art-as-such the sociology of modern aesthetics

Upload: alihadian

Post on 06-Jul-2018

222 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    1/27

     

    Art-as-Such: The Sociology of Modern AestheticsAuthors(s): M. H. Abrams

    Source: Bulletin of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, Vol. 38, No. 6 (Mar.,

    1985), pp. 8-33

    Published by: American Academy of Arts & Sciences

    Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20171773

    Accessed: 24-03-2016 00:03 UTC

     

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

    http://about.jstor.org/terms

     

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted

    digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about

    JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    American Academy of Arts & Sciences is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extendaccess to Bulletin of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    2/27

     Stated Meeting Report

     Art-as-Such: The Sociology

     of Modern Aesthetics

     M. H. Abrams

     For the last two centuries the professional

     philosophy of art, and more recently the prac

     tical criticism of the various arts, has been

     grounded on a theory which, for easy reference,

     I shall call art-as-such. This theory uses a very

     distinctive terminology to make the following

     claims:

     (1) Art is used as a term interchangeable

     with the fine arts, which consist primarily of

     five arts: poetry (or literature), painting, sculp

     ture, music, and architecture. The considera

     tion of these essentially related products

     constitutes an area of inquiry which is sui generis.

     (2) What defines a work of art is its status

     as an object to be contemplated, and contem

     plated disinterestedly ? that is, attended to as

     such, for its own sake, without regard to the

     personal interests or the possessiveness or the

     desires of the perceiver, and without reference

     to its truth or its utility or its morality. A work

     of art may or may not be true to the world or

     serve practical ends or have moral effects, but

     such considerations are held to be supervenient

     upon (or in some views, destructive of) the

     defining experience ? that is, the absorbed and

     disinterested contemplation of the product for

     itself, simply as a work of art.

     (3) A work of art is accordingly described

     as an object that is self-sufficient, autonomous,

     independent. It is asserted to be an end in it

     self, not a means to an external end, and its

     artistic value is said to be intrinsic, not extrin

     sic, to its own being. The work, in other words,

     is conceived as an entity that exists simply in

     order to be looked at or read or listened to with

     an absorbed, exclusive, and disinterested at

     tention.

     8

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    3/27

     One can illustrate such theories by two terse

     but comprehensive statements. One is by T E.

     Hulme, whose views had an important forma

     tive influence on T. S. Eliot and the American

     New Criticism that began about 1930. Con

     templation, Hulme says, is a detached interest.

    The object of aesthetic contemplation is

     something framed apart by itself and regard

     ed without memory or expectation, simply

     as being itself, as end not means, as individu

     al not universal.

     The other is a felicitous summation by Iris

     Murdoch (a practicing novelist as well as a

     philosopher) in her Romanes Lecture on art

     in 1976:

     Good art [provides the] clearest experience of

     something grasped as separate and precious

     and beneficial and held quietly and unpos

     sessively in the attention.

     Such formulations are usually presented by

     aesthetic philosophers and critics as universal

     and timeless truths about works of art, and we

     tend to think of the history of art theory as a

     sustained movement toward the triumphant dis

     covery of these truths, sidetracked and delayed

     by various false leads. The historical facts,

     however, make this view a dubious one. For

     more than two thousand years after the philo

     sophical consideration of one or another of the

     arts was inaugurated by Plato and Aristotle,

     theorists and critics did not even class together

     the diverse products that we now identify as the

     fine arts. Instead, they grouped one or another

     of these arts with mathematics or with the

     natural sciences or with a practical art such as

     agriculture or shoemaking. They proposed no

     terms for specifying a distinctive or essential

     artistic property, nor for talking about works

     of art in a way that undertook to be distinctive

     for that class and exclusive of all other human

     artifacts. Instead, they discussed one of the arts

     at a time; and when they paralleled that art to

     another of what we now call the fine arts ?

     9

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    4/27

     especially poetry to painting?it was for limit

     ed comparative purposes, and with reference

     only to selected features. And during those two

     millennia, it occurred to no thinker to assert

     that a product of even one of the human arts

     exists in order to be contemplated disinterest

     edly, for its own sake, without reference to

     things, events, human beings, purposes, or ef

     fects outside its sufficient and autonomous self.

     The historical fact is that the theory and

     vocabulary of art-as-such was introduced, quite

     abruptly, only some two or three centuries ago

     into what had hitherto been a relatively con

     tinuous development of the traditional views

     and terminology that philosophers and critics

     had inherited from Greek and Roman antiq

     uity. And in retrospect, it becomes clear that

     the revolution effected in the theory of art in

     volved a replacement of the implicit understruc

     ture of traditional theory by a radically different

     understructure.

     Theorists of the various arts, from classical

     Greece through most of the eighteenth centu

     ry, whatever their divergencies, had assumed

     the maker's stance toward a work of art, and

     had analyzed its attributes in terms of a con

     struction model. That is, they posited a poem

     or any other work of art to be an opus, a thing

     that is made according to a techne or ars, that

     is, a craft, each with its requisite skills for select

     ing materials and shaping them into a work

     designed to effect certain external ends, such

     as achieving pleasure or instruction or emotion

     al effects on an audience, as well as for adapt

     ing the work to a particular social occasion or

     function. It is clear that from the viewpoint of

     this construction model, the patent differences

     between the materials and practical skills of a

     poet, a painter, a sculptor, a musician, or an

     architect would keep these diverse occupations

     and products from being classified together in

     any systematic fashion, and for other than limit

     ed purposes. The critical undertaking, conse

     quently, was to deal with a single art ?most

     often, in classical time, poetry or a subclass such

     as tragedy; and the critical treatises were

     designed at least as much to guide a poet in

     10

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    5/27

     writing a particular kind of good poem as to

     help a reader to judge whether, and in what

     ways, the poem is good or bad. In this orienta

     tion to the making of a poem, Aristotle's Poet

     ics, whatever its important differences, is

     congruent with the views of Horace, whose

     enormously influential Ars Po?tica is explicitly

     a how-to document; that is, it is a verse-letter

     addressed to a novice instructing him how to

     write poems that will appeal most widely and

     enduringly to a discriminating readership. In

     this aspect of their treatises, both these writers

     are at one with the rhetoricians and with Lon

     ginus; and all of these thinkers together estab

     lished the basic mode and operative terms for

     dealing with the verbal, and later the plastic

     and musical, arts that persisted, without radi

     cal innovations, through the seventeenth

     century.

     In sharp contrast, theories of art-as-such

     tacitly presuppose, not the maker's stance to his

     work in process, but the perceiver's stance to

     the finished product; and they formulate their

     discussion not on a construction model, but on

     a contemplation model. That is, they assume

     that the paradigmatic situation, in defining and

     analyzing art, is that in which a lone perceiver

     confronts an isolated work, however it happened

     to get made, and simply attends to the features

     that it manifests to his exclusive attention.

     What I want to do is to sketch the emergence

     of the point of view and operative vocabulary

     of art-as-such, and then to investigate some of

     the attendant conditions, both social and in

     tellectual, that may explain why, after so many

     centuries of speculation, this radical innovation

     appeared suddenly just when it did and why

     it developed rapidly in just the way it took.

     /.

     The perceiver's stance and the contemplation

     model were not products of late nineteenth

     century aestheticism, but of the eighteenth cen

     tury. More precisely, they appeared at the end

     of the first decade of the eighteenth century,

     in the writings of Joseph Addison and of the

     third Earl of Shaftesbury; only eighty years

     11

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    6/27

     later, in 1790, they had developed into the full

     modern formulation of art-as-such in Im

     manuel Kant's Critique of Aesthetic Judgment.

     Let me stress what, for our enterprise, are

     salient features of Kant's theory. Despite its

     epoch-making importance for the philosophy

     of art, there is hardly a single observation about

     the nature and experience of an aesthetic ob

     ject that Kant did not find in his eighteenth

     century precursors, English and German, be

     ginning with Addison and Shaftesbury In fact,

     Kant does not even argue for, but simply ac

     cepts, certain concepts, already current, and de

     votes himself to grounding and systematizing

     these concepts by showing how the uniquely

     distinctive aesthetic experience (what he calls

      the pure judgment of taste ) is possible, as he

     puts it, a priori ? that is, how it can be account

     ed for by reference to the faculties and their

     operations that the mind brings to all its ex

     perience. And his theory relies squarely and ex

     clusively on the perceiver's stance and the

     contemplation model. As Kant posits the situ

     ation that he assumes to be paradigmatic for

     the philosophy of aesthetics: a pure judgment

     of taste combines delight or aversion immedi

     ately [i.e., without the intervention of concepts ]

     with the bare contemplation [Betrach

     tung] of the object irrespective of its use or of

     any end. Only after he has established this

     frame of reference does Kant go on, in the sec

     ond book of his Critique, to discuss what he calls

     die sch?nen K?nste, or fine arts; his list of the

     major arts is the one that had recently become,

     and still remains, the standard one of poetry,

     painting, sculpture, architecture, and music ?to

     which he adds the other arts, prominent in his

     time, of eloquence and landscape gardening.

     In this second section of his treatise, Kant also

     introduces the topic of the production of a work

     of art. His aim, however, is precisely opposed

     to traditional constructive theories, which un

     dertook to establish the principles by which an

     artist deliberately selects and orders his materi

     als in order to effect preconceived ends. Kant's

     enterprise, on the contrary, is to explain how

     the producing artist, despite such concepts and

     12

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    7/27

     intentions, nonetheless manages, however unin

     tentionally, to achieve a product that meets the

     criteria already established by reference to the

     concept-free and end-independent encounter

     between a percipient and a ready-made aesthet

     ic work.

     In discussing the nature of the normative aes

     thetic encounter, Kant encompasses all the key

     concepts and terms that constitute the theory

     of art-as-such in our own time. Crucially, the

     percipient's aesthetic judgment is, he says, dis

     interested or a pure disinterested delight, in

     the sense that it is purely contemplative (bloss

     kontemplativ), hence impartial ?that is, it is free

     of any reference to the interests or acquisitive

     ness or desires of the perceiver, and is indiffer

     ent even to the reality of the thing that is

     represented in the mode of art. The object con

     templated, Kant says, pleases for its own sake

    (f?r sich selbst), in strict independence from what

     he calls the external ends of utility or of moral

     ity. A fine art, accordingly, is intrinsically fi

     nal, devoid of an [extrinsic] end. In Kant's

     overall view, a human work of art, no less than

     a natural object, is to be regarded as having

     no end other than simply to exist, to be just

     what it is for our disinterested aesthetic con

     templation.

     Aspects of Kant's theory were quickly adopt

     ed and developed by a number of German

     metaphysicians, including Schiller, Schelling,

     Hegel, and Schopenhauer, and so entered the

     mainstream of aesthetic philosophy. What needs

     to be stressed is the rapidity and completeness

     of this Copernican revolution in the theory of

     art. In the course of a single century a great

     variety of human products, from poetry to ar

     chitecture, conspicuously diverse in their me

     dia and required skills, as well as in the occasion

     and social function of individual works within

     each art ?products of arts which hitherto had

     been grouped with diverse human crafts, or

     even sciences ? came to constitute a system of

      the fine arts ; that is, a single, essentially relat

     ed, and unique class of products. The construc

     tion model, which had treated each of the arts

     as a procedure for selecting and adapting its

     13

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    8/27

     distinctive elements to preconceived ends and

     uses, was replaced by the contemplation model,

     which treated the products of all the fine arts

     as ready-made things existing simply as objects

     of rapt attention. And the essential feature

     predicated of the fine arts, setting them off from

     all cognitive, practical, and moral pursuits, was

     that each work is to be experienced disinterest

     edly, for its own sake, unalloyed by reference

     to the world, or to human life or concerns, or

     to any relations, ends, or values outside its all

     sufficing self.

     A conceptual revolution so sudden and dras

     tic cannot be plausibly explained as an evolu

     tion of the traditional ideas about the arts; the

     orientation and operative terms of art-as-such,

     as I have pointed out, were entirely alien to that

     tradition. To account for the revolution we

     must, I think, turn to external factors which

     enforced, or at least fostered, the new way of

     thinking. Let us pose this question: Was there,

     just preceding and during the eighteenth cen

     tury, a radical alteration in the social conditions

     and social uses of the diverse products that came

     during that period to be grouped as the fine

     arts ? changes both concurrent and correlative

     with the conceptual changes I have outlined?

     This is, broadly speaking, a question concern

     ing the sociology of art; but whereas altering

     social conditions have often been used to ex

     plain changes in the subject matter, forms, and

     styles of practicing artists, I shall instead ad

     vert to social conditions in order to explain a

     drastic change in the general theory of art ? that

     is, in the focal concepts by which the arts were

     identified, classified, and systematically

     analyzed.

     //.

     A conspicuous phenomenon in the seven

     teenth and eighteenth centuries was the rapid

     spread of a mode of life, hitherto limited to a

     privileged few, that I shall label connoisseur

     ship. By this term I mean the devotion of part

     of one's leisure to the study and enjoyment of

     the products of an art for the interest and pleas

     ure they afford. Since the attitude and theory

     14

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    9/27

     of art-as-such emerged in England and was de

     veloped in Germany, I shall focus on the so

     cial phenomenon of the spread of

     connoisseurship in those two countries.

     We can begin in the seventeenth century with

     the introduction of two new terms from the

     Italian into the English critical lexicon. The first

     term was gusto, translated as taste, and applied

     in the metaphorical sense of a capacity to

     respond to the beauty or harmonious order of

     objects, whether natural or artificial. This

     responsiveness was considered to be an innate

     sensibility, inherited by individuals in various

     degrees, yet capable of being trained so as to

     constitute a socially desirable good taste or a

      polite (that is, a polished, upper-class) taste;

     and even of being so informed by the acquired

     knowledge of the rules of a particular art that

     it becomes a just taste or correct taste. This

     new term quickly became a staple in critical

     discussion, where it obviously served to empha

     size the perceiver's point of vantage to a finished

     artifact. (Note that in 1790 Kant labeled the

     normative aesthetic response by the deliberately

     paradoxical phrase: a pure judgment o? taste?)

     The second, and related, word from the

     Italian is virtuoso. This was introduced into

     the English vocabulary in 1622 by Henry

     Peacham, in his book on the requisites of an

     upper-class education that he entitled The Com

     plete Gentleman. Men who are skilled in such

     antiquities as statues, inscriptions, and coins,

    Peacham says, are by the Italians termed vir

     tuosi? In the course of the seventeenth century,

     the term virtuoso came to be applied to a

     mode of life increasingly engaged in by gen

     tlemen of the leisure class who applied them

     selves to one or both of two pursuits. One

     pursuit was collecting, and developing a degree

     of expertise about, the curiosities of natural

     history and the contrivances of contemporary

     technology. The other was collecting, and de

     veloping an informed taste for appraising, var

     ious artifacts, which included an extraordinary

     range of rarities and bric-a-brac, but most

     prominently paintings and statuary. By the end

     of the seventeenth century, the term virtuoso

    15

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    10/27

     had already become derogatory, largely because

     of the devastating attacks by Restoration wits

     against the pedantry and fondness for natural

     and artificial oddities by the science virtuoso.

     The life-style of the aristocratic art virtuoso

     nonetheless continued to flourish and expand

     in the eighteenth century, although now under

     a new title, this time imported from France,

     of connoisseur.

    The English painter Jonathan Richardson,

     with great fanfare, announced in 1719 a new

     science to the world which, he says, since it

     is yet without a name, he will call the

     SCIENCE of a CONNOISSEUR. He points

     out that in England, unlike in Italy, although

     there are many gentlemen of a just and deli

     cate taste in music, poetry, and all kinds of liter

     ature. . .very few [are] lovers and connoisseurs

     in painting. His great endeavor, he says, is to

     persuade our nobility and gentry to become

     lovers of paintings and connoisseurs. . .by

     shewing the dignity, certainty, pleasure and ad

     vantage of that science.

    Note two features of Richardson's exposition.

     He points out, first, that in England an

     aristocratic connoisseurship ?which he equates,

     using our earlier term, with a just and deli

     cate taste ? already exists for poetry and music.

     He now undertakes to add painting (and, later

     in his book, sculpture) to this class ? thereby

     linking, for his purposes, four of what were soon

     to be grouped as the fine arts. He does so,

     however, not on the ground that these arts pos

     sess a common nature or shared objective fea

     tures, but solely on the ground that they are

     all capable of a common function or social

     role ?that of yielding to the perceiver what he

     describes as at once an intellectual and a sen

     sual pleasure, that is enhanced for those who

     have learned to see these things. Second, he re

     veals that a prime value of connoisseurship, in

     addition to the refined pleasure that it yields,

     is its conspicuous uselessness, which makes it

     an index that one belongs to the leisure class ?

     in his term, to our nobility and gentry. Con

     noisseurship, Richardson points out, is not for

     the vulgar (that is, the common people). The

     16

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    11/27

     fact that it is a nonproductive, nonutilitarian

     way of employing one's time is what enhances

     the dignity of a connoisseur, making him al

     ways respected and esteemed.

    The virtuoso vogue in the seventeenth cen

     tury (as Walter Houghton has pointed out) had

     all along been strongly class-conscious, flaunt

     ing a leisure-time avocation free of material and

     utilitarian ends as a sign of social rank un

     achievable by what a number of virtuosi, like

     Peacham, had called the Vulgar and requir

     ing a cultivated knowledge and taste that serves

     to distinguish the polite class from social

     climbers. This defensiveness of the landed up

     per classes against interlopers from below is it

     self an index to the instability o? the established

     class structure in England, in an era of new

     wealth acquired by flourishing commercial and

     manufacturing enterprises. But the rapidly en

     larging class of the well-to-do in the eighteenth

     century were not to be foiled by such defen

     sive tactics. They simply took over from the

     nobility and gentry the cultivation of connois

     seurship, in part as a pleasant pursuit to fill a

     new-found leisure, but also, clearly, because it

     served as a prominent indicator of the gentle

     manly or polite status to which they aspired.

     In his Spectator paper on Taste, published in

     1712, Addison tells his large, primarily middle

     class readership that since the word taste arises

     very often in conversation, I shall endeavor to

     give some account of it and to lay down

     rules. . . how we may acquire that fine taste of

     writing which is so much talked of among the

     polite world. Such a deliberate cultivation of

     connoisseurship in the eighteenth century by

     a rapidly expanding part of the population

     resulted in a conspicuous set of social innova

     tions. I refer to the sudden appearance and ac

     celerating development, for the first time in

     Western history, of a great variety of institu

     tions and arrangements for making one after

     another of the objects of fine taste ?that is,

     products of the diverse arts ?accessible, usually

     for pay, to an ever-growing public. I have time

     17

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    12/27

     to give only a brief overview of this remarka

     ble but neglected social phenomenon, in each

     of what at that time came to be classified as

      the fine arts, that is, the nonutilitarian arts.

     And first, literature. In the latter seventeenth

     century, secular literature was still being writ

     ten largely under the patronage of the nobility

     and of political parties; an author was supported

     by writing to order, as an occasion or commis

     sion required, or else to gain favor with the pa

     tron or patrons on whom he depended for a

     livelihood. A century later, this system had

     given way to one in which booksellers paid for

     and published literary works, and so made

     authors reliant on the sale of their books to the

     general public. By Dr. Johnson's time, in Ger

     many as well as England, there existed for the

     first time a reading public in the modern sense,

     large enough to support, though in many in

     stances on a level of bare subsistence, a sub

     stantial number of writers by the books they

     bought. In this period new literary forms were

     invented to satisfy the expanding demand ?

     above all the novel, which at first pretended to

     be both true and edifying, but soon relaxed into

     the candid condition of being produced to be

     read merely for the pleasure in the fiction, by

     a readership now composed in large part by

     tradesmen, and especially the newly-idle wives

     and daughters of tradesmen. Another commer

     cial institution was invented, the circulating

     library, to make literature, and especially nov

     els, cheaply available to those who could not

     afford, or chose not, to buy them outright. This

     was the age also of the emergence and rapid

     development of various types of periodical pub

     lications. One was the critical review, which

     served to guide the public in the appreciation

     and appraisal of works of literature. Another

     was the magazine, so called because it includ

     ed a variety of prose and verse forms. A clear

     indication that such new publications owed part

     of their appeal to upper-class aspirations is the

     fact that the first periodical of this latter type,

     published in the 1690s, was named The Gentle

     mans Journal, and that in the next century the

     18

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    13/27

     most successful example (it endured until 1914)

     was named The Gentlemans Magazine.

     It was, then, in the eighteenth century that

     literature became a commodity, subject to the

     exchange values of the marketplace, with all the

     consequences of such a condition. But for our

     present purpose, note that both books and

     magazines incorporated literary forms that were

     bought to be read by a reader in isolation, for

     the interest and pleasure of doing so, indepen

     dently of any practical purpose or specific oc

     casion, and at a distance from their author and

     his circumstances. It was in 1710 that the term

     belles lettres was imported from France, to signi

     fy those literary works which were not doctri

     nal or utilitarian or instructional, but simply

     appealed to taste, as writings to be read for

     pleasure. In the course of time belles lettres

    became simply literature and replaced the

     earlier generic term poetry, which was based

     on the construction model; for in the root sense

     that endured through the Renaissance, poetry

    signified the art of constructing a poem ?a

     word derived from the Greek poiema, a made

     thing.

    Music. Through the Renaissance, composed

     music (as distinguished from folk-music) had

     been available to a broad, nonaristocratic au

     dience only in churches, or on the occasion of

     public festivals. The latter seventeenth centu

     ry, however, saw the emergence of the earliest

     organizations for making music public ?that

     is, accessible to all who were able and willing

     to pay to hear it. Examples are the Abendmusiken

     and Collegia M?sica in various German towns,

     then in Holland and elsewhere. In Restoration

     London, regular public concerts came to be

     offered in a number of taverns; and the first

     hall specifically designed for public concerts was

     constructed in the York buildings. The earli

     est of the great public gardens, Vauxhall, be

     gan to provide instrumental and vocal

     programs both of light and serious music, and

     was frequented by all classes of citizens, from

     the high nobility down through merchants and

     their apprentices ?together with the usual

     camp-followers of such diverse crowds. In the

     19

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    14/27

     process of the eighteenth century, public

     concerts ?music for profit, as a commodity

     art?became a matter of course, not only in

     London (as in other major European cities) but

     also in cathedral towns, the university towns,

     the new industrial cities, and even in many vil

     lages, where groups of amateur musicians

     offered performances for a small admission fee.

     Such concerts included what, in their origin,

     had been a diversity of compositions to serve

     different social purposes; all were now equiva

     lently presented, however, for no other end than

     to provide pleasure to a broad audience ?

     including, specifically, the tired businessman.

     As one English commentator put it in 1725,

     music is a charming Relaxation to the Mind,

     when fatigued with the Bustle of Business. Var

     ious new musical forms, designed to be suita

     ble for performance to a large audience and to

     be both attractive and intelligible to untrained

     listeners, were developed to satisfy the grow

     ing demand ?most prominently, the sympho

     ny scored for a large orchestra, which was for

     the middle-class public very much what the new

     novel was for the middle-class reading public.

     Painting and sculpture I'll deal with in conjunc

     tion. There were contemporary and parallel in

     novations in the arrangements for providing

     public access to pictures and statues. The Con

     tinental Grand Tour, usually lasting several

     years and with Italy and Rome as its chief goal,

     had by the seventeenth century become almost

     obligatory as a finishing school for the sons of

     the high aristocracy in England and elsewhere;

     and some graduates of that school emulated no

     ble or rich Italian collectors of the visual arts?a

     vogue that had begun in Italy in the early

     Renaissance ? by buying the works they had

     learned to prize. Enormous collections were

     gathered ?by purchase, or not infrequently as

     loot following a military conquest ?by princes

     and noble landowners, then by wealthy mer

     chants and industrialists, in many cities of Eu

     rope, and notably in London. In England,

     private collectors, from the late seventeenth

     through the eighteenth century, acquired the

     bulk of the sculpture and paintings that have

     20

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    15/27

     ever since made England a major place for the

     study of the art of Europe, both classical and

     post-classical.

     Some collectors were doubtless, in some part,

     impersonal connoisseurs of works of painting

     and sculpture; but their motives were also ac

     quisitive and proprietary, and they were of

     course very few in number. Our concern is with

     the growing number of nonowners who visit

     ed such collections because of interest in the

     works themselves. Through most of the seven

     teenth century, access to the princely galleries

     had, with few exceptions, been restricted to per

     sons of quality and to qualified scholars. But

     gradually, as the vogue of art connoisseurship

     spread, and in response to increasing demands,

     a number of private galleries were at first de

     facto, then officially, converted into the first pub

     lic museums. The British Museum was estab

     lished as a national institution in 1759, followed

     in 1773 by the establishment of the Vatican

     Museum, as well as by the Uffizi gallery in

     Florence; from then to our own time the pub

     lic collections have, like insatiable sponges, ab

     sorbed ever more of the major works in private

     hands.

     Other institutional innovations served to feed

     the growing appetite for the visual arts. Attend

     ing public auctions of visual arts became a

     popular amusement; Sotheby's was founded in

     the 1740s, and Christie's in 1762. To visit an

     nual exhibitions sponsored by academies of liv

     ing painters became nothing short of a craze

     and filled both building and street with crowds

     of people. Horace Walpole, with his union of

     caustic wit and sense of gentility, wrote in 1779

     that the taste for virtu has become universal;

     persons of all ranks and degrees set up for con

     noisseurs; and even the lowest people tell

     familiarly of Hannibal Scratchi, Paul Varnish,

     and Raphael Angelo. Walpole's comment is a

     humorous exaggeration of the remarkable

     diffusion of interest in the visual arts, while his

     defensive snobbery reminds us of the persist

     ing function of connoisseurship as a sign of so

     cial rank. To cite another example: in 1776

     21

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    16/27

     Thomas Martyn published in two volumes The

     English Connoisseur, a guide to collections of

     painting and sculpture in the palaces and seats

     of the nobility and principal gentry of England,

    intended specifically for the instruction of what

     he calls the rising Connoisseur. Now, the ris

     ing connoisseur, translated into modern so

     ciologese, is the upwardly mobile connoisseur ;

     and Martyn's book is motivated, he tells us, by

      the great progress which the polite arts have

     lately made in England, and the attention

     which is now paid them by almost all ranks of

     men.

    * * *

     In sum: during the span of less than one

     hundred years, an extensive institutional revo

     lution had been effected, with the result that,

     by the latter eighteenth century, the cultural sit

     uation in England (as, to various degrees, in

     Germany and other countries) was recogniza

     bly the present one, with a large, primarily

     middle-class public for literature, together with

     public theaters, public concerts of music, and

     public galleries and museums of painting and

     sculpture. We now take such a situation so en

     tirely for granted that it requires an effort of

     the historical imagination to realize the radi

     cal difference this made in the social role of the

     arts and, as a consequence, in what philoso

     phers and critics assumed to be the standard

     situation when theorizing about them. Through

     the Renaissance and later, works of music,

     painting, and sculpture had been produced

     mainly to order, on commissions by a church

     man, prince, wealthy merchant, town council,

     or guild; very often they were produced for a

     specific function or occasion, religious or secu

     lar; and the accomplished work had been ex

     perienced by some members of its audience, no

     doubt, as the occasion for what we now call an

      aesthetic experience, but at the same time as

     thoroughly embedded in a particular institu

     tion or event, and as an integral component in

     a complex of human activities and functions.

     Now, however, the new institution of the pub

     lic concert might include pieces, both vocal and

     22

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    17/27

     instrumental, which had originally served to

     intensify sacred feelings in a religious ceremo

     ny, or to add splendor and gaiety to a private

     or public celebration, or to provide melodic

     rhythms for social dancing ?together with new

     pieces written for the concert hall itself. There

     exist numerous paintings which represent a

     room in an eighteenth-century gallery or muse

     um. One can see that they display side by side

     statuary that was both ancient and recent, pa

     gan and Christian, sacred and profane. And

     the walls display in close array, extending the

     length of the room and from floor to ceiling,

     paintings that were originally made to serve as

     altar pieces, or else as reminiscences of classi

     cal myth, moral allegories, a Flemish bedroom

     record of a marriage, memorials of historic

     events, representations of a family estate, or or

     naments for a noble salon. All such products,

     in the new modes of public distribution or dis

     play, have been pulled out of their intended con

     texts, stripped of their diverse religious, social,

     and political functions, and given a single and

     uniform new role: as items to be read or

     listened to or looked at simply as a poem, a

     musical piece, a statue, a painting.

     Suppose, while you are looking at a paint

     ing of the Madonna and Child in its original

     location in a chapel, you are asked: What's the

     painting for? A manifest answer is: To illus

     trate, beautifully and expressively, an article of

     faith, and thereby to heighten devotion. Now

     suppose that same painting moved to the wall

     of a museum and hung, let's say, next to a

     representation of Leda and the Swan. To the

     question What's it for? the obvious answer

     now is: To be contemplated, admired, and en

     joyed. Note that each of these is a valid answer

     to the same question ?within the institutional

     setting in which that question is asked.

     I have reserved for special treatment architec

     ture, the fifth of the standard fine arts, because

     it is an especially instructive instance of the way

     in which an altered social role effected a dras

     tic alteration in the conception of a craft. For

     of all the fine (that is, nonutilitarian) arts, ar

     chitecture seems the most obviously and

     23

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    18/27

     thoroughly utilitarian, in that a building is spe

     cifically designed to serve as a shelter and to

     subserve a variety of other purposes ?to be a

     sacred place for worship, to house a great fam

     ily and its retainers, or to function as head

     quarters for a political or social or economic

     body; as well as to announce by its magnitude,

     formal symbolism, and ornament, the status

     and wealth of the institution or family for which

     it is intended. On the Continental Grand Tour

     in the seventeenth century, however, one aim

     had been to seek out a diversity of ancient and

     modern structures, simply as instances of ar

     chitectural achievement. Such a pursuit, hither

     to limited to a few members of the aristocracy,

     grew enormously in the eighteenth century. For

     this was precisely the period both of the inau

     guration and the rapid development of a new

     human activity, and that was the leisure-time

     journey, not to Italy but within England itself,

     and for no other purpose than to get acquainted

     with places and things. Before the end of the

     century, this activity had become so widespread

     as to require an invented word; that new word

     was tourist. The company of English tourists

     included increasing numbers of the middle

     classes. A principal aim of the tour, in addi

     tion to viewing picturesque landscapes, was to

     visit great country houses ?many of these soon

     provided (for a fee, of course) detailed guide

     books to the estate ?in order to admire and

     judge the works of art, the interior appoint

     ments, and the landscaped gardens, and very

     prominently, the architectural structure itself.

     It may surprise you, as it did me, to learn that

     in the year 1775 alone, close to 2,500 tourists

     visited the famous country estate at Stowe;

     multiply that number by ten or twelve, to cor

     respond to the increase in the present popula

     tion of England, and it turns out that the

     popularity of English tourism, very soon after

     that activity began, nearly equalled its popular

     ity now. You will recall that the turning point

     of the novel Pride and Prejudice, which Jane

     Austen began writing in 1798, occurs when

     Elizabeth Bennet is taken by her aunt and un

     cle, the Gardiners ?who, the author stresses,

     24

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    19/27

     are in trade, members of the merchant mid

     dle class ?on a vacation tour that includes her

     rejected lover Darcy's great estate of Pember

     ley, at a time when its owner is supposedly

     absent.

     It is also noteworthy that in the eighteenth

     century a flourishing market developed for

     books of engraved views of royal palaces and

     famous urban and country houses. Buildings

     can't easily be relocated in museums, but these

     published engravings served as a museum

     without walls, hence as yet another vehicle to

     move works of architecture into their new and

     widespread social role as, like the products of

     sculpture and painting, a set of things to be

     pored over, as such, simply for their capacity

     to interest and give pleasure to the observer.

     What had been a utilitarian craft thus became

     an art ?a fine art.

     * * *

     What we find, then, beginning late in the

     seventeenth century, is the emergence of an

     astonishing number of institutions for making

     a diversity of human artifacts public ?as com

     modities, usually for pay?in order to satisfy

     a burgeoning demand for the delights, but also

     for the social distinction, of connoisseurship.

     The sum of these changes constitute a new

      form of life (in Wittgenstein's phrase) in the

     leisure-time pursuits both of the high-born and

     the newly well-to-do. Since humankind is an

     enquiring and loquacious being, a new form

     of life calls for an appropriate language ?a set

     of terms for sorting things out, and for sys

     tematizing and analyzing them, in accordance

     with the altered mode of common or normal

     experience. In such an enterprise, the normal

     experience readily becomes the normative ex

     perience. The new critical language, according

     ly, does not envision a product of art from the

     traditional point of view of its expert construc

     tor or maker, but from the point of view of the

     connoisseur, who confronts the work as a com

     pleted product which he attends to as an iso

     lated thing, for the sake of the satisfactions that

     doing so yields. And certain hitherto largely

     25

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    20/27

     distinct and diversely classified human

     products ?especially poetry, music, painting,

     sculpture, architecture ? since all of them have

     now acquired, on a broad scale, the same so

     cial role as standard objects for connoisseur

     ship, are for the first time classified together

     as an entirely distinctive class of things called

      the fine arts. Addison, with his customary acu

     men, identified this new principle of classifi

     cation when he remarked in The Spectator that

     the fine arts derive their laws and rules from

     the genuine taste of mankind, not from the

     principles of these arts themselves. This is a

     contemporary recognition of the turn from the

     construction model to the spectator model for

     the newly identified class of the fine arts; and

     for the philosophy of this class of objects, the

     German theorist Baumgarten in the mid

     eighteenth century coined the term aesthetics.

    In such a philosophy, works of fine art,

     despite their conspicuous differences in physi

     cal and other attributes, are naturally enough

     assumed to share a distinctive quality or essence

     that enables them to perform their common

     role as objects of connoisseurship. This role,

     although often requiring payment of a fee, was,

     anomalously, not utilitarian or moral but spe

     cifically a diversion or escape from ordinary

     utilitarian and moral interests and pursuits.

     The essential feature that qualified a product

     to be accounted a work of fine art was accord

     ingly identified as its inherent capacity to serve

     as a sufficient and rewarding object of atten

     tion as an end in itself?a very elusive, non

     material feature that Kant called its beauty

    or form or aesthetic quality.

    To put what I have just said in a different

     philosophical idiom: the condition and status

     of being a work of art, in accordance with the

     standard definition of art-as-such, is not an in

     herent fact but an institutional fact. The most

     prominent institution which functions to con

     fer this status has become the public museum;

     the exemplary art-of-arts, which over the cen

     turies had been poetry, has become painting,

     in which the product is hung on a wall and iso

     lated from its surroundings by a material frame;

     26

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    21/27

     and the disinterested and absorbed contempla

     tion of an isolated art object ?the paradigmatic

     experience of the theory of art-as-such ? is typi

     cally a museum experience. The power of be

     ing accepted and displayed by a reputable

     museum to transform a utilitarian object into

     a work of fine art was melodramatically re

     vealed when Marcel Duchamp took a very

     homely utility, machine-made and mass

     produced?a urinal ?from the thousands of its

     duplicates and had it mounted on a museum

     wall. Many of us, once the initial shock or in

     dignation or derisive laughter has worn off, suc

     cumb to the institutional compulsion, assume

     the aesthetic attitude, and begin to contemplate

     the object as such, in its austerely formal and

     monochromatic harmony.

     IV.

     Let me anticipate what some of you are no

     doubt thinking, and admit that the conditions

     for the emergence of the theory of art-as-such

     are not so simple as I have made out. In this

     short presentation, I have had to omit a num

     ber of complications and qualifications. Above

     all, I have omitted a surprising fact, which be

     comes evident only if we turn our attention

     from the sociology of art to intellectual histo

     ry. I said that the theory of art-as-such was a

     radical conceptual innovation of the eighteenth

     century. That assertion is valid, so long as we

     limit our purview to the basic concepts and

     operative vocabulary within earlier theories of

     the arts. But if we take a more comprehensive

     historical overview, we find that the vantage

     point, the defining concepts, and the distinc

     tive vocabulary of art-as-such were actually

     commonplaces ? indeed, they were very old and

     familiar commonplaces; they had functioned,

     however, not in the traditional philosophy and

     criticism of the arts, but in alien realms of

     metaphysics, and especially of theology These

     ancient commonplaces were imported into, and

     specialized for, the theory of fine art ?they

     achieved, that is, a radical novelty of

     application ? only when the new social role of

     the various arts invited and fostered concepts

     27

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    22/27

     of a requisite sort. It seems highly likely that,

     if these concepts and terms had not existed

     ready-made, modern aesthetics could not have

     developed so quickly from its beginnings into

     the complex, complete, and sophisticated form

     of Kant's Critique of Judgment.

     I have told this story at some length else

     where, and have time only to present a few

     highlights. The prototypical conception of an

     object that evokes a selfless and absorbed con

     templation is Plato's Idea of Ideas ?that ulti

     mate essence, uniting Beauty, Goodness, and

     Truth that Plato posited as the terminus of all

     human love and desire. The ultimate

     knowledge, and the supreme human value, Pla

     to says, is the contemplation with the eye of

     the mind of beauty absolute, separate, sim

     ple, and everlasting ?an entity which is per

     fect because, possessing autarkeia, it is utterly

     self-sufficient. Plotinus, following Plato, simi

     larly endowed his Absolute with the attribute

     of being wholly self-sufficing, self-closed, and

      autonomous. And in passages of high conse

     quence for later Christian thought ?and if I am

     right, also for modern aesthetics ?Plotinus

     described the highest good of the human soul

     to be contemplation of the essential Beauty

     and Good which is a state of perfect surrender

    of the self that constitutes the soul's peace, with

      no passion, no outlooking desire. . .reasoning

     is in abeyance and all Intellection and

     even. . . the very self. The soul in this contem

     plation has in perfect stillness attained iso

     lation.

    By one of the strangest developments in in

     tellectual history, this pagan concept of a self

     sufficient Absolute Beauty, which is to be con

     templated without reference either to the self

     or to anything beyond its own bounds, became

     thoroughly identified, early in Christian the

     ology, with the God of the Old Testament, a

     very personal God. He is described in the Bi

     ble as creative, loving, just, and often very an

     gry, but is never said to be beautiful or

     self-sufficient or an impersonal essence or Ab

     solute. It was St. Augustine who, in his emi

     nently influential expositions of the nature of

     28

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    23/27

     Christian cantas, or love, early in the fifth cen

     tury, was more than anyone responsible for this

     fusion of the Christian God and the classical

     Absolute; and in doing so he promulgated the

     lexicon of the categories and terms that, some

     fourteen hundred years later, came to consti

     tute the spectator's vantage and the contempla

     tion model of the theory of art-as-such.

     Augustine's controlling distinction is between

     uti and frui, between loving something for its

     use and loving something for pure enjoyment,

     as an end in itself. All the good and beautiful

     things in this world, he asserts, are to be loved

     for their utility, as a means to something else.

     Of all things in the universe, God, and God

     alone, because He is the ultimate in beauty and

     excellence, is to be loved with a pure enjoyment,

     and in a visio Dei', that is, in a contemplation

     of God by the eye of the mind. And Augustine

     details the loving contemplation of God's

     supreme beauty and excellence in terms

     familiar to us: He is enjoyed as His own end,

     and non propter aliud, for His own sake (propter

     se ipsam), simply for His inherent excellence

     and, in Augustine's repeated term, gratis ? that

     is, gratuitously, independently of our personal

     interests or of any possible reward. Here are

     all the elements of the theory of art-as-such; the

     radical change is the shift of reference from God

     to a beautiful work of art as the sufficient ob

     ject of contemplative enjoyment, and not by the

     eye of the mind but by the physical eye.

     The crossing over of these theological terms,

     especially contemplation and disinterested,

    into aesthetic theory occurred, as I have indi

     cated earlier, in 1711 in the book by the Earl

     of Shaftesbury entitled Characteristics. The ex

     press subject of Shaftesbury's urbane essays,

     however, was not aesthetics or art ? his book has

     been preempted by historians of aesthetics only

     retrospectively?but religion, morals, and the

     life-style appropriate to a gentleman. Shaftes

     bury's ideal is the virtuoso ideal of connoisseur

     ship, a mode of contemplation which (in his

     Platonic way of thinking) applies equally to

     God, to objects of beauty, and to moral good

     ness. Shaftesbury's first published work had

     29

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    24/27

     been a theological essay demonstrating that

     God is to be loved not from a desire for per

     sonal gain, nor as a Mean, but [as] an End,

    and for what he is in himself, in his own Love

     liness, Excellency, and Beauty. In his later

     Characteristics, Shaftesbury imports the rest of

     Augustine's vocabulary, which he applies

     primarily to theology and morality, and secon

     darily to the beauties of nature or of works of

     art.

     I shall cite one German thinker, largely

     neglected by historians of aesthetics, Karl

     Philipp Moritz, who in 1785, five years before

     Kant's Critique, published a short essay which

     is the earliest unqualified presentation of the

     view of art-as-such. The essay demonstrates

     that, in little more than seventy years after

     Shaftesbury, these distinctive theological and

     moral terms have not only become specialized

     to the arts, but are used to oppose the ex

     perience of a work of art to religious and moral

     experience, as well as to all practical concerns.

     Only the mechanical or useful arts, Moritz says,

     have an outer end ?that is, an end outside

     themselves in something other. He poses in

     stead a contemplation model for discussing the

     fine arts:

     In the contemplation [Betrachtung] of the

     beautiful object... I contemplate it as some

     thing which is completed, not in me, but in its

     own self, which therefore constitutes a whole

     in itself, and affords me pleasure for its own

     sake [um sein selbst willen].

     In adding to this formulation the further con

     cepts of aesthetic disinterestedness and the self

     sufficiency of a work of art, Moritz inadver

     tently reveals the degree to which his views are

     indebted to the ancient Plotinian and Augus

     tinian representation of the selfless and gratu

     itous contemplation of the ultimate beauty of

     God:

     While the beautiful draws our attention ex

     clusively to itself. . .we seem to lose ourselves

     in the beautiful object; and precisely this loss,

     this forgetfulness of self, is the highest degree

     of pure and disinterested pleasure that beau

     30

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    25/27

     ty grants us. In that moment we sacrifice our

     individual confined being to a kind of higher

     being. . . . Beauty in a work of art is not

     pure. . .until I contemplate it as something

     that has been brought forth entirely for its

     own sake, in order that it should be some

     thing complete in itself.

     Kant must surely have studied Moritz's

     writings ?there are many parallels I haven't

     cited ?but he stripped away the patent indi

     cators in Moritz of an origin in a Platonized

     Christian theology. Other writers ofthat time,

     however ?like a number of more recent propo

     nents of art-as-such, from Flaubert and Clive

     Bell through James Joyce and some of the

     American New Critics ?manifest the tenden

     cy of a contemplation theory of art to recuper

     ate aspects of its original context in religious

     devotion. Here is Wilhelm Wackenroder, for

     example, writing in 1797, seven years after

     Kant's Critique, on the experience of objects of

     art-as-such; and explicitly, now, in what has

     become their normative setting in a public

     museum:

     Art galleries. . .ought to be temples where,

     in still and silent humility and in heart-lifting

     solitude, we may admire great artists as the

     highest among mortals. . .with long, stead

     fast contemplation of their works. ... I com

     pare the enjoyment of nobler works of art to

     prayer. . . . Works of art, in their way, no more

     fit into the common flow of life than does the

     thought of God.... That day is for me a

     sacred holiday which ... I devote to the con

     templation of noble works of art.

     V.

     Well, what does this excursion into social

     and intellectual history come to?

     The theory of art-as-such consists of asser

     tions that have been claimed, or assumed, by

     a number of philosophers and critics to be

     timeless truths about a distinctive class of ar

     tifacts. I have proposed, on the other hand, that

     it is a way of talking about art that emerged

     at a particular time, as an integral and

     reciprocative element in an altering form of

     31

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    26/27

     social life, marked by the development of many

     new institutions to make highly diverse human

     products widely public, and for no other os

     tensible purpose than simply to be attended

     to for their own sake. I have also proposed that

     these changes were in part motivated by the

     prestige of connoisseurship, and of a

     nonutilitarian aesthetic culture, as a sign of

     upper-class status; and furthermore, that the

     determinative idiom and concepts of the new

     theory were translocated into the realm of art,

     ready-made, from the realm of a Platonized

     Christian theology.

     I do not, however, mean to assert that this

     theory of art is, as a consequence, an invalid

     theory. It describes the way that, in our present

     circumstances, many of us in fact frequently

     experience works of art. Furthermore, when

     a theory of art is put to work in applied criti

     cism, its provenience ceases to matter, and the

     criterion of its validity becomes the profitabil

     ity of what it proves capable of doing. (The

     same holds for some of the profitable theories

     in the natural sciences, which have also had

     a strange, and even dubious, provenience.) In

     criticism, the view of art-as-such has fostered

     an unprecedented analysis of the complex ele

     ments, internal relations, and modes of organi

     zation of works of art that has undeniably

     deepened and subtilized our experience of

     them. This theory has also been held as their

     working hypothesis by major modern artists,

     including such literary masters as Flaubert,

     Proust, Joyce, and Nabokov.

     It is, then, in this heuristic and pragmatic

     sense, a valid theory; but like all competing

     views of art, it is also a partial theory. It is a

     very profitable way of talking, when we want

     to deal with a work of any of the arts simply

     in its formal aspects and internal organization.

     For some kinds of works, this way of talking

     is relatively adequate. But if we turn to King

     Lear, or Bach's St. Matthews Passion, or the fres

     coes of Michelangelo (still, happily, in their

     original situation in the Sistine Chapel) ?or

     for that matter, to Byron's comic masterpiece,

     Donju?n ? the view of art-as-such, while it re

     32

    This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Thu, 24 Mar 2016 00:03:56 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

  • 8/17/2019 Art-As-Such the Sociology of Modern Aesthetics

    27/27

     mains pertinent, becomes woefully inadequate.

     We need to substitute a different perspective,

     and a very different critical vocabulary, to be

     gin to do justice to the diverse ends and func

     tions of such works, and the patent way that

     our responses to them involve our shared ex

     periences, appeal to our convictions about the

     world and our life in that world, implicate our

     moral interests, and engage our deepest hu

     man concerns.

     M. H. Abrams is Class of 1916 Professor of English

     Literature Emeritus at Cornell University.

     33