it by the past34),I

am referringto moments whose discreteness from one another is purelynotional. But that, of course, does not imply the unreality or illusoriness

of the time in which we live and act. Time is neither a razor edge of in-

stantaneity whose end is simultaneous with its beginning, nor an atomic

fragment of consciousness which does not linger even long enough to

be noted as a temporal now. Rather,since the

present

is the

platform

or

worktable of events, its duration is as long as their occurrence requires.A given event, as identified by one set of criteria, might be completed

long before the largersequence in which it forms a part, and from which

it draws significance when identified by other criteria. In the deathless

words of Yogi Berra,"Itisn't over 'til it's over."

As long as an event goes on-even if it takes years or centuries, like

the fighting of some wars, or the buildingof cathedrals or civilizations, or

revolutions in human relations or consciousness-every moment re-

mains intimately and organically connected to the rest, and the actions

undertaken now play their role in determining the ultimate meaningor effect of the whole. Hartshorne's attempt to discover an absolute

asymmetry of time behind the level of symmetry that Bergson finds thus

vitiates a part of the truth Bergson sought to explain. It reinstates the

false linearityfrom which Bergson sought to show us how to escape and

sunders the connectedness of duration, all for the sake of a rathertrivial

point about the doneness of what is done and some rather dubious

theological claims that amount to a preference for natura naturata over

natura naturans.

78

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 12: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 12/45

II.Creation and Symmetry

Surely there is one sense in which temporal moments are symmetri-cal with one another: the moments (orvirtualmoments) before the world

began (if it began) are undistinguishable from one another. It was on that

basis that Parmenides, Aristotle, Proclus, Averroes, and Spinoza sustained

the eternity of the world: moments undistinguishable because they areempty possess neither anteriority nor posteriority, but all collapse into

nullity; they do not exist. The argument is causal at the root: if all

events need an objective determinant, the world's imagined coming to

be would never come about, since no potential moment was any better

than the rest as the first moment of creation. Creationists from Philo-

ponus to al-KindT,o Avicebrol, al-Ghazal, Maimonides, and Leibniz,saw

that voluntarism offered the only escape from such fixity:35he world was

indeed created; but will, not reason or necessity, made the difference,

where none was found, among the prospective temporal moments,

choosingone as the first. The determinant was not

objectivebut

subjec-tive: God decided to create a world and chose the moment and the

manner.

The rejection of radical creation has been a thesis of philosophersalmost from the beginning. Anaximander (ap. Aristotle, De Caelo II13,

295b 10) held that the earth's position and stability depend on symmetry:"Itstays still because of its equilibrium. For it befits what is seated at the

center and equally disposed toward the extremes not to be borne a whit

more up or down or to the side-and it is impossible for it to move in

opposite directions at once-so it stays fixed by necessity." It was proba-

bly Anaximander himself who adapted this argument from symmetry to

apply to time as well as the directions. Forjust as he sought to sketch the

figure of the earth and sea in his map and to chart the rhythm of the

seasons with his gnomon, Anaximander enshrined the symmetry that

gives stability to change in his idea of the justice of time, which maintains

the equilibria of change and thereby obviates an absolute creation, by

overseeing the coming to be of all things out of the Indefinite and their

passing away into their proximate sources "according to the assessment

of time." Thus, in the words of Aristotle: "Inorder for generation not to

fail it is not necessary for perceptible body to be infinite actually, since it

is possible for the destruction of one thing to be the generation of the

other, while the sum of things remains limited" (Physics III , 208a 8).

Parmenides will argue explicitly from the likeness of each moment to

the next that being can have no origin:"Forwhat creation will you seek

for it.... And what need would have driven it on to grow, starting from

nothing, at a later time rather than an earlier?"(ap. Simplicius, Phys. 145,

1). He even alludes to Anaximander's Justice, as what "holds realityfast,"

not merely spatially but temporally, so that it cannot come to be or

perish but remains forever fully actual, since "it must either completely LennE.Goodman

79

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 13: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 13/45

PhilosophyEast&West

be or not be," and nonbeing is impossible. Parmenides' argument from

the equivalence of all moments is taken up by Aristotle and elaborated

by Proclus, Simplicius, and the Muslim Aristotelians in their polemics

against absolute creation. Passing from the Jewish Averroists to Spinoza,the idea of an immutable order loses its aura of divinity only in the

mechanism of the nineteenth century, where it lodges in the metaphysi-cal certitude of the conservation of matter. Butin a way this aura is never

wholly lost, from the time that Anaximander claimed the apeiron to be

immortal and divine as well as inexhaustible. For the counterpart of

mechanism, in modern as in Hellenistic times, was nature mysticism: the

aura of eternity is diffused in the immanence of romantic and trans-

cendentalist poets, painters, and essayists-dispersed and secularized,

attenuated in the aesthetic of the sublime, but still outspoken in the

spiritualismof pantheism.36The idea of eternity in nature persists into the

twentieth century, in the steady state thesis in cosmology, althoughbattered

by entropyand evolution and all but

finallyexploded bythe

BigBang.

Hartshorne praises eternalism in Bergson as "the well argued rejec-tion in Creative Evolutionof the idea that 'there might have been nothingat all'."He writes, "Hume's belief that all existential statements are con-

tingent is incorrect; since 'something exists' is necessarily true. 'Nothing,'the zero, the naught, has only a relative meaning; absolutized, it be-

comes nonsense. 'Nothing at all' either expresses an incoherent thoughtor implies some qualification, such as 'nothing to the present purpose.' I

have only admiration for Bergson's reasoning here."37But this is sheer

dogmatism. The only way we have of knowing that 'something exists' is

phenomenological. Itis true, as Descartes observed, that Icannot escapethe givens of my consciousness, but it does not follow, as Descartes well

understood, that my consciousness is a necessary being. I cannot think

my own nonexistence; but that does not imply that it is impossible for

me not to exist. The existence that is necessary can only be of what is

absolute, and monotheists are rightly chary about assigning absoluteness

of existence to just anything at random-as they are rightly chary of

assigning absolute significance to just any values in general. Hartshorne

is rather casual about this. Justas he is ready to say that some being, any

being, is necessary, he is correspondingly ready to downgrade divine

transcendence: "The highest conceivable form of reality, deity, is onlythe highest conceivable form of becoming or duration.... Berdyaev is the

clearest of all [about this].... Forhe hints at a divine kind of time."38

But was Bergson an eternalist? Hisdisciple Jacques Chevalier claimed

him as a creationist, much as he and others were eager to claim him as

a Catholic. But the facts are a bit more complex: Bergson played down

the centrality of an initial moment of creation because the great theme

of his philosophy was the ongoing creativity of the divine. But Bergson's

80

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 14: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 14/45

voluntarism, his finitism, his commitment to the idea of entropy, as

developed, for example, in the work of EmileMeyerson, his rejection of

the discrete, atomic matter and infinite, absolute space of the mechanis-

tic science of his day, ally him squarely with the creationists, albeit in a

sense necessarily modified by his own predilections, biases, and limita-

tions.39The atomist tradition from Democritus and Epicurus o al-RazT,oGassendi and the modern materialists, made space absolute and time

in effect reversible, with the constant random play of the changeless,Democritean, ultimately Parmenidean particles. Itwas against this vision

of nature that Bergson's philosophy and entire life's work set its face.

Entropy seemed to him to argue unequivocally for the irreversibilityof

time, as finitude in the world's determinations argued for its ultimate and

continuing origination.40

Bergson objected to the Kantian first antinomy, between eternityand creation, on the grounds that both horns of its dilemma treated the

universe as acompleted

whole. Herejected

the notion of time with

nothing in it. Buthe did not imagine (as Hartshornedoes) that if the world

was originated, it must have been preceded by illimitable eons of event-

less time. Against the notion of absolute time, either full or empty, from

eternity, he took up the classical creationist view that time itself is amongthe features of the world that first appear with creation. This was the

position of Philo, Augustine, Philoponus, al-Ghazal , Maimonides, and

others, who accepted the Aristotelian teaching of the relativity of time

but found in it a response to the Aristotelian, eternalist elenchus that

held it absurd to number moments in which nothing yet in nature had

moved or changed or even begun to be.4' In Bergson's case, as

Capekmakes clear,42 he same position flows naturallyfrom the deep harmonyof his view of time with that of Einsteinianrelativity:time has no meaning

apart from events. But Hartshorne fails to see that time relativism does

not commit one to eternalism but takes a well-trodden route through a

creationism that regardstime itself as created-or, in Bergson's case, we

might say, emergent, although in the nature of the case (as Aristotle saw)

there can be nothing gradual about the origin of time-the becoming of

becoming. Perhaps Eliot Deutsch's idea that time is what actions make of

it43best expresses the nuance Bergson sought to give to the idea of the

becoming of time.

Ironically, Hartshorne's discomfort with creation actually compro-mises Bergson's thesis of the asymmetry of time. For that asymmetry is

just what is at stake in the idea of creation: only God is necessary and

self-explanatory; the world is contingent, temporal, perhaps ephemeral.44When a Christian theist like Philoponus made the perishing of things a

central thesis of his cosmology, he did so in behalf of the idea of creation,not as a counterpart or alternative to it. And the same dialectic is found

in the vivid contrast of God's eternity with the world's temporality and LennE.Goodman

81

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 15: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 15/45

PhilosophyEast&West

contingency that is pinioned in the powerful Quranic image: "Allthings

perish except Hisface."45The idea is formalized and universalized in the

theology of the kalam (loquentes), and forged into systematic and coher-

ent metaphysics by Avicenna, following the lead of Plato's Timaeus:that

which is temporal is evanescent and contingent; that which is immutable

and (in Plotinus'term) impassive is ultimately creative, whether continu-ously, as in the model of emanation, or in the discrete but unremitting

fulgurations of Leibniz,the continual re-creations of the kalam-or the

act of Genesis that created heaven and earth, the sea, and all that is in

them. The monotheistic idea of perishing is the counterpart, ultimately,not of Aristotelian becoming but of Biblicalcreation.

A key argument of creationists like al-GhazalT nd Maimonides46was

that the eternalist thesis rests on a determinism so strict as to debar

change altogether and block emanation at the Source. Aristotle had

sought to pay deference to Parmenidean logic while maintaining the

realityof time and

change, by introducinghis distinctive model of

altera-tion. He preserved Parmenides' thesis that a thing must be what it is and

made it the cornerstone of First Philosophy. Change became possible

through the conjunction of unchanging form with unchanging matter.

The logical difficultyof a thing's becoming what it was not was overcome

by the logical expedient of distinguishing essence from accident, form

from matter, and actuality from potentiality: a thing became actuallywhat it already was potentially; such potentials would reside in matter.

Matter remained constant, and the changeable object would remain

constant in the only sense that really mattered to logic-it preserved the

same essence, unless denatured, that is,destroyed,

asby

death. The

corollaries that all change required a substrate, whose existing nature

would limit the scope of change, that no change was absolute or radical

(that is, nothing ever created de novo or destroyed completely), and that

essences were immutable were welcome and scientific seeming. But

there was a price to pay: since neither essences nor matter could be

altered or destroyed, evolution and extinction were impossible a priori,

sports of nature were by definition nonsignificant: since they breached

the essential boundaries of the species concept, they had to be dismissed

as accidental.

The scheme was both heuristic and limiting:it opened up vast fields

for scientific observation, classification, and inductive hypothesis. But it

ruled quantitative differences rather unimportant (nonessential) and so

inflamed Aristotle's failure to share Plato's enthusiasm for mathematics

into a general bias against the significance of measurement. Similarly, he

normative Aristotelian scheme deemed "unnatural"events uninterest-

ing. So for centuries it silently blocked the path of inquiry by forestallingthe development of controlled experimentation, by which investigators

(using Bacon's model of Elizabethantorture) would one day take nature

82

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 16: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 16/45

to the limit to make her yield up her secrets. It systematically devalued

efficient causes in favor of formal and material causes, further biasing

explanation in the direction of the conceptual and qualitative in place of

the mechanical and precisely measured, and elevating Aristotle's pre-

judice against cosmogony as myth into an arbitrary assumption that

accounts oforigins were somehow not a form of explanation-making

history not a real science, and treating the order observed in biology or

astronomy as a flat, atemporal schema, to which no temporally causal

account was relevant.47

Creationism was less rationalist, but more empiricist in outlook. It

saw nature, including human nature, in terms of possibilities, where

essentialism looked to regularities. But both views fostered a variety of

science, and both were deeply religious, the Aristotelian finding the

marks of divine wisdom in the invariance of natural patterns; the cre-

ationist, finding the hallmarks of divine grace in the emergence of novel-

ty,whether in nature or in the events of human life and

history.Neither

view was so narrowly framed as to be incapable of responding to criti-

cisms or countercases from the other, so both, in a way, were and remain

resistant to refutation. Bergson's bent as a philosopher was always to-

ward what could be validated in experience; and it was this penchant,

perhaps, that drew him most insistently away from creation as a uniqueevent and toward creation as an ongoing process. But even here Hart-

shorne is unrelenting in his criticism.

He takes Bergson to task for ignoring KarlPopper's concern "that if

no conceivable experience could falsify an existential assertion, it is not

empiricalin the usual sense."48 The criticism is not that

Bergsonhas

committed himself to views that are unfalsifiable but that he has given

preference to the view that seems to him to be best confirmed by our

knowledge and experience. The complaint is that Bergson has betrayed

metaphysics by appealing to experience for validation of his insights.

Bergson, Hartshorne writes, "seems not to see Popper's point...", as

though Popper's Conjectures and Refutations (London, 1963) lay openbefore Bergson. But why should Bergson's metaphysics observe Hart-

shorne's restrictions-especially if they bring it up against Popper's legiti-mate concern that unfalsifiable claims seem to say nothing about the

world?It is odd to invoke Popper, of all philosophers, to show both that

metaphysical claims are nonempirical, and that that is what they oughtto be.

Capek argues, very much in the spiritof Bergson, that creationism is

not crucially refutable, since all the evidence that seems to converge on

a first moment of time can be taken as pointing not to an absolute

origination of nature but to one first moment in what might have been

a series of Big Bangs, cataclysmically followed, in an immense celestial

rhythm, by successive occurrences of a BigCrunch. The most Capek will LennE.Goodman

83

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 17: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 17/45

PhilosophyEast&West

say is that the evidence is compatible with absolute origination,and that,

in turn, with theistic explanations. We can go a step farther. For the

evidence can be read not merely as compatible but as suggestive of

creation: creation is a possible hypothesis, and may be argued to be the

most acceptable, on the basis of its observed outcome, that is, the actual

character of nature. When the argument takes such a turn, Bergson'semphasis on continuing creation becomes most relevant, not as an

alternative to the unique event that most clearly manifests the absolute

insufficiency of the finite and determinate to originate itself, but as a wayof access to the character of divine creativity, a way that does not

arbitrarilyconfine the divine creative act to a unique and remote occa-

sion in the past.49 Again the move is hardly unprecedented. The dailyHebrew liturgy argues playfully "Who in His goodness reneweth each

day, continually, the act of creation, as it is said, 'To Him who maketh

great lights, for His favor is eternal."50 If we find creativity in all emer-

genceand do not

regardthat

creativityas the blind outcome of

mechan-ics or take its immanence as the mark of self-sufficiency but as the

hallmark of pervasive grace, the idea of divine creation remains fruitful

for us in all our inquiries.It is in this spiritthat we should relate Bergson'sideas about creativity, say, to Maimonidean creationism and specificallyto Maimonides' affirmation,following the hints of Saadiah, of the Rabbis,and of Scripture,that nature, in both its rational and its arbitraryseeming

aspects, is the overt expression through which God's character is made

manifest to us51-or, in more familiarterms, that nature is an epiphany.It is true that absolute creation will never be verified or falsified

conclusively.But the same is true of

any categorical claim, includingall

the factual claims of science, since any hypothesis can be modified to

account for seemingly conflicting evidence. The real question is how

much damage must be done to the fabric of our knowledge, how much

evidence must be explained away, how deep under the carpet must

experience as a whole be swept to preserve a single, increasingly isolated

notion? The most we can say of any transcendental claim is that it is

confirmed or disconfirmed by the evidence, harmonious or inharmoni-

ous with the consilience of experience. And in these terms we can saythat in recent years the findings of cosmology and of physics in generaltend to confirm the world's origination and to disconfirm its eternal,

steady state existence-whatever metaphysical construction may be

put upon those facts.

What is sound in Popper's thesis is that we ought to be suspicious of

a claim for which no evidence can be specified pro or con. Such a claim

is too well hedged to be taken as a commitment. But,as I showed years

ago, it was the creationists who brought concern with falsifiability(al-

though they did not call it that) to metaphysics-when first al-GhazalTand then Maimonides52criticized neoplatonism on the grounds that the

84

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 18: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 18/45

neoplatonic God seemed to make no detectable difference in the world:

the world seemed to be the same whether it existed eternally, as a re-

sult, say, of an immanent rationality, or through the transcendent ratio-

nality that neoplatonic theists claimed to share with their more scriptural(that is, more voluntaristic, creationist) coreligionists. The same criticism

can be returned (with a few hundred years' interest) to today's ProcessTheologians: creationists can cite evidence for the world's finite age in

support of their theism. In classical philosophy, from Plato to Philoponusto the high middle ages at least, such evidence was construed to include

evidence that the world or matter might be destroyed. Thus Philoponusused entropy, as well as he could understand it, and the apparent

changes observable in celestial bodies, to show that the world system

might run down, that the stars were not "simple substances" and there-

fore immutable.53Rather,the whole cosmos was corrosible, corruptible,

destructible, ergo contingent, transitory, not of the sort of being that

could endure forever or of its ownaccord-therefore,

created.Todaythe account is easier. We can cite evidence from the red shift, or from

apparent "echoes" of the original cosmic boom, supporting the thesis of

the world's origination. One family of metaphysical explanations for that

origination would be the world's precipitation from the fullness of God's

grace, an absolute creation, sharply contrasting the fullness of God's

being with the contingency of all finite and conditioned things. What

such an argument has in common with the older tradition (and with

Bergson)is commitment to empiric consequences of its theses.54 We saythat the evidence supports creation, but we know that the evidence

mighthave been otherwise. We know what sort of evidence would

count against origination.This Hartshorne finds offensive. He defines metaphysics "as the at-

tempt to deal rationally with noncontingent, nonempirical truths about

existence," and takes Bergson to task because, "He seems to think that

metaphysics is empirical."55But how, I wonder, are we to deal rationally

with truths about existence if we cut ourselves off from any experience

we may have? Limitedthough our experience may be, it is clear that we

will not get knowledge without experience. Hartshornecomplains that to

make metaphysics empirical is to make God just another contingent

being in need of explanation. But that is a plain confusion. That our

knowledge is contingent (and corrigible)does not mean that its object is

such. Finiteexperience often leads us (as in morals, or in causal explana-

tions, or even in our talk about conscious subjects or persistent objects)

to project beyond the immediate givens of sensation. No thought police

prevent us from so doing. There will be problems about making any such

projection, and we can expect disagreements about rival outcomes. But

that does not leave us without standards of appraisal. Clearly some

philosophers make more coherent sense out of experience than others LennE.Goodman

85

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 19: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 19/45

do. But, if a truth is indeed noncontingent, it will be exemplified in

experience without exception or contradiction. Dispensing with experi-

ence will not strengthen metaphysics but weaken it. Indeed, it will de-

prive it of its subject matter, the materials and values it is to interpret,

organize, and explain.

Hartshorne argues that pure potentiality is no real thing, and thatpure nothingness is inconceivable. But creationists do not argue that the

world came from nothingness but from God. What they mean by ex

nihilo is that God's ultimate creative act was conditioned by no priorlimitation but only by the limitations inherent in finitude itself and in the

determinate character of the things to be created.56Leibnizexpressed it

well in the idea of compossibility. It is true, as Hartshorne argues, that in

itself possibility is a mere abstraction, resting for us on the negation of

something actual. But it does not follow that we cannot abstract com-

pletely from all the conditionality and givenness of things and conceive

the entire universe ascontingent.

Thisprecisely

is what Genesis calls on

us to do. It shows us, in the words of Avicenna, that existence itself is a

notion super-added to the given essences of all things. None of this (so

long as this is finite, that is, conditioned in any way) need have existed.

The world is not a necessary being, does not contain within itself the

conditions of its own perpetual existence. If a necessary being is to be

sought, as the condition or ground of all that is contingent, it must be

sought as the counterpart of the contingent. If philosophy begins in

wonder, there is no good reason why it should not at times begin with

wonder about why anything exists at all.57

JacobAgus

shows usvividly

where we would land if we followed in

the direction Hartshorne approves. He does this by translatingthe meta-

physical propositions of a Bergsonian eternalism back into the languageof ritual and myth, from which they are sprung and out of which Bergsonseeks escape into the cool Parisianair.Agus writes:

Bergsonwavers between the concepts of life and spirit .. a blind,cosmic

life-forcewhich is unconcernedwithindividuals, urposelessand ruthless ..

and ... the elan vital... conceived after the analogy of the human spirit ...

revealed nthe progressive efinementof man'sethical conscience and inthe

esthetic organon.... Thetension between the representation f Godas Lifeor as Spiritreflectsthe dichotomybetween Judaismand ancient paganism.The premonotheisticpagans celebrated the rhythmsof life in their cults.Therewere vegetationgods, dyingand coming back to life.... None of the

gods representedan ethicalabsolute.... InJudaism,God ... is Thoughtand

Justice,Loveand Sublimity....Itis in the hearts and minds of humanbeingsthat He isbest revealed.God is not subjectto the rhythmsof life.Theancient

agriculturalestivalswere givenfreshmeaning n the Torah.... The rhythmsof sacredhistoryweresubstituted orthose of nature.58

PhilosophyEast&West The act of absolute creation captures both the moral and the metaphysi-

86

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 20: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 20/45

cal absoluteness of God, as ultimate Cause and ultimate Judge, God of

history and the moral law as well as God of nature and its laws. It is in

recognizing the same one answer to the moral and the cosmological

quest for ultimates that monotheism overcomes the partiality of pagan

religiosity and integrates both life and the cosmos.59

Despite Bergson's New Testament rhetoricabout

Godas

love, Agusargues, the elan vital, even when manifested in the spirit of man, does

not adequately represent divine holiness, wisdom, reason, justice, or

power. Rather, it reduces God to the energies of nature (and culture!),no

longer merely cyclically conceived, but still pulsating with vernal and

destructive force, still to be celebrated as much in the orgiastic rites of

springand autumnal sacrifice, death and rebirth,as in chaste prayersand

pacific meditations or ardent but conscientious visions of the working

out of justice in history, the moral liberation of human life from tragedy.60Monotheism seeks one God where it finds one world; it pursues one

good-thesame law and existential deserts for all.61But

paganismcele-

brates all energies, whether creative or destructive; and neo-paganism

arrogates to itself the right or power to create the energies it celebrates,

and to assign them value and validity not for their merit or coherence

with one another in thought or in a life, but for the intensity of their

frissons.

Fortunately it is not necessary to follow Bersgon in the direction

Hartshorne so warmly approves.62ForBergson himself is uncertain on the

subject and leaves alternatives open to our judgment, even if we find

elements of his thinking about time that we cannot leave behind. The

central idea ofcreativity

and of theasymmetry

of time does notrequireus to abandon but in a way endorses the idea of the world's creation,

which can as readily be a liberating as a confining idea, depending on

whose mind it falls into for interpretation.63 Bergson himself did not

follow the elan vital in the direction of a neopagan naturalism, but de-

scribed God, in Creative Evolution, as a kind of "supra-consciousness";and in The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, he developed the

(quite Maimonidean64) dea of God as the Creator of creators. It is not the

idea of immanence that is inconsistent with monotheism in Bergson's

thinking, or it would hardly be appropriate for Agus to counterbalance

the elan vital with the

spirit

in the heart of man.65The trouble, rather, is

the reductionism-of God to good, or life, or "passage," power, Thought

or thing-of Thou to this. As Job (26:14) expressed it, after surveying the

awesome majesty of God's rule over nature, "These are but the fringes of

His doings, and how small a snatch of hearsay do we have of Him."

Toward the end of his life, Bergson wrote about the special role of

mystics in articulating morally and socially the meaning of divine love for

humankind-taking the Hebrew prophets as paradigms of his intent. He

also told of his admiration for Catholicism. His chief reason for rejecting LennE.Goodman

87

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 21: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 21/45

PhilosophyEast& West

conversion to that faith was equally telling: the rise of Hitler left him

unwilling to abandon solidarity with his Jewish roots when his people

were facing persecution and would soon be facing death for their con-

nection to a common past and to one another.66

III.The Mirrorof NarcissusGeorge Wald, a Nobelist in biology, for his work on the biochemistry

of rhodopsin, the photoelectric pigment of the eye, in recent yearshas developed his famous classroom lecture on nature or the world

into a kind of performance piece, presenting it for the scientists at Los

Alamos,67for public fora in many communities including my own,68and

at least on one occasion connecting it with the name of Bergson.69When

I was an undergraduate in his prizewinning biology lab course for non-

scientists, the lecture was known around Harvard,with Wald's encour-

agement, as "Fromthe Electron to Hamlet." Taken in reverse, it would

have seemed a reductionist sort ofthesis,

about man as a few cents'

worth of chemicals, or the like. But in the order that he gave it, it was a

humanistic credo about the construction of complexity out of simplicity,a Lucretianexercise in the issuance of life and splendor out of the merest

of subatomic lego-units, with never a nod in the direction of emergent

evolution, let alone orthogenesis, elan vital,or the Aristotelian priorityof

the actual to the potential. Inthe current versions, heard now by literallythousands of symposiasts and readily obtained in careful transcriptionsof the taped voice of the speaker, lecturing familiarly, always without

notes, never quite repeating the same words, all that is changed. The

materials are much the same as in the 1960s, with some newargumentsand illustrations;the order of exposition is identical. But the theme now

is the need for consciousness within, behind, beneath the cosmos. More

than one listener has asked Wald if he has changed his tune because he

is growing older, but he just smiles and says that he hopes he is growingwiser.

Wald's argument is that "we live in a life breeding universe," that

matter, as he once put it in a thought he shared with Einstein,"won in

the fight" with anti-matter, and so did, say, L-amino acids win out over

D-amino acids, although both of these symmetric kinds might have

seemed at the start to have an equal chance. Had the universe begunwith exactly equal parts of matter and anti-matter, all would have been

annihilated in the Big Bang. "But ... there was a little mistake in the

equality, of one part in one billion. And when all the mutual annihilation

had finished, one part in one billion remained, and that's the matter of

the universe."70Similarly, f electrons and nucleons were not so far apartin mass, the proton would not remain undisturbed by the behavior of

electrons and there would be no solid matter, no crystals, or complexstable compounds.71 Similarly(pace R. A. Lyttleton and Herman Bondi),

88

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 22: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 22/45

if there were a difference in the charges of a proton and electron, of

2 x 10-18e, where e is the actual charge of either, "that almost infinitesi-

mal difference in charge would be enough to overwhelm all the forces of

gravitation that bring matter together in our universe. So we would have

no galaxies, no stars, no planets...."72

Climbing the "scale of states of organizationof

matter,"Wald ob-

serves that only carbon, hydrogen, oxygen and nitrogen have the "abso-

lutely unique properties ... on which the existence of life depends,"73and

that without water's strange property of expanding when it freezes, ice

would sink and grow ever thicker on the bottoms of all bodies of water,

accumulating intolerably and making survival impossible there for life

forms. Again, a star much larger than our sun "would probably never

have a planet bearing life,"because its mass does not give it enough time

on the "MainSequence" for life to evolve.74Ingeneral, "we find ourselves

in a very curious universe. It possesses exactly those properties that

breedlife,"

and thatfact,

Waldargues,

in thegreat

tradition of natural

theology that stretches from Genesis to Paley, but with suitable hesita-

tion, ellipsis, periphrasis, preterition, and apology, is best explained by

consciousness, of which Wald says, "It has no location. It will never be

located"-much as Socrates answered, when his students asked where

he wanted to be buried:bury me wherever you like, ifyou can catch me.

"When this idea struck me, Iwas elated. Ienjoyed it immensely. But

I was also embarrassed. I thought, 'My God, Wald, senility is hitting youin a big way.' The idea violated all my scientific feelings. But it took onlya few weeks to realize that that kind of idea is not just centuries old but

millennia old in Easternphilosophies....

[C]onsciousness or mind is not,

as I had believed and most biologists tend to believe, a late product in

the evolution of life on this planet.... On the contrary, it was there all the

time. The reason this is a life-breeding universe is that the pervasiveexistence of mind guided it in that direction for a reason."75The warrant,

then, for connecting these thoughts with those of Bergson lies in a

distinctively modern interpretation of the idea that the symmetry of

time somehow brings God into contact or communion with Himself:

evolution/creation is working out a plan that links mind in the universe

with mind in us.

None of this is unfamiliarto philosophers, theologians, historians of

ideas. The thought that thought is responsible for nature is, as Wald

suggests, perennial, and not just in Eastern but in Western philosophiesand religions. There are problems aplenty in the claim, ranging from

matters of verification and interpretation to validation of its proven-ance-for it does matter whether this is just an idea that we have

suggested to ourselves, culturally, socially, mythically, to serve some

function quite distinct from its explicit content. But I want to focus on

a particular application of this trend of thought: it matters very much LennE.Goodman

89

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 23: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 23/45

PhilosophyEast&West

if we begin or end our search for God by looking in the mirror.Such a

move has become almost a standard topos in the literature of scientific

confessions.

A similar statement to Wald's was made on the same platform bythe biophysicist Harold Morowitz, then of Yale, who speaks of a "new

covenant" emerging gradually, "fromthe experiences of individualswhoseek to understand the world."76Morowitz is a bit more blunt than Wald:

he types the new covenant as pantheism and contrasts its revelations

with the moral and spiritual revelations of the ancient God that was

encountered as a person. He speaks warmly of Bergson and Spinoza, and

glowingly of Richard Lovelock's Gaia hypothesis as a religious opening:"The new pantheism" he writes, "reasons from science to a cosmic

intelligence that is not unrelated to our existence."77 What volumes are

spoken by that academic litotes-not unrelated to our existence! "What

we are discussing is the ascendancy of God, the waning of God, and the

rebirth ofgod.

Thesubject

matter is so awesome thatany attempts

in

this direction seem tinged with hubris. But if these matters are vital to

human existence and human happiness, then we must proceed."78This is not the place to wrestle with the curious greased logic of

Gaia-ism, or Morowitz' response to it.79"The bottom line," as Morowitz

draws it here, "is that our understanding of molecular biology, ecology,

geophysics, meteorology, and hydrology now makes it clear that the

detailed working of all the features of our planet is necessary for con-

tinuing life. This lends great force to the argument from design and urgesus one step further. The precise workings of all the different componentsto make

possible intelligentlife on earth

suggestthat the

planof the

universe somehow had us in mind."80 fthe argument is vital to human

happiness, then on Jamesian grounds, let Wald's hesitancy and humility,let hubris itself be damned.

Such protestations as those of Wald or Morowitz might seem wel-

come to theists, especially when they bear the authority of scientism,

confessing that it came to scoff but stayed to pray. John Eccles, a Nobel

neurophysiologist, is proud, in his GiffordLectures, to cite the argumentsof J. A. Wheeler81 that unless the universe were of a critical size, there

would literallynot be world enough and time for intelligent life to evolve:

"Forexample, the mass for 1011 galaxies with a total of 1022stars, givesthe time scale from Big Bang to Big Crunch of 59 billion years. If we

economize and have the BigBang producing the mass for one galaxy of

1011stars, which is still an immense universe, the time from BigBang to

BigCrunch is reduced to 1 year!"82Again the classic inference is to designand plan, intention, and ultimately (in Eccles' application of the argu-ment), to grace. But there is a fly in the ointment when we examine

Wheeler's elaboration of the impact of this argument, for it takes on a

familiarbut peculiarly subjectivist cast:

90

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 24: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 24/45

No search has ever disclosedany ultimateunderpinning,ither of physicsor

mathematics,that shows the slightest prospect of providing he rationale

for the many-storiedtower of physical law. One therefore suspects it is

wrongto think that as one penetrates deeper and deeper into the structure

of physics he will find it terminatingat some nth level. One fears it is also

wrongto think of the structuregoing on and on, layerafter layer,ad infini-

tum. One finds himself in desperationasking if the structure,rather than

terminatingn some smallestobject or in some most basicfield,or going on

and on, does not lead back in the end to the observerhimself, n some kind

of closed circleof interdependencies.83

Wheeler appropriately wonders whether the search for ultimate causes,

what Aristotle called first principles, is really a matter of finding ever

smaller particles and subparticles, that display no particularreadiness to

yield an answering simplicity-and no readiness at all to provide explan-

atory ultimacy in any other sense. But then, instead of saying that the

search forexplanations

mustexpand

itself to a search for other sorts of

ultimates than those of physics-must embrace the search for ultimate

values, a "why?"and "wherefor" as well as an "out of what?"-Wheeler

almost startlinglyturns inward, not to a critical examination of the condi-

tions of our inquiry (as in Kant or Freud),but to the self as the ground of

being. He does not pause to notice how the question has been shifted

from one of material composition to one of purpose, or seek to examine

critically whether the human mind, the all-judging observer, has the

capacity for the role it is addressing.Likethe born-again athlete offering testimony in the service of mus-

cularChristianity,

thenewly enlightened

scientist is welcomed in all

simplicity and innocence. Eccles writes: "Wheeler (1977) defines two

contrasting views on the genesis of the Universe: '... Life is accidental

and incidental to the machinery of the Universe.... Or... is the directly

opposite view closer to the truth?-that the universe, through some

mysterious coupling of future with past, required the future observer to

empower the past genesis? Nothing is more astonishing about quantummechanics than its allowing one to consider seriously on quite other

grounds the same view that the universe would be nothing without

observership."'84The dichotomy, of course, is a false one: that either the

universe is an accident or it is somehow devised by or for our minds. The

latter view is qualified by Maimonides as indeed the height of hubris, in

that it takes things more noble than we are-the celestial bodies-and

treats them as existent solely for our sakes.85 Eccles wants to link the

future to the past, but the means by which he does so seem to find the

meaning of the future and the power of the past in human observership.When we have reached this point, the eternalism that Hartshorne

prizes and elevates in Bergson'sthought and the sundering of the present

from the past by which Hartshorne breaks the cord that ties his philoso- LennE.Goodman

91

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 25: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 25/45

PhilosophyEast&West

phy of process to the views of Bergson, begin to reveal their character

and potential. For just as that eternalism threatens Bergson's broader

creationism, the radical and stridently defended sundering of the sym-

metry of time places at riskthe very values of human freedom, natural

contingency, empiricism, and the open future, in whose behalf-or

rather, on the basis of which-Bergson's theses of natural creativity andhuman freedom were argued. To explain: Hartshorne's eternalism was

meant to compromise divine transcendence and push Bergson in the

direction of immanence. But in the doubling back upon itself of the

human quest for explanations, we glimpse the outcome of an imman-

ence that is disconnected from any ultimate Goal or Source. BlindingGod in effect, reducing supraconsciousness to subconscious memory,and the groping of evolution to a rudderless themelessness that is called

creative only out of courtesy, nostalgia, or polite fiction was just the first

step of a progression. A nameless mechanism stands in the wings. Hart-

shornemay

think he hears ameaning

in thesongs

ofbirds,86

but the

deeper harmonies and rhythms of the cosmos as a whole, once his break

with Bergson is complete, will no longer sound as melody, since their

relationality,the inner intentionality of one moment toward another, has

been broken. The second step is the emergence of the self-selected

surrogate for the Unmoved Mover and the Highest Aim and Good, the

eager understudy for the role of God. The nameless mechanism has

assigned itself a name.

The anthropic principle invoked by Wheeler, and by many others, in

behalf of a kind of humanism compounds the fracture that processeternalism has

begun.Where ancient creationism

soughtthe end

prod-uct of creation in the first intention of divine thought,87 this modern

version misappropriates the Bergsonian symmetry of time, blocking it

before it can reach the absoluteness of divine purpose, making human

thought not just the aim but the condition and ultimate origin of nature.

What process philosophy contributes here, perhaps most vividly in Hart-

shorne's thinking, is a demotion of God to the role of "fellow learner,"and a corresponding and compensatory elevation of man to fill God's

shoes. Advocates of this view, seeking a heritage for it, call it Socinian,

using the term in a sense that Leibnizdefines lucidly,as the tendency "to

conceive of God (on the pretext of upholding his liberty) ... as a man

who takes decisions according to the circumstances."88 It is by con-

ceiving God "on human lines,"as Leibnizputs it,89 hat the new, Process

Socinians render divinity no more than a developing condition, a mod-

ality perhaps, of the world's flux.

Freeman Dyson's GiffordLectures of 1985 are a fairly representative

example of the theological appropriation of the neo-Socinian approach.

Dyson invokes the anthropic principle to find in "meta-science" a mean-

ing and purpose for existence that science itself, as he construes it, seems

92

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 26: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 26/45

to debar: "laws of nature can be explained if it can be established that

they must be as they are in order to allow theoretical physicists to

speculate about them."90Dyson links his "taste" for the anthropic princi-

ple, which "seems to imply an anthropocentric view of the cosmos," with

a conception of the divine which he labels Socinian and attributes to the

influenceof

Hartshorne:

IfIremembercorrectlywhat Hartshorneaid,the main tenet of the Socinian

heresyisthat God is neitheromniscient noromnipotent.He learnsandgrowsas the universe unfolds. I do not pretend to understand the theologicalsubtleties o which thisdoctrine leadsifone analyzes t indetail.Imerely ind

it congenial,and consistentwith scientificcommon sense. Ido not makeanycleardistinctionbetween mind and God. Godiswhat mind becomes when it

has passedbeyondthe scale of ourcomprehension.Godmay be considered

to be eithera world-soulora collection of world-souls.We are the chief inlets

of Godon this planetat the present stage of hisdevelopment.We may later

growwith himas he

grows,or we

maybe left behind.As Bernal

aid,"That

may be an end or a beginning,but from here it is out of sight."91

There is, of course, more to Hartshorne than this, but what Dyson ap-

propriates from Hartshorne and finds vital in his thought is the ability to

place God not within thought but within reach. Quoting from Dante, but

subtly shifting Dante's sense, Dyson concludes his final lecture:

Canyou not see that we are the worms,each one

Born o become the angelic butterflyThat lies defenseless to the JudgmentThrone.

Among Process Theologians, the idea of taking God off His pedestaloften has a marked Christian (or even Jewish) emotive appeal, since it

opens up the devotional, mystical Christian (and Kabbalistic)theme of

divine suffering.But the development of that theme, especially among its

scientistic admirers, proves anything but Judeo-Christian.The image of

the butterfly is lovely, disarming hearers who might have thought that

theoretical physicists never speak of butterflies, let alone quote Dante.

But some ambiguity remains whether the soul's flight is to stand before

the Judgment Throne, as Dante may have imagined, or to sit upon it. And

behind the image of the butterfly is the image of the sufferingand indeed

the dying god. Its roots are pagan, and its dynamic, as appropriated here,

often becomes neo-pagan. Forthe humanization of God is never unac-

companied, in the versions we are considering, by the divinization of

man. The reason is not just the need to fill the vacuum left by God's

dethroning, for to meet that purpose any surrogate would do. Rather the

reason is that the blurring of the subjective boundaries and objectivedistinctions between humanity and divinity is eagerly appropriated byclaimants to the divine role. Thus Dyson's modest, almost Aristotelian, "I LennE.Goodman

93

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 27: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 27/45

Page 28: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 28/45

purpose as the guiding and governing beacon of the whole-the Good

that all things have in them and strive to reach or realize in their in-

stantiated particularity, insofar as in them lies-the ship is now piloted

by a blind creativity that seems to have our name embroidered on its

cap. Time is now the absolute, and God is just another time-server. But

man is made the arbiter ofvalues,

and indeed thecreator

andjudge

of

the universe.

The pride of ancient and medieval theists was the discovery that the

long arcing line of creative emanation from the Divine led down to us

and back again through the miracle of human consciousness returningto its source in the Divine. But here the world is spun forth from our own

minds, and the return is to ourselves. The inability to trace time to a

source beyond itself is symptomatic of the shift in roles. The sufferingGod becomes the bearer no longer merely of human sins, but now of

human guilt, anxiety and fear. The father God is kept on too, at times, to

hear theplaints

ofJob,

since these will not be shoulderedby

the new

man in the head office. But wherever vitality, creativity, emergence,

youth, spring, life, or sustenance are found, the New Boss will be the one

to take the credit.

For hubris there is always one more step, and that step is taken, not

atypically, by Bernhard Rensch, an astute but problematic evolutionary

biologist.94Rensch is not as innocent of Kant or Freud as the scientists

who seek to ground an amorphous idealism of pantheistic tinge on the

vaunted influence of the observer in quantum physics.95 He sees that

the subjectivism of the anthropic principle licenses not merely man's dis-

covery that the world was made for or

byhim, but man's

powerto invent

or reinvent himself as God. LikeWald, Rensch finds much that is attrac-

tive in Eastern philosophy, perhaps in part because, like others of that

penchant, he does not fully know the discipline such philosophies de-

mand of their adherents, and in part because he seems to expect that the

variety of idealism he finds in such philosophies (once decontextualized

and so deracinated) will not prove impenetrable to his projects of trans-

valuation and self-empowerment.

Speaking for the impersonality of what he will reckon as divine,Rensch's pantheistic drift seems somehow to render God not trans-

personal, as traditional ideas of creation and transcendence might lead

us to hope or to expect, but inhuman-at once dehumanized and all too

human. Rensch writes: "We are quite rightly brought up to think mod-

estly of ourselves.... But when we study man's phylogeny, it must also

seem to us extraordinarythat this species, Homo sapiens, with his 'god-like intellect,' as Charles Darwin called it, has emerged as the crown and

culmination of the whole process of evolution.... Not only has this

strange Homo sapiens come to an understanding of himself and the

universal laws; he has developed further godlike qualities, creating his LennE.Goodman

95

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 29: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 29/45

own new and complicated environment, changing almost the whole face

of the earth...." This Faustianrole brings responsibilities,not for unintell-

ectual toilers, or even for "a large proportion of so-called intellectuals,"

but for "those engaged in creative intellectual work," planning for the

future, developing institutions:they must become gods or demigods, the

masters of human destiny, rather than its slaves: "men have often re-ferred to themselves as gods, or demigods. Rulersamong the Egyptians,

Romans, Chinese, Japanese and Incas have done so...." Evolution is

completed, and "its apparently most developed of creatures," are readyto take charge.96 By a consummate, indeed Orwellian, irony, human

freedom and creativity, the very freedom and creativity in which Bergsonhad found the point of contact between man and God, are to become

the banners we shall follow, willingly, back to the closed society that

Bergson rightly named, prophesied against, feared, and faced with all his

courage. The gods we are to worship, and who will hand down our laws,

shall be ourselves-orrather,

our ownimages,

blownup

to thegigantic

proportions of idolatry by the puffing behind and within them of our own

wind. As Rensch writes:

Medicalskillcontinues to improve,eating habits are more sensible,homes

are healthier,better lighted,better ventilated.... The increasing empo of

scientificdevelopmentwill often lead to states of conflict.... This will lead

to a spiritualizationf the meaningand symboliccontent of ritesand cus-

toms.... In modernizedIslamic countries there is a strong movement to

have done withmanyancientcustoms;women have ceased to wearthe veil

and are now emancipated,and polygamyis abolished.Many communist

countrieshave broken withreligious radition,

and modern China hasgone

througha rapid ransformation f manycustoms. Examplesikethese show

what can and what willhappen in other countries. Ethicaland moral ideas

that do not conflict withscientific acts are the onlyones that willsurvive....

Thetendency to theosophy ... willpossibly ncrease.... A panentheism ike

that of medievalmystics maylinkreligionwithphilosophical iews.Inourageof space researchand increasingbiologicaland psychologicalanalysisof life,

many people willfind it more and moredifficult o imagineHeavenand Hell,

angels and devils-and it will become impossibleto imaginea god who

thinks like human beings,for such thinking s absolutelybound to certain

physiologicalprocesses in a complicated central nervous system. Hence,

manyhumanswillabandon

religionaltogether,or be content with Spinoza's'deus sive mundus[sic]'or Goethe's'God-Nature,'he HinduistBrahman, r

the BuddhistNirvana.Allthese processeswillprobably ake manycenturies.

Religiouscustoms, the worshipof a superhumanbeing to whom one may

pray in straitenedcircumstances,will be an urge, in spite of rationalistic

counter-arguments.But he whole of mankindwillfinallybe forced to realizethat it willhave to master ts fate by itself.

This apocalyptic litany of unilinear progress has already, in the two

PhilosophyEast& West decades since it was written, proved tendentious, more wishful than

96

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 30: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 30/45

prophetic, more conflicted than coherent in its prescriptions, more

stereotypic than incisive in its analysis of crosscurrents and alternatives

to its vision.97

This is not the place to seek agreement about who or what God is;

but, in the light of what is being made of the elan vital, at least in some

quarters,98a word is in order about what God is not: God is not us, oreven some subgroup, caste, or class of us. The symmetry that links the

future with the past does not transform creatures into their own creators,

although we do in our own ways create, and in a sense create ourselves,

not radically but more or less adequately. The asymmetry that divides

the future from the past does not cut it off completely and is not a barrier

to the holism of process, and so of meaning, causes, reasons, powers,

values, and potentials. It is not a barrierto God, to judgment or account-

ability, cutting off the future morally from the past. In the nature of the

case (inview of entropy and the fragilityand delicacy of what is complexand

subtly balanced),human

beingshave more skill at radical destruc-

tion than at radical creation. We know that we are not gods when we

detect the bias, ignorance, and intolerance of the very projects by which

the name of god is claimed for us, or smell the odor of the camps still

lingering on the clothing of those who come forward to claim the title.

We have, as the existentialists were fond of pointing out, some measure

of the freedom and responsibility of gods, but much less of the authority,and very little of the power. There will always be something more divine

in knowing how and when to die and suffer than in knowing how and

why to conquer and to kill.But even suffering and death will not make

us

gods.LikeRensch and Morowitz, Vaclav Havel is touched by the idea of

the complex interconnectedness of the fibers in the web of life, and

clearly also by the spiritof the earth ethic, perhaps a bit by a much more

ancient land mystique. But Havel also knows what we are not. Speakingof the not-yet alienated life-world that he calls our natural world, he

writes:

In this world, categories like justice, honour, treason, friendship, nfidelity,

courageor empathy have a wholly tangiblecontent, relating o actual per-sons and actual life.... The naturalworld,in virtue of its very being, bears

within it the presuppositionofthe Absolute which

grounds,delimits,ani-

mates and directsit, and without which it would be unthinkable.ThisAbso-

lute is somethingwhich we can only quietly respect;any attempt to spurnit, master it or replace it with somethingelse appears... as an expressionof hybris or which humans must pay a heavy price,as did Don Juanand

Faust.

To me, personally, he smokestacksoilingthe heavens is not just a re-

grettable lapse of technology.... It is a symbol of an epoch which denies

the binding importance of personal experience ... crashes through the

bounds of the naturalworld,which it can only understandas a prisonof LennE.Goodman

97

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 31: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 31/45

PhilosophyEast&West

prejudices.. an unfortunate eftover rom our backward ncestors,a fantasyof their childish mmaturity.Withthat, of course,it abolishesas merefiction

even the innermost oundationof our naturalworld:t killsGod andtakesHis

place on the vacantthrone,so that henceforth t mightbe science which,as

sole legitimateguardian,holds the order of being in its hand.... The fault is

not one of science as such but of the arroganceof humankindn the age of

science. Humanssimply are not God, and playingGod has cruel conse-

quences.... We have rejectedourresponsibilitys 'subjective llusion' nd in

its place installedwhat is now proving o be the most dangerous llusionof

all:the fiction of objectivity strippedof all that is concretely human,of a

rationalunderstanding f the cosmos, and of an abstractschema of a puta-tive 'historicalnecessity' ... and technologicallyachievable 'universalwel-

fare,' demandingno more than experimental nstitutesto invent it while

industrial nd bureaucratic actories urnit into reality.Thefact that millions

of peoplewillbe sacrificed o this illusion nscientifically irectedconcentra-

tion camps is not somethingthat concerns our 'modernperson'unless bychance he or she lands behind barbedwireand is thrown back drastically

upon hisor her naturalworld....The chimney 'soiling he heavens' is not just a technologicallycorrigible

designerror, r a taxpaidfor a bettertomorrow,but a symbolof a civilization

which has renounced the Absolute,which ignoresthe naturalworld and

disdains ts imperatives.So, too, the totalitarian ystems warn of somethingfarmoreseriousthan Western rationalisms willing o admit.Theyare,most

of all,a convex mirror... of its own deep tendencies ... not merely dangerous

neighbours,and, even less, some kind of an avantgarde of worldprogress.Alas,just the opposite.... Perhaps omewhere there may be some generalswho thinkthat it would be best to dispatchsuchsystemsfromthe face of the

earth and then all would be well. But that is no different rom a plain girl

trying o get rid of her plainnessby smashing he mirrorwhich remindsher

of it.99

Another specious remedy, if we don't like what the mirrorshows us,rather than smash it, is to bend and distend it to make its surface more

convex, blow up our image larger, so that at least in some moods we

forget that our own image is all that the shiny surface shows. As the

anthropic principle reveals most clearly, there is a tendency in all of us,when we look at nature, to project our own image onto the surface of

our object, a desire, like that of Narcissus, to turn nature at large into our

mirror,and then, perhaps, to reach into that mirror,enamored of what

we see there and desirous of getting closer to it, getting inside it, forget-

ting that it is just an image. The same illusion and attraction led Narcissus

on to drown. The Narcissus in us vainly wants to be the author, judge,and ruler of the universe. It paints itself as such in a form of subjectiveidealism and moral solipsism that is predicated on forgetting that the

power of an author is vitiated if his work is a delusion. The world itself

remains, the natural world, creation. Only its image is blurred by the

ripples we have caused on the waters, but its realities and requirementsare untouched. And the self, human nature, with its foibles and its graces,

98

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 32: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 32/45

also remains. The image that we saw was not ourselves, but just an

image, painted not by our minds but by the light. When it rises up to

meet us, what we touch is not the self but the water. The self (as all real

mystics know) is not caught but lost by self-absorption. It is recovered

only when we "objectify"-look away from our own image and toward

nature and otherpersons.100The move to metaphysics is the move from the reductive, partitive

question that seeks ultimacy in ever finer levels of analysis, at a cost of

ever higher orders of abstraction from the wholeness and thickness of

life, what Havel calls our natural world, and toward larger questions,where ultimacy is understood in more comprehensive terms. There is

nothing wrong with the partitive type of question, but as even Thales

saw, the millingof reality to ever finer stuff is not the only kind of quest,and success in answering its questions is no guarantee of skill in answer-

ing or even adequately framing questions of another kind. Metaphysics

requiresa kind of

disciplineand

chastityof mind that the

arroganceof

scientism does not prepare one for, although the humility of science

might. Followingthe suggestive remarks of Maimonides, Spinoza explainsthat there is an aspect of God or nature that we understand in terms of

intelligence, because we have intelligence, and an aspect that we under-

stand in terms of matter, because we have that too. But,he argues, there

are infinite other aspects-as there must be, in view of the exuberance

of being-which we can never know, because we have nothing in

common with them.101

What is engaging in Wald's or Wheeler's Bergsonian meditations is

the endeavor of a naturalist to seekexplanations

for the commodi-

ousness, coherence, even teleology of nature. Here the inquiries of sci-

ence and religion come together-the questions of Aristotle and the

questions of Job.102The intricate, intimate, inner connectedness of thingsis somehow the stuff of the relations that respond to our whys. But it

is childish sophistry to pretend that such anatomies are revealed by the

announcement that the stuff of those relations is there because we putit there. Plotinus had a far grander and more cosmic and conceptual idea

of mind than Bernhard Rensch or Freeman Dyson does, but he saw

clearly that the highest God cannot be mind, because, as he insisted,

even against Aristotle, mind is not the best of things.'03

NOTES

The author thanks Milic Capek, Jonathan Westphal, Steve Odin, and

the anonymous readers of Philosophy East and West for their valuable

suggestions.

1 - Charles Hartshorne, "Bergson'sAesthetic Creationism Compared to LennE.Goodman

99

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 33: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 33/45

Whitehead's," in Andrew C. Papanicolaou and Pete A. Y. Gunter,

eds., Bergson and Modern Thought (Chur, Switzerland: Harwood,

1987), p. 372.

2 - EnneadsV 7.1-2.

3- For Bergson's reflections on Zeno's paradoxes, see his "L'lntuition

philosophique," Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale 19 (1911);

reprinted in La Pensee et le Mouvant (Paris,1934). Bergson came to

Zeno's paradoxes and thus to the problem of time with the back-

ground of a promising mathematics student. Of his school days he

writes: "it was at Condorcet that I experienced the first and perhapsthe only hesitation of my life. Iwas attracted equally by science and

by letters; I felt an equal aptitude for mathematics and philosophy.And then, when Ihad decided for letters, my teacher of mathematics

came and made a scene before my parents, telling them Iwas about

to commit an irremediable act of folly." Forthe impact on Bergson's

thought of the ideas of JulesTannery,Jules Lachelier,EmileBoutroux

and others in subverting the claims of mechanistic science in generaland the mathematical, geometrical modeling of nature in particular,see Ben-Ami Scharfstein, Roots of Bergson's Philosophy (New York:

Columbia University Press, 1943), pp. 8-19.

4 - Confessions XI19-37.

5 - A Treatise of Human Nature (1739), ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (London:

1968, 1888), Book I,Part II,Section II,p. 31.

6 - See Albert EduardMichotte, The Perception of Causality,trans. T. R.

Miles and ElaineMiles (London:Methuen, 1963; first Frenched., 1946,

University Press of Louvain).Michotte wrote (p. 256): "If Hume had

been able to carry out experiments such as ours, there is no doubt

that he would have been led to revise his views on the psychological

origin of the popular idea of causality." Cf. the fictive dialogue be-

tween Hume and Michotte by D. C. G. Macnabb, "Michotte and

Hume on Mechanical Causation," in Hume and the Enlightenment:

Essays Presented to Ernest Campbell Mossner (Edinburgh:Edinburgh

University Press, 1974). From a Bergsonian point of view, of course, it

is not the immediacy of any impression of causal force that is essen-

tial to the critique of Hume but the relationalityand thus temporalityin the sense of duration implicit in the Humean notion of succession.

This relationality is concealed when Hume treats succession as the

mere occurrence now of one sensum now of another.

7 - My physicist friend David Yount has argued (in a private paper) that

the temporal moment should be envisioned "as an arbitrarilyshort

interval" and duration as "the sum or integralover a number of such

PhilosophyEast&West intervals." The profit is that the Laplacean fiction of a point instant

100

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 34: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 34/45

that is still somehow pregnant with the future (and indeed with all

possible pasts and futures) is eliminated, and the causal efficacy of

events at a given moment is not reduced to their logical relation to

all other events via a set of ontologically mysterious "laws."

8 - See his Discourse on Metaphysics 13; cf. to Arnauld,March 23, 1690;

to John Bernoulli, February21, 1699; all in Leroy E. Loemker, Gott-fried Wilhelm Leibniz:Philosophical Papers and Letters (Dordrecht:

Reidel, 1976), pp. 310, 360, 513.

9 - See M. Capek, "Leibniz'Thought Prior o the Year 1670: FromAtom-

ism to a Geometrical Kinetism,"Revue Internationale de Philosophie20 (1966):249-256.

10 - G. Lemaitre, The Primeval Atom: An Essay on Cosmology, trans. after

B.and S. Korff New York: Van Nostrand, 1950), pp. 18-19.

11 - Cf. Augustine, Confessions XIxxviii38: "Iam about to repeat a Psalm

that I know. Before I begin, my expectation is extended over thewhole; but once Ihave begun, whatever Ipluck off from it and let fall

into the past enters the realm of memory. So the life of this action of

mine extends in two directions, my memory of what I have repeatedand my expectation of what I am about to repeat. But all the while,

my attention is present with me, so that through it what was future

may be conveyed over to become past."

12 - See Johannes Itten, The Art of Color(New York:Van Nostrand, 1973),first published as Kunst der Farbe(Ravensburg:Otto Maier,1961); cf.

ErrolHarris,Hypothesis and Perception (London: Allen and Unwin,

1970), pp. 237-292. Bergson remarked trenchantly in his Huxley Lec-ture at the University of Birmingham, May 29, 1911: "When I openand close my eyes in rapid succession, I experience a succession of

visual sensations each of which is the condensation of an extraordi-

narily long history unrolled in the external world. There are then,

succeeding one another, billions of vibrations, that is a series of

events which, even with the greatest possible economy of time,would take me thousands of years to count. Yet these momentous

events, which would fill thirty centuries of a matter become con-

scious, occupy only a second of my own consciousness, able to

contract them into one picturesque sensation of light" (quoted inCapek, "Bergson's Theory of the Mind Brain Relation," in Papani-colaou and Gunter, Bergson and Modern Thought, pp. 139-140).

13 - An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), Section II, 16, pp. 20-21 (from the

1777 ed.); cf. A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Selby-Bigge, Book I,Part I, Section I, p. 6. Hume has the candor to allow that one who

had never seen a particular shade of blue would still notice its LennE.Goodman

101

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 35: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 35/45

absence from a continuous progression containing all other shades,

and would be able to supply the missing shade. He infers: "the simpleideas are not always, in every instance, derived from the correspon-dent impressions." But he evades the further inference that "simpleideas" and even "simple impressions"may be simple only superficial-

ly, subjectively, or in certain respects. And he treats the case as "sosingular, that it is scarcely worth our observing, and does not merit

that for it alone we should alter our general maxim." Hume does not

recognize how typical the case of the particularshade of blue actual-

ly is: All simple percepts are the achievements of integrative activity.The supposed simplicity of sensory intuitions is emblematic of their

givenness, their all-at-onceness, but even phenomenologically they

may be quite complex: no matter how often I have dived into cool

water, I can never anticipate the actual sensation I feel each time I

dive. The sensation is rich,complex, and for its moment all-engulfing.

Physically,intuitions are

invariably complex.Their

givennessis not

dependent on their supposed atomicity.

14 - Milic Capek, Bergson and Modern Physics (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1971),

pp. 30-39.

15 - See Capek, in Papanicolaouand Gunter,Bergsonand Modern Thought,

pp. 141-142.

16- It was a device of Hume's to designate the elements of a natural

event by different names, so as to demonstrate their logical indepen-dence on the basis of their logical discreteness. But this was achieved

only by ignoring the ontological unities in the case. When medievalphilosophers called cause and effect "correlatives" they were can-

onizing in logic the same natural relationship that Hume canonically

ignored.

17 - In Papanicolaou and Gunter, Bergson and Modern Thought, p. 140.

18 - Capek urges that "the volume of the present, or what may be called

'the mnemic span,' is variable." But he applies the point strictly

psychologically (Papanicolaou and Gunter, Bergson and Modern

Thought, pp. 141-142).

19 - Cf. Ali Dashti, In Search of Omar Khayyam,trans. L. P. Elwell-Sutton(New York: Columbia University Press, n.d.; reprintof London: Allen

Unwin, 1971).

20 - See Capek, Bergson and Modern Physics, pp. 226-236.

21 - Bergson, A Study in Metaphysics: The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle

L. Andison (Totowa, New Jersey:LittlefieldAdams, 1965), p. 211.

PhilosophyEast&West 22 - Bergson, The Creative Mind, p. 83; cf. Capek, Bergson and Modern

102

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 36: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 36/45

Physics, pp. 129-130. Memory, for Bergson, was not, of course, con-

fined to the mental realm; like Leibniz' 'perception', memory here

had something of the sense that metallurgists give the term.

23 - Hartshorne, "Bergson Compared...." in Papanicolaou and Gunter,

Bergson and Modern Thought, p. 372.

24 - See Alfred North Whitehead, The Concept of Nature (Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1920), p. 71, and the discussions led by

Margaret Masterman and Dorothy Emmet in The Pardshaw Dia-

logues: Sense Awareness and the Passage of Nature, in Process

Studies 16, no. 2 (1987): 91-92, 103-104. Under the influence of

quantum discoveries, Whitehead came in the end to quantize time;but Ithink in so doing he lost some of the value of his original more

Aristotelian and Spinozistic approach, that regards occasions as dif-

ferentiated more by the interconnectedness of their active constitu-

ents than by isolation from their environment.

25 - Essays in Science and Philosophy (New York: Philosophical Library,1947), p. 117; and Dorothy Emmet in The Pardshaw Dialogues, p. 126.

What Hartshorne values most highly in Bergson is the theologicalfoundation of this point of Whitehead's. Hartshorne writes: "But

Bergson is consistent in taking preservative becoming as the para-

digm of reality.Thiswas a great step." "BergsonCompared," 373. It is

true that Bergson has a notion of the continued living presence of

the actions of the past. Butfor Bergson what mattered most was the

taking up of the past in life, not the embalming of its pastness.

26 - Hartshorne, "BergsonCompared," p. 377.

27 - Cf. Bergson's letter of March 25, 1903: "The more Itry to grasp myself

by consciousness, the more I perceive myself as the totalization or

Inbegriffof my own past, this past being contracted with a view to

action. 'The unity of Self' of which philosophers speak, appears to me

as a unity of an apex of a summit to which I narrow myself by an

effort of attention-an effort which is prolonged duringthe whole of

life, and which, as it seems to me, is the very essence of life."To denythe purchase of the past upon the present is to deny causality, justas clearly as it is a denial of freedom to

deny

the

power

of the

present to break away from the past. But, as Kant saw vividly, moral

freedom has no meaning without causality, since only through cau-

sality can the will effectuate its designs.

28 - Hartshorne, "Bergson Compared," p. 372.

29 - See my Monotheism (Totowa, New Jersey:Allenheld Osmun, 1981),

pp. 54-60; cf. "Context," Philosophy East and West 38 no. 3 (July1988): 307-323. Lenn E.Goodman

103

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 37: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 37/45

30 - To reduce the continuing presentness of the past to the unalterable

facticity of past events, as Hartshorne tends to do, is to substitute a

metaphysical truth for an empiric one-a kind of category error.The

echoes of the past die, blurred and averaged into forgetfulness bythe interference patterns of new and other old events. How little we

know of Elam or Ebla-how little we know of Amalek, despite theBiblicaladmonition to remember. Indeed, that admonition is accom-

panied by the admonition to blot out the name of Amalek. And it is

true, as Bergson saw, that the ability to forget is the counterpart and

condition of the ability to remember. But consciousness is not na-

ture;the presentness of memory is not the livingpresence of the past(which might lie, all unconscious, in the genes), and the unalterabilityof what is past is not the same as its persistence, but is its comple-

ment, the aspect no longer accessible to praxis.Who can deny, on

learning of the suicide of Primo Levi or the schizophrenia of some

child of thecamps,

thatHitler,long

after hisdemise,

isstill exacting

casualties, or that the Holocaust left no intact survivors.

31 - See L. E. Goodman, On Justice (New Haven: Yale University Press,

1991), esp. chaps. 4-5.

32- Under the rubric "The creativity of the past," F. BradfordWallack

writes:"There is nothing passive or static about objects, the anteced-

ent occasions which are the data of prehensions. Endowed with

creativity, they are in fact very forceful and energetic, aspects of the

efficient causation of new subjects.... Objects are not simply the

passive recipients of the actions of subjects, but the very activity

fueling the subjects" (The Epochal Nature of Process in Whitehead's

Metaphysics (Albany:SUNYPress, 1980), p. 140).

33- Cf. David Burrell,"Why Not Pursue the Metaphor of Artisan and

View God's Knowledge as Practical?" n L. E. Goodman, ed., Neo-

platonism and Jewish Thought (Albany: SUNY Press, 1991); JosephIncandela, Aquinas' Lost Legacy: God's Practical Knowledge and

Situated Human Freedom (Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University,1986).

34 - It is somewhat disingenuous for Hartshorne to rely on the logical

contrast of potentiality with actuality to ground the claim that thepotential is nothing actual. The ontic status of various kinds of poten-

tiality is quite varied. Aristotle located potentiality in matter and

found the boundaries of potential change in the specificities of mat-

ter. Surely,when we speak of dispositions, capacities, talents, and the

like, we are not excluding the instantiation of such potentials. A

disposition may intend a variety of possibilities, and these are virtual,

PhilosophyEast&West not actual. But it is absurd to claim that no actuality corresponds to

104

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 38: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 38/45

them, e.g., that the masa harina which might be made into tortillas

or something else (but not into a chili relleno) has no actuality at the

basis of its potentiality, or to suggest that its transformation from a

potential to an actual tortilla is taken simply as a "rebaptizing."

35 - See, for example al-GhazalT,The Incoherence of the Philosophers

(Tahafut al-Falasifa),2d ed., ed., M. Bouyges, (Beirut:Catholic Press,1962), p. 57, rem. 30, and my "Maimonides and Leibniz,"Journal of

Jewish Studies 31 (1980):214-236.

36- Spiritualismreveals its materialist backdrop in its pictorialism and in

other unceasing efforts to physicalize the "spiritworld"-to make it

answer to the epistemic categories of materialism and the sensuous

demands of empiricism. The same desire to body forth the transcen-

dent is present in the paintings of Inness as in the essays of Emerson.

It takes even more concrete form in the novelists' convention of the

appearance of some fetish or sign from the "Beyond" at the climax

of a chilling tale or, still more vulgarly, in the attempt to capture

ectoplasm on film, or the use of "state of the art engineering equip-ment" to validate claims about psychokinesis and "precognitive re-

mote perception." See R. G. Jahn and B. J. Dunne, in Papanicolaouand Gunter, Bergson and Modern Thought,pp. 271-307.

37 - Hartshorne, "Bergson Compared," pp. 373-374.

Ibid.,p. 373. As Wolfson showed, the idea of duration originates with

Plotinus and his project of discovering a mode of temporality that

would not be the mere measure and correlative of motion. Plotinian

duration, the temporality of the hypostatic Soul, is psychic ratherthan physical and mediates the transition from the atemporality of

pure thought to the temporality of nature, via the temporality of

discursive thinking. Monotheistic creationists, in a sequence that

includes Philo, Saadiah, Maimonides, Crescas, al-TabrizT, nd Albo,

adapted Plotinian duration as the archetype of (created) time, in a

way anticipating Bergson's discovery that real duration is not con-

fined to the realm of thought. See Enneads III ii 8 and H. A. Wolfson,

The Philosophy of Spinoza: Unfolding the Latent Process of his Rea-

soning (New York:Schocken, 1969; Harvard,1934), vol. 1, pp. 331-

346. The object was not to engage God in temporality but to derivetemporality from God. Quite the contrary with the new tradition.

Wallack writes (p. 197):"Thetime spans of actual occasions are sub-

ject to many a curious calculation.... Lewis Ford has produced a

diagram which ... 'standardizes the temporal length of an occasion,

which may be considered to vary considerably, perhaps between 20

milliseconds for a human occasion and 20-24 seconds for subatomic

occasions.'... There is even a debate as to the exact specious present, Lenn E.Goodman

105

38

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 39: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 39/45

the exact duration of the time-span of God.... Apparently God is to

become and perish faster than any earthly actual occasion." Wallack

cites discussions from Hartshorne and Cobb as to just how short the

divine specious present must be for God to be present at the begin-

ning and end of each worldly occasion to present it with a subjective

aim and receive it as objectively immortal. See The Epochal Nature,p. 197, and Rem B. Edwards,"The Human Self:An Actual Entityor a

Society?"Process Studies 5 (1975):203.

39 - See Emile Meyerson, Identity and Reality, trans. Kate Loewenberg

(London, 1930; Identite et Realit, Paris,1908);see Bergson'sreview of

1909, in Ecritset Paroles, ed. R.M. Mosse-Bastide (Paris:Presses Uni-

versitaires de France, 1959); cf. Capek, Bergson and Modern Physics,

pp. 108, 368-397.

40 - Capek, Bergson and Modern Physics, esp. p. 375.

41-

Philo, De Opificio Mundi 7.26; Philoponus, apud Simplicius On Aris-totle's Physics, 1169c: "time co-exists with the heavens and the world

... so the assumption of the eternity of time is refuted" in Philo-

ponus Against the Eternity of the World, trans. Christian Wildberg(Ithaca:Cornell University Press, 1987), p. 140; al-GhazalT: Duration

(al-mudda) and time according to us are created" (Incoherence of

the Philosophers, 56; cf. 66); Maimonides, Guide to the Perplexed, II

13. Averroes reports that "Most people who hold the world to have

originated hold time to be,originated with it" Incoherence of the

Incoherence (Tahafutal-Tahafut),ed. Bouyges (Beirut:Catholic Press,

1930), p.32.

42 - Capek, Bergson and Modern Physics, pp. 238-256.

43 - See Eliot Deutsch, "On the Being of Time," in Personhood, Crea-

tivity and Freedom (Honolulu:University of Hawaii Press, 1982), esp.

pp. 92-99: "Timeis uniquely performed in art"(p. 99).

44 - For the values tied up in the idea of creation, see my "Three Mean-

ings of the Idea of Creation," in D. Burrelland B. McGinn, eds., God

and Creation (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990),

pp. 85-113.

45 - Qur'an 28:88; cf. 2:115: "Whithersoever you turn, there is the faceof God"; see Emil Fackenheim, "The Possibility of the Universe in

al-FarabT,bn STnaand Maimonides," American Academy for JewishResearch 16 (1947): 39-70; reprinted in A. Hyman, ed., Essays inMedieval Jewish and Islamic Philosophy (New York: Ktav, 1977),

pp. 303-334.

46 - Maimonides, Guide to the Perplexed11 9, 21; al-GhazalT,ncoherence

PhilosophyEast&West of the Philosophers, 58-59.

106

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 40: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 40/45

47- Creationism proved more fruitful in these areas than steady state

notions, giving birth to the ideas of evolution, universal history, the

contingency of matter, and, of course, cosmic origination. Anti-

Darwinism in the nineteenth century did not defend Biblicism but

hid behind it to guard the Aristotelian essentialism in which Victorian

theism wasinvested. The real quarrel of today's anti-Darwinists, by

contrast, is with a kind of neo-Spencerian triumphalism that is

thought to take aid and comfort from evolutionism; see L. E.Good-

man and M. J.Goodman, "Creation and Evolution:Another Round in

an Ancient Struggle,"Zygon 18 (1983):3-43.

48 - Hartshorne, "BergsonCompared," p. 374-a rather limp-wristed for-

mulation of Popper's falsifiabilitytest!

49 - Classical Process Theology seems not quite so accommodating. That

is, it dismisses creation, where exponents of creation traditionallywelcome

creativity.Robert Neville is trenchant at this

juncture,see-

ing in the Whiteheadian dissatisfaction with divine creation and the

resultant division of God from creativity not only an arbitrarybifurca-

tion of the divine but a descent into a kind of positivism: "The basic

ontological problem," he writes, "isto account for the unity of manyand one through creativity.... Whitehead's response ... would have

to be that ... there is no decision responsible for the basic togeth-erness of one and many in creativity.... Creativity must simply be

accepted as something given. The issue here is whether the irratio-

nality of the category of the ultimate must be accepted.... IfWhite-

head accepts the irrationality of the category of the ultimate, he

accepts an irrationality in one place yet does not accept it in an

analogous one; he might as well say that events happen with pure

spontaneity and no causation. We rightly boggle at this. It is a

betrayal of rational faith"(Creativityand God:A Challenge to Process

Theology (New York:Seabury Press, 1980), pp. 44-45; cf. my Mono-

theism, pp. 61-69). The issue Neville poses is precisely the one posed

by Spinoza's insistence on the distinction between the self-caused

and the uncaused. Neville, now addressing Hartshorne,finds a lasting

significance in the idea of creation: "the important category at the

ontological level has to do with creation ex nihilo, not with creativi-

ty," he writes. "And at the cosmological level something like Plato's

irreducible contrast between being and becoming exhibits more in-

tensity for experience than the swallowing of being in becoming or

vice versa" (p. 50). The reason is that Plato's "irreducible"dichotomy

represents a balance rather than a reduction. Neville proposes a

synthesis of creation with creativity when he writes: "God is the

creator of every determinate thing, each in its own occasion of

spontaneous appearance. In contrast to God's ontological creativity, Lenn E.Goodman

107

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 41: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 41/45

cosmological creativity is the descriptive fact that the spontaneity, in

occasions brings unity out of multiplicity"(pp. 8-9); cf. Paul Weiss:

"To create is to make something be, to give it an existence. If So-

crates' existence does not belong to him, if it is not truly and fullyand indelibly his, then surely he was never created" (Beyond All

Appearances (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1974),p. 169). Weiss' comments are made in criticism of Thomism, but Isee

a powerful affinitybetween Maimonides' position and Neville's partlyThomistic response to Whitehead/Hartshorne. To explore this fullywould take us far beyond the confines of the present essay.

50 - From the blessings before the Shema: Ha-mehadesh be-tuvo be-khol

yom tamid ma'aseh bereshit, ka-amur: "le-'oseh orim gedolim, ki-le-

'olam hasdo," glossing Psalm 136:7, by stressing the use of the

imperfect tense and the linking of eternal and continuous grace or

favor (hesed) with the ongoing act of creating the "great lights" of

the heavens.

51 - See my "Matter and Form as Attributes of God in Maimonides'

Philosophy," in R. Link-Salinger,ed., A Straight Path ... Essays in

Honor of ArthurHyman (Washington: Catholic Universityof America

Press, 1988), pp. 86-97.

52 - See my "GhazalTsArgument from Creation," InternationalJournalof

Middle Eastern Studies 2 (1971):67-85, 168-188; and Rambam (New

York:Viking, 1976), pp. 175-204, on Guide 11 0-21.

53 - See Shmuel Sambursky, The Physical World of Late Antiquity (Lon-

don: Routledge, 1962), pp. 154-175; RichardSorabji,ed., Philoponusand the Rejection of Aristotelian Science (Ithaca:Cornell University

Press, 1987), esp. the chapters by Michael Wolff and LindsayJudson.

54 - Although Bergson did not share the positivist penchant for equating

meaning with verifiabilityor falsifiability,he was well aware of the

risks of vitiating or vacating metaphysical judgments by makingthem independent of all possible confirmation or disconfirmation. He

proudly and truthfully stated: "Ihave constant recourse to scientific

argumentation" (M. Gremil,"Reportof a Visit to Bergson,"Mercure

de France,pp. 108, 397 (1914),cited in Ben-Ami Scharfstein, Roots of

Bergson's Philosophy (New York: Columbia University Press, 1943),

p. 10).

55 - Hartshorne, "BergsonCompared," p. 374.

56 - Neville writes: "Apartfrom the relative nature the divinity gives itself

as creator in creating the world, God is utterly transcendent" (p. 8);cf. Maimonides: "every predicate we assign to Him either designates

PhilosophyEast&West His act or, if intended to apply to Him rather than His work, its

108

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 42: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 42/45

Page 43: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 43/45

son; see his Bergsonian Philosophy and Thomism,trans. M. L.Andi-

son (New York:PhilosophicalLibrary,1955)).When the Petain regime

agreed to collaborate with Hitler, Bergson returned all his French

medals and awards: "He stood in line to register as a Jew and wore

his six-pointed star with pride until the day of his death" (Agus,

Jewish Identity, p. 238).67 - See Los Alamos Science 16 (1988).

68 - "Lifeand Mind in the Universe,"in D. DeLuca, ed., Essayson Creativ-

ity and Science (Honolulu: Hawaii Council of Teachers of English,

1986), pp. 1-14.

69 - "Consciousness and Cosmology: Their Interrelations,"in Papanico-laou and Gunter, Bergson and Modern Thought,pp. 343-352.

70 - "Lifeand Mind in the Universe,"pp. 2-3.

71 - Ibid.,p. 3.

72 - Ibid.,pp. 3-4.

73 - Ibid.,p. 4.

74 - Ibid.,pp. 5-7.

75- Ibid.,p. 10.

76- Harold Morowitz, "Modern Science and Pantheism," in DeLuca,

Essays,p. 203.

77 - Ibid.,p.

209.

78 - Ibid.,p. 203.

79 - Cf.Morowitz,Mayonnaise and the Originof Life New York:Scribners,

1985); Cosmic Joys and Local Pain:Musings of a Mystic Scientist (New

York:Scribners, 1987); The Wine of Life and other essays on Society,

Energy,and Living Things(New York: St. Martins,1979).

80 - Morowitz, in DeLuca, Essays, p. 209.

81 - J.A. Wheeler, "The Universe as a Home for Man,"American Scientist

62 (1974):683-691; "Genesis and Observership," in R. Butts, J. Hin-

tikka, eds., Universityof Western Ontario Series in the Philosophy ofScience (Boston: Reidel, 1977).

82 - SirJohnEccles, The Human Mystery (Heidelberg:Springer,1979),p. 28.

83 - Wheeler (1977),cited in Eccles, Human Mystery, p. 29.

84 - Eccles, Human Mystery, pp. 30-31.

PhilosophyEast&West 85 - Guide to the Perplexed III 3; cf. Rambam, pp. 262-277.

110

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 44: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 44/45

86 - See his Born to Sing: An Interpretation and World Survey of Bird

Song (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1973).

87- As the Hebrew liturgy puts it, sof ma'aseh be-mahshavah tehilla:

What was last in the making was first in the design.

88 - The Leibniz ArnauldCorrespondence,

trans. H. T. Mason(Man-chester: Manchester University Press, 1967), p. 14, cf. 26.

89 - LeibnizArnauld Correspondence, p. 19.

90 - Freeman Dyson, Infinitein All Directions (New York:Harperand Row,

1989), p. 296.

91 -Ibid., p. 119; cf. p. 295.

92 - See ErrolHarris,Nature, Mind and Modern Science (London: Allen

and Unwin, 1968; 1954), p. 398.

93 - See Adolf Grunbaum, "The Pseudo-Problem of Creation in PhysicalCosmology," Philosophy of Science 56 (1989):373-394.

94 - Rensch's concept of the Rassenkreis gave evolutionary significanceto racialvariations among biological strains. His 1928 paper and 1929

monograph on the subject were bellwethers of German biology for

the 1930s. Introduced to the American reading public by Theodosius

Dobzhansky as one of the most penetrating theorists of evolution in

the twentieth century, Rensch was taken up by the racist physical

anthropologist John Baker, who appealed to the Rassenkreis to

ground the claim that it is "absolutely necessary" for scientists to

obliterate "alldistinction between races and species." See BernhardRensch, Evolution Above the Species Level (New York: Columbia,

1974) and Dobzhansky's preface; Das Prinzipgeographischer Ras-

senkreise und das Problem der Artbildung(Berlin:Borntraeger,1929);

John Baker,Race(New York:Oxford University Press, 1974), p. 83 and

nn. 891-894. See L. E.Goodman and M. J.Goodman in International

Journal of Group Tensions 19 (1989):221-243, 365-384.

95- Capek shows how Bergson, read in the light of de Broglie's 1928-

1953 outlook, undercuts the popular subjectivist readings of quan-tum phenomena: indeterminacy would reflect not the mere involve-

ment of the observer but the impossibility in principle of fixating the

ultimacy of change in a single, instantaneous velocity and location

(Bergson and Modern Physics, pp. 284-299; p. 300 cites an apprecia-tion of Bergson by Einstein on this point). Capek's fine argumentationwould hardly satisfy those who seek a free pass for subjectivism in

the findings of science, but physics itself is hardly relevant to their

quest: if subjectivism holds, physics (including the indeterminacy

principle) lacks the authority they seek to build on. LennE.Goodman

111

This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.72.222 on Sat, 24 Nov 2012 03:27:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 45: (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

7/28/2019 (Bergson) Time, Creation, & the Mirror of Narcissus

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/bergson-time-creation-the-mirror-of-narcissus 45/45

96 - Homo Sapiens: FromMan to Demigod (New York:Columbia Univer-

sity Press, 1972), pp. 158-161.

97- For the example of the Islamic lands, see my review of Albert

Hourani's Arabic Thought in the LiberalAge, in The International

History Review 8 (1986):107-111.

98 - I emphasize that my concern here is not with implications of Berg-son's views, but with applications of them.

99 - Vaclav Havel, "Anti-PoliticalPolitics," n John Keane,ed., CivilSocietyand the State (London:Verso, 1988), pp. 381-398; I quote from pp.383, 386, 389-390.

100 - An old Hasidic story tells of the sage who instructs a young man to

look through the window. "What do you see?" he asks. "People,"the

young man answers. Turningthe youth around to face a mirror, he

sage asks again, "Now what do you see?" "Only myself." "And what

made the difference?"Silver. As I write, the new Czechoslovak gov-ernment that Vaclav Havel helped to found and rose to lead is

contracting to sell off its excess tanks to Syria-ironic evidence of

the truth in Havel's words that the smokestack staining the horizon

is not just some aberration but an almost organic outgrowth of the

land we live on, more like a cancer that must be cut out than like a

blemish that may be salved or masked.

101 - Spinoza, Ethica,PartI, Definition 6; Propositions 9, 10.

102 - See The Book of Theodicy, Saadiah Gaon's Commentary on Job,

trans. L.E.Goodman (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1988), esp.,p. 392, and my introduction, pp. 100-119.

103 - Enneads VI9.2; cf. I7.1, 8.2.8, V 1.5; and Republic 509B.

PhilosophyEast&West