ari allen on intellectual property and innovation: reforming how information is transformed

Upload: ari-allen

Post on 09-Mar-2016

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Ari Allen on Intellectual Property and Innovation: Reforming How Information is Transformed

TRANSCRIPT

  • REFORMING HOW INFORMATION IS TRANSFORMED:

    INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AS NATURAL MONOPOLY

    Ari Allen

    Georgetown University Law Center

  • 1

    I. Introductory Remarks

    The Congress shall have Power To promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their

    respective Writings and Discoveries.1

    In the depths of Article I of the United States Constitution, the Founders of our

    nation hid a fundamental principle of governance: promote the Progress. Without very

    much instruction or specificity, the Constitution instructs all future legislators to promote

    progress. Of course, its scope is limited to the entire library of human knowledge,

    industry and creativity. And of course, it does give some instruction: intellectual property

    can be granted protection for any time spanning less than perpetuity.

    Indeed, this seemingly innocent clause prompts a very large question, with very

    little direction. And so, like most contentious debates, two sides of the same coin have

    emerged rather independently: intellectual property and antitrust law. Emphasis on

    intellectual property often leads to conclusions that reflect Joseph Schumpeters view that

    market concentration increases innovation, while emphasis on antitrust law reflects

    Kenneth Arrows desire for competition as a driving force of innovation.2

    Yet both of these views are accurate, depending on the circumstances at hand. In

    this paper I will most broadly attempt to reconcile these views and show that market

    concentration and intellectual property rights are often necessary to spur revolutionary

    innovations in fragile emerging markets, while antitrust law must be used as a tool to

    reignite competition in markets that are matured and potentially stagnant. In recent years,

    it has become more obvious that these two approaches are converging and find each other

    1 U.S. Const. art. I, 8, cl. 8. 2 Michael Carrier, Two Puzzles Resolved: Of The Schumpeter-Arrow Stalemate and Pharmaceutical Innovation Markets, 93 Iowa L. Rev. 396 (Feb., 2008).

  • 2

    quite complementary. Soon enough perhaps, they will find themselves more properly

    integrated under a larger subheading that seems to be implicitly intertwined with

    promoting progress: innovation. Exploring the means and ends of this essential

    integration is the aim of this paper.

    The rest of Part I will be dedicated to preparing the reader for the theoretical

    analysis that follows. Specifically, I will make brief remarks explaining the following

    fundamental intuitions: (a) progress is best understood through the lens of innovation; (b)

    innovation is the product of the transformation of information the essential input of

    every product, service and market; and (c) information is protected as intellectual

    property, but is more properly classified as a form of natural monopoly.

    In Part II, I will argue that: (a) similarly to the grant of legal monopoly status to

    natural monopolies, the grant of intellectual property rights are vital to maintaining ex-

    ante incentives to innovate and establish new markets; (b) similarly to mandates of equal

    access imposed upon legal monopolies, compulsory licensing regimes should be

    instituted when such intellectual property falls under the essential facilities doctrine; and

    (c) compulsory licensing and antitrust mechanisms are just as legitimate a form of

    government intervention as the initial grant of intellectual property rights.

    In Part III, we will explore the theoretical framework through the following

    practical examples: (a) a case study on the Google Books settlement; and (b) price

    discrimination in the pharmaceutical industry.

    In Part IV, I will conclude by briefly recapping the argument, tying it together

    into a brief synthesis, and recommending future areas of possible theoretical and practical

    development.

  • 3

    a. Progress as Innovation

    Defining progress may be the most fundamental debate pondered by political

    theorists and legal jurists. It is, most literally, the direction of the future, and we all have

    different views of what that future should look like. However, all of these views share

    one overarching theme: progress always involves change. Nobody proclaims that the

    world is perfect (although some may be resigned to the fact that it can never be better).

    Progress then, is defined by change, although we may disagree about what type of change

    is appropriate. However, we also know that change never happens without the

    introduction of something new innovation. As such, every angle from which progress

    is approached involves a propensity toward innovation. Even social progress involves

    innovation: the creations of new social norms and perceptions. Martin Luther King Jr.s

    I Have A Dream speech something one may define as a cultural artifact, is also a type

    of social innovation. It is also intellectual property.3 Indeed, innovation is the mechanism

    underlying all types of progress, and it is promoted and protected through intellectual

    property rights and antitrust law.

    There are other common understandings of progress as well, especially within the

    economic domain. Firstly, there is progress in terms of efficiency improving the ratio of

    beneficial output (in terms of quantity, or quality) to input costs. Increases in efficiency

    lead to greater revenues and lower costs, increasing profits while lowering prices.

    Consequently, both businesses and consumers benefit as does society as a whole.

    On the other hand, there is progress in terms of equity. Increases in efficiency can

    lead to increases in equity (by making products more affordable), but equity can also be

    3 David Firestone, King Estate and CBS Settle Suit Over Rights To Famous Speech, N.Y. Times (July 14, 2000).

  • 4

    encouraged independently of price mechanisms. Greater accessibility or interoperability

    may enhance equity by allowing more consumers to reach a product. For example,

    former FCC chairman, William Kenner has described one innovation, the Internet, as

    the great equalizer.4

    Yet increases in efficiency and equity can both be reduced to innovative

    improvements.5 Increases in efficiency and equity are both changes that result from

    innovations that range from establishing new growth strategies that capture economies-

    of-scale to the introduction of entirely new product lines. Indeed, innovation may be the

    term of convenience we seek in defining progress whether it is increases in efficiency,

    equity or novelty. Thus, the breadth of progress is not fully captured by greater freedom,

    equality, wealth or justice yet innovation can lead to all of the above. E pluribus unum.

    From a policy standpoint, promoting progress is about protecting market

    participants just enough so that they will actually participate, while also putting pressure

    on them to continue to innovate and provide greater access preventing complacency,

    stagnation and bottlenecking. As such, progress is maintained by promoting active

    participation in the innovative process the creative introduction of new intellectual

    property into the stream of commerce and consciousness. This process represents the

    transformation of information.

    b. Innovation as Transformation of Information

    The fundamental unit of innovation is information. Essential to every tangible

    product or service is the intangible thought or idea that lies behind it. In this sense, while

    4 William Kennard, The Great Equalizer, Remarks at Supercom 2000 International Dinner (June 5, 2000). 5 In fact, innovation is often termed dynamic efficiency, as contrasted against static efficiency.

  • 5

    it is only beginning to receive the attention it deserves, information has always been an

    essential input to progress. Indeed, it is now commonly accepted that knowledge is

    power.

    It is this fundamental distinction that separates real from intellectual property.

    Intangible and disembodied intellectual property is the genetic code of tangible and

    embodied real property. As such, the transformation of this information is the impetus

    behind the innovation of every good. However, transformation requires investment

    labor, capital and time. Consequently, transformation does not occur on its own. How,

    then, does this transformation occur? How is innovation promoted?

    c. Intellectual Property as Natural Monopoly of Information

    Investment in innovation will only occur if the proper ex-ante incentives are in

    place namely, adequate returns on the initial investment. No innovators will risk and

    invest capital, effort or time in an endeavor that will cost them more than they stand to

    benefit. As a result, intellectual property rights were created to protect investment

    incentives and consequently, to promote innovation.

    Since its inception however, intellectual property has struggled with the tension

    between its legal excludability and its intrinsic nonrivalrous quality. A modern adage of

    unknown origin reflects that information wants to be free.6 Yet, information is also

    only born, or transformed, through its granted excludability. From an economic

    standpoint, intellectual property often involves high fixed costs and extremely low

    marginal costs. More simply stated, creating or transforming information often involves

    intense research and development upfront, but is relatively inexpensive to duplicate or

    6 The source is of unknown origin, though it is often attributed to a hacker at 1984 computer conference.

  • 6

    copy after this initial effort is expended. Information is born in chains, but wants to be

    free.

    Indeed, many have proclaimed that intellectual property is in fact, better described

    as a type of monopoly, because a single entity is granted rights of exclusion over a

    nonrivalrous resource. Furthermore, ownership of a disembodied idea allows

    monopolization over the entire market of goods that embody that idea. As a result,

    monopolistic prices are charged because marginal costs being near zero, are easily

    surpassed by supracompetitive prices. Adam Smith recognized this problem at the very

    outset of capitalist thought:

    [T]he author of a new book has an exclusive privilege of publishing and selling his books [for a limited time] Some indeed contend that the book is an [e]ntire new production of the authors and therefore ought in justice to belong to him and his heirs for ever, and that no on should be allowed to print or sell it but those to whom has given leave But it is evident that printing is no more than a speedy way of writing. Now suppose that a man had wrote a book and had lent it to another who took a copy of it, and that he afterwards sold this copy to a third would there be here any reason to think the writer was injured. I can see none, and the same must hold equally with regard to printing. The only benefit one would have by writing a book would be that he would have the first of the market and may be thereby a considerable gainer. The law has however granted him an exclusive privilege for [a limited time], as an encouragement to the labours of learned men But there are few so harmless. All monopolies in particular are extremely detrimental.7

    Harvard Professor Lloyd Weinreb remarked more succinctly, the most that can

    be said confidently about copyright or patent is that it confers a monopoly.8 Smith,

    however, makes a crucial observation about this necessary evil, and views it as an

    encouragement to the labours of learned men. In these words, Smith is alluding to the

    7 Adam Smith, Lectures on Jurisprudence, 83 (R.L. Meek, D.D. Raphael & P.G. Stein eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1978) (1896). 8 Lloyd L. Weinreb, Copyright for Functional Expression, 111 Harv. L. Rev. 1149, 1205 (1998).

  • 7

    notion that supracompetitive prices are necessary to recoup the fixed costs that are not

    accounted for in marginal costs.

    However, Smith also points out that printing is no more than a speedy way of

    writing. Thus, after the fixed costs are recouped, and returns on investment satisfied, we

    must not forget that authors do not handwrite every copy of the information on the page,

    but rather, provided their contribution only initially, by transforming the information that

    would later be copied. As such, the innovator may be compensated beyond the intensity

    of his efforts. Indeed, the author may be rewarded for Guttenbergs efforts in inventing

    the printing press, and many others efforts in establishing the Internet. While of course,

    Guttenberg would be an extreme example; it is illustrative of the fact that innovators are

    often rewarded with profits from related competitive markets in which labor was not

    applied.

    Understanding the contribution of the printing press to every future author also

    illustrates the underlying unity between intellectual property and natural monopoly

    namely, high fixed costs with extremely low marginal costs. These marginal costs are

    heavily depressed by innovations such as the printing press, and thus, enhance the

    nonrivalrous nature of the intellectual property. If it can be easily copied and transferred,

    then it is more clearly a nonrivalrous good. In other words, as the marginal cost

    approaches zero, the good approaches being perfectly nonrivalrous.

    The combination of high fixed costs and low marginal costs can be unified under

    the single phrase, declining average costs. This phenomenon defines the nature of

    natural monopoly a firm that can provide supply at continually increasing economies of

    scale. The natural monopoly phenomenon has been observed in many industries,

  • 8

    including: common carriers, transportation, electric utilities and telecommunications.

    Interestingly, every revolution whether in transportation, energy or

    telecommunications has been accompanied by this natural monopoly phenomenon. The

    revolution provides for a sudden decrease in marginal costs, and thus, declining average

    costs. Thus, it becomes more efficient for a single firm to supply the entire market. In the

    age of the information revolution, information is becoming increasingly subject to the

    same phenomenon. From the printing press to the Internet, it seems that information truly

    does want to be free and it is increasingly becoming so.

    However, the law has not yet fully taken account of this transformation in the way

    information is transformed. Natural monopolies are providers of excludable and

    nonrivalrous goods namely, club goods. Due to their low marginal costs, club goods are

    often supplied by selling access to the good, rather than the good itself. Since

    nonrivalrous goods can be easily duplicated, access is enough to provide a consumer with

    an opportunity to tap into the multiplicative resource. As a result, a television viewer

    doesnt pay for the amount of hours he watches television, but rather for access to the

    broadcast television network. As an aside, it may be worthwhile to note that in natural

    monopoly industries where marginal costs are still relatively substantial (but still

    markedly less than fixed costs), a consumer may still need to pay a marginal price. The

    point however, is that access is a precondition to being a consumer in the market itself.

    As such, access retains its primacy in all club goods. Consequently, and as we will

    explore later, unilateral exclusionary conduct (forbidding access) is particularly harmful

    in these types of markets.

  • 9

    Yet in this age of information, it is becoming increasingly true that disembodied

    information is easily duplicable. Moreover, certain types of informationespecially

    copyrights (e.g., books, music and film)are also becoming easily duplicable in its

    embodied form.9 Records have become MP3s, and books have become e-books. As a

    result, these embodiments are becoming increasingly centralized through emerging

    centralized service providers (such as Google Books, iTunes and Hulu). Indeed,

    intellectual property is becoming increasingly subjected to the phenomena of declining

    average costs, and in many cases, represents a natural monopoly over every embodiment

    of a disembodied idea. The idea need only be created once any additional investments

    would be duplicative and socially inefficient. As such, intellectual property owners may

    increasingly find themselves as the owner of a club, regulated by admission, rather than

    the owner of an invention, physically produced for consumption.

    II. Theoretical Framework

    a. Intellectual Property and Legal Monopolies

    Pioneers are unlikely to explore new frontiers if they are not adequately equipped

    with protections that guarantee returns on successful investments. Intellectual property

    rights confer these protections by granting the pioneer a legal monopoly over the usage of

    their innovation. This protection ensures that pioneers will profit from their innovations,

    and not be too quickly driven to marginal cost pricing that prevents the recouping of

    fixed costs. Thus, similarly to natural monopolies, the economies of scale inherent in

    9 The difference between embodied copyrights, which have become increasingly subject to declining average costs, and disembodied patents, which sometimes require high marginal costs to provide for embodiment, will be discussed later in Part III.

  • 10

    intellectual property require initial legal protections that allow the emerging innovation to

    reach the critical point at which these scales can be realized.

    In short, the granting of intellectual property rights is tantamount to the granting

    of natural monopoly status an example of necessary government intervention in order

    to promote the Progress. However, before we become too comfortable with these

    protections, we must remember that intellectual property rights are not a moral right,

    but a legal tool that encourages economic utility.

    Two illustrative examples come to mind. First, consider a competitor who has

    expended as much (and possibly more) effort and investment on the same innovation, but

    has lost the race to the finish line. This competitor is excessively damaged by the sudden

    excludability of these rights. On the verge of a great breakthrough, another innovator may

    be the victim of the antiquated rule of capture that defines early property laws, and lose

    his entire investment in the matter.10 Similarly, and secondly, future innovators not even

    born yet are afforded no opportunity to independently discover the same innovation

    rather, future generations are forever indebted to past innovators, and are subject to their

    monopolistic will. Even an independent effort to recreate the same innovation, in an

    attempt to avoid dealing with the monopolist, is forbidden by the legal right of exclusion.

    Yet both of these examples are illustrative of the absurdity of intellectual property

    rights in the face of its nature as a nonrivalrous resource. An innovator who is granted

    exclusive intellectual property rights becomes the owner of a disembodied idea, but also

    10 Similarly to early determinations on hunting cases, ideas can be considered ferae naturae in that they are wild and up for capture. See Pierson v. Post, 3 Cai. R. 175 (N.Y. 1805). This reasoning was also later applied to cases of oil. See e.g., Prohosky v. Prudential Ins. Co. of Am., 584 F. Supp. 1337 (N.D. Ind. 1984).

  • 11

    inherits a monopoly over all embodied iterations of that idea preventing anybody from

    utilizing (or independently formulating) a specific thought.

    b. Essential Facilities and Compulsory Licensing

    If the granting of private monopoly over ideas sounds a bit absurd, then the

    recommended remedy will come as a welcome addition to this framework. In industries

    characterized as natural monopolies, grants of legal monopoly status often come with a

    symmetrical and complementary mandate to provide equal access at competitive prices.

    An example of this is in the public utility industry, in which a public utility is granted a

    legal monopoly over the provision of electricity in a specified geographical region, but is

    also mandated to equally serve all consumers within that region.

    In short, a protected market must at some point be opened up and allowed access

    both for consumer welfare and for its own growth and efficiency. The newfound

    accessibility of the good allows it to be both utilized, and innovated upon. In the case of

    intellectual property, permitting improvements of the idea allows for the further

    transformation of the information at stake evolutionary, rather than revolutionary

    innovation.

    While it may not be desirable to impose a similar mandate on all grants of

    intellectual property rights, it may be necessary in certain circumstances. Proper

    identification of intellectual property that should receive such a mandate can be achieved

    through the analogous antitrust analysis that is applied in identifying natural monopolies:

    the essential facilities doctrine. Such essential facilities can be made accessible through

    compulsory licensing regimes that ensure continued revenues for the innovator.

    Yet, the right of exclusion is fundamental within the bundle of rights proscribed to

  • 12

    property. Indeed, under the Colgate doctrine, a firm is free to unilaterally refuse to deal.

    However, the Supreme Court has noted that such a right is not absolute; it exists only if

    there are legitimate competitive reasons for the refusal.11 Thus, the essential facilities

    doctrine developed as the applicable antitrust limitation on this unilateral exclusionary

    conduct.!In brief, the essential facilities doctrine renders a unilateral refusal to deal subject to potential liability as a monopolization violation of Section 2 of the Sherman

    Act.12!For example, in 1983, the Seventh Circuit Court of Appeals required a monopolist

    provider of telecommunications services to provide access to its local service network to

    competitors in long-distance services.13 Many other examples are prevalent within the

    history of antitrust litigation, and promise to continue to stir up contentious debates.14 A

    subset of these debates should most certainly apply to questions of the extreme

    dominance provided by intellectual property rights. Whether specific information, or

    intellectual property, should be openly accessible is a question of whether the information

    satisfies the four factors of essential facility analysis: (1) control of the essential facility

    by a monopolist; (2) a competitors inability to practically or reasonably duplicate the

    essential facility; (3) the denial of the use of the facility to a competitor; and (4) the

    feasibility of providing the facility to competitors.15 Former Chairman of the FTC,

    11 See Eastman Kodak Co. v. Image Technical Servs., Inc., 504 U.S. 451, 483 n.32 (1992). 12 Robert Pitofsky, The Essential Facilities Doctrine Under United States Antitrust Law, Submission to European Commission In Support of National Data Corporation, 3 (2001). 13 Id., at 4 (citing MCI Communications v. American Tel. & Tel. Co., 707 F.2d 1081, 1132-33 (7th Cir. 1983)). 14 See also, Associate Press v. United States, 326 U.S. 1 (1945); Otter Tail Power Co. v. United States, 410 U.S. 366, 377-79 (1973). 15 Pitofsky, supra note 12, at 6 (citing MCI Communications, 708 F.2d at 1132-33).

  • 13

    Robert Pitofsky, notes that [t]his test for antitrust liability has been adopted by virtually

    every court to consider an essential facilities claim.16

    However, prior to analyzing the claim under these four factors, it must first be

    established that the facility is truly essential to competition i.e., constitutes an input

    without which a firm cannot compete with the monopolist.17 In the case of intellectual

    property, this is a common occasion. The benefit provided by accessing Ayn Rands

    Atlas Shrugged cannot necessarily be matched by some other substitute. In this sense,

    creative pieces are often unique enough to form a market of their own, without adequate

    substitutes although this point is surely up for a debate beyond the scope of this paper.

    Specifically, however, the Antitrust Guidelines of the Federal Trade Commission and

    Department of Justice refuse to presume that intellectual property rights confer

    monopolization.18 However, this lack of presumption is no reason to avoid the frequency

    of its occurrence.

    Consequently, intellectual property often satisfies the first two conditions rather

    easily. An intellectual property right essentially confers control of the essential facility

    by a monopolist, and competitors are generally excluded from practically or reasonably

    duplicat[ing] the essential facility. Moreover, from a societal standpoint, the efforts to

    duplicate the essential facility, or invent around it, would be considered a wasted

    overinvestment in something already provided for.

    16 Id. 17 Id. 18 U.S. Department of Justice and Federal Trade Commission, Antitrust Guidelines for the Licensing of Intellectual Property, 2.2 (The Agencies will not presume that a patent, copyright, or trade secret necessarily confers market power upon its owner.)

  • 14

    The third and fourth conditions however, provide the pivot point at which the

    analysis turns. First, if the intellectual property owner is not exhibiting anticompetitive

    conduct in relation to the relevant information (i.e., refusing to deal or gouging prices),

    then, tautologically, access is being provided at a competitive rate. Second, if it is

    unfeasible to provide access to competitors, then of course, such access should not be

    mandated. However, in cases of intellectual property, it is generally extremely feasible to

    share the facility (especially in its disembodied form) due to the low marginal costs and

    nonrivalry implicit in the good. Consequently, it seems that the essential facilities

    doctrine may apply broadly to intellectual property and information, which has already

    been identified as an essential input to innovation.

    Relevantly, Pitofsky notes that [t]he doctrine seeks to prevent the firm with

    monopoly control over an essential asset from unlawfully excluding actual or potential

    rivals, or from extending its monopoly over that asset to the final stage of production.19

    Hence, in the case of information, the doctrine prevents intellectual property owners from

    utilizing their control over an essential input (the information) in order to monopolize the

    final stage of production namely, the embodiment of the disembodied idea, and more

    importantly, the innovation market as a whole.20 In 1992, the Supreme Court observed

    this dynamic: The Court has held many times that power gained through some natural or

    legal advantage such as patent, copyright or business acumen can give rise to liability if

    19 Pitofsky, supra note 12, at 10. 20 See Pitofsky, supra note 12, at 12 (United States courts are sensitive to concerns that limiting intellectual property protections may dampen incentive for innovation. However, the courts have recognized that permitting antitrust liability in proper circumstances appropriately promotes competition, and, ultimately, innovation as well.).

  • 15

    a seller exploits his dominant position in one market to expand his empire into the

    next.21

    However, the feasibility element of the essential facilities test may come into

    consideration when fixed costs are not adequately recouped. In these cases, the

    innovation must be protected from renewed creative gales of destruction,22 so that

    mandated access does not inhibit the defendants ability to serve it customers

    adequately.23

    From this analysis, it seems clear that intellectual property and natural monopoly

    share the essential facilities doctrine as a potentially procompetitive legal framework.

    Indeed, United States courts have applied the essential facilities doctrine [to intellectual

    property] just as they have when the undisputed natural monopolies involved utilities,

    transportation facilities or other physical assets.24

    c. Government Intervention as Cause and Remedy

    One important theme emerges from the prior analysis: compulsory licensing

    regimes and natural monopoly regulations are not some sort of an interventionist crusade.

    Rather, government intervention occurs at many stages within the lifecycle of intellectual

    property, including the very grant of those property rights. Jeremy Bentham wrote:

    Before laws were made there was no property; take away laws, and property ceases.25

    This notion cannot be more clearly revealed than through this analysis of intellectual

    21 See Eastman Kodak Co., 504 U.S. at 479 22 Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, 87 (Harper Perennial 1976) (1942). 23 Hecht v. Pro-Football, Inc., 570 F.2d 982, 992-93 (D.C. Cir. 1977). 24 Pitofsky, supra note 12, at 11. 25 Jeremy Bentham, Principles of Civil Code, Pt. 1, Ch. 8.

  • 16

    property. Before the law, nobody could own an idea, and this notion should be quite

    obvious from the very absurdity that it arises.26

    With an attempt to silence free market ideologues that cling to conservative

    principles, such as those set forth in the Colgate doctrine, I now move on to remedy the

    situation at hand. No remedies are possible, or even debatable, until the possibility of

    remedy is viewed as a legitimate form of government intervention. Fortunately, the

    fundamental principle underlying remedies to intellectual (or natural) monopoly is also

    the foundation of the modern era: increased access and inclusivity the fruit of

    innovation in the age of information.

    Rebutting criticism is simple when one notes that even when compulsory licenses

    are imposed, some property rights remain attached to the owner of the intellectual

    property. In other words, the property is not taken away without compensation. Rather,

    compulsory licensing remedies ensure that such mandates continue to compensate the

    innovator. The process by which these licenses are priced and administrated is beyond the

    scope of this paper. However, the proper execution of this process is essential to the

    remedys success.

    III. Practical Applications

    a. Case Study: Copyright Law and the Google Books Settlement

    The recent Google Book settlement is a fruitful example to examine under this

    framework. Two fundamental features of the settlement are relevant to our analysis: first,

    the orphan works problem; and second, Googles potential monopolization of the digital

    26 See e.g., Reiko Aoki and John Small, Compulsory Licensing of Technology and the Essential Facilities Doctrine, Department of Economics, University of Auckland, 6 (Sept. 2002).

  • 17

    book market. The orphan works problem is a legal dilemma arising out of the Copyright

    Act of 1976.27 The Act ended the requirement that copyrighted materials be registered

    with the U.S. Copyright Office. As a result, thousands of works would be published

    without any central record of copyright ownership. Thus, contacting copyright-holders

    for potential licensing has become near impossible. In a sense, the Act granted a mass of

    legal monopolies without any way of regulating these monopolies (orphan works). As a

    result, current efforts to consolidate the mass of human knowledge into megalibraries,

    such as Google Books Search, have become especially difficult.

    Yet it has never been clearer that these libraries are the wave of future innovation.

    In the age of information, these libraries have begun to emerge everywhere (e.g., iTunes,

    Wikipedia, Hulu, and many others). Centralization has become a form of innovation.

    However, there seems to be no library more important than the entire wealth of human

    knowledge all books, accessible to anyone, from a single location.

    This effort becomes impossible without viewing intellectual property properly

    as a form of natural monopoly. Recognizing this fact allows us to mandate access to an

    innovation after it has been granted its initial protections, so long as the intellectual

    property is considered an essential facility. In the age of information, knowledge has

    become power, and access to that knowledge has become essential.

    Applying an essential facility analysis in this instance is rather simple. First, as

    discussed earlier, a legal monopoly has been conferred upon the intellectual property

    owner books tend to be unique enough to create a market of their own (although again,

    this is a contentious point of debate). Second, new authors are legally precluded from

    27 Copyright Act of 1976, Pub. L. No. 94-553 (1976).

  • 18

    attempting to duplicate the work. Third, the feasibility factor is easily proven as satisfied:

    Google has already digitized a large mass of these books. Finally, the last factor

    whether there is a refusal to dealis particularly interesting in this scenario. While the

    owners of orphan works are not explicitly refusing to deal with Google, they are

    implicitly refusing to deal by making their whereabouts unknown. While the refusal to

    deal has not typically been approached from this perspective, it could be pivotal in

    resolving the orphan works problem.28

    The Google Books Settlement seems to recognize the shakiness of the refusal to

    deal factor by providing a compulsory licensing regime in which all books are

    licensable, by default, so long as the author does not opt out of the settlement. This

    scheme of providing licenses by default solves a large coordination problem that is a

    legal barrier to centralization namely, identifying authors of unregistered orphan works.

    It also resolves the equally difficult problem of negotiating individual licenses with each

    owner of millions of scattered pieces of intellectual property. However, it simultaneously

    maintains the authors right to refuse to deal, so long as there is a legitimate business

    reason to do so (which would be assumed to be rare in this scenario).

    However, the original Google Books Settlement, as proposed in October 2008,

    was flawed in that it would have potentially created a new monopoly that of Google

    Books itself.29 This is a flaw, because unlike most natural monopolies, Google Books

    requires no protections to encourage its creation in fact, for the most part it has already

    28 It is important to note that Google can easily be considered a retail competitor, seeking to sell books amongst a wide collection. On the other hand, the author may be viewed as a wholesaler of the essential input the book. 29 See Proposed Settlement, Authors Guild v. Google Inc., No. 05 CV 8136 (S.D.N.Y. filed Oct. 28, 2008).

  • 19

    been created. The question to be posed is whether or not the digitization of books requires

    a grant of legal monopoly in order for it to be economically feasible. Considering the fact

    that Google has already undertaken much of this endeavor, and other competitors such as

    Amazon and Yahoo are equally eager to do so, it does not seem that the emergence of a

    centralized book market requires a grant of legal monopoly. Indeed, these databases are

    classic public goods, and neither Google nor the Registry will need exclusive rights over

    them as an incentive.30

    The new settlement, released in November 2009 recognized this flaw. It seems

    that the new settlements has emerged with new language that has begun to remove

    Googles exclusivity from the agreement.31 In other words, the compulsory licensing

    regime would remain, but anybody, not only Google, could become a licensee (though

    interpretations of the settlement remain highly contentious). It is hopeful that a final

    settlement will emerge that allows Google to digitize books, but also frees orphan works

    to the general public. This result would provide for an equality of access that promotes

    competition sustaining both dynamic efficiency (or innovation) and static efficiency

    (competitive pricing and output).32

    b. Extremity Stress Test: Patent Law and Essential Pharmaceuticals

    30 James Grimmelmann, How To Fix The Google Book Search Settlement, Journal of Internet Law, 10(1): 2, (April, 2009). 31 See Amended Settlement, Authors Guild v. Google Inc., No. 05 CV 8136 (S.D.N.Y. filed Nov. 19, 2009). 32 This would also help avoid the current predicament within the music industry regarding Performance Rights Organizations. These organizations act as an exclusive central registry, through which works can be licensed. Many scholars have criticized this as a collective monopoly. See Ariel Katz, The Potential Demise of Another Natural Monopoly: Rethinking the Collective Administration of Performing Rights, Journal of Competition Law and Economics, 1(3) (2005).

  • 20

    While patents, in contrast to copyrights, often face higher marginal costs for the

    embodiment of intellectual property, the intellectual property itself remains easily

    duplicable. Additionally, the fixed costs, such as research and development, are usually

    even higher for patents than for copyrights. As a result, the declining average cost

    phenomenon remains in tact.

    One area of intense patent debate often surfaces in the pharmaceutical industry.

    Intellectual property in this area often represents an intermediate good or input of

    production. Additionally, the final good often represents an essential drug that could

    provide massive social benefits if access is promoted. As one scholar has noted:

    The biopharmaceutical industry is characterized by the cumulative innovation paradigm, wherein the discovery of a gene sequence is only the first step It is feared that patents over upstream gene sequences may block further downstream research and consequently adversely impact drug discovery.33

    However, similarly to our earlier examples, if access is mandated without

    providing for sufficient returns on investment, these important initial innovations will not

    occur in the first place. As a result, it is of the utmost importance that compulsory

    licensing regimes in this area are particularly sensitive to the ex-ante incentives it creates.

    Yet pharmaceuticals are equally demanded across the globe. An HIV vaccine

    created in the U.S. may have an even higher demand in Africa. Unfortunately however,

    the socioeconomic level of most Africans is significantly lower than an American, and

    so, access can be difficult for a majority of the demand-side of the market.

    This problem can be solved through a compulsory licensing regime that permits

    price discrimination. In fact, such a regime, if executed correctly, could have a positive

    33 Shamnad Basheer, Block Me Not: Are Patented Genes Essential Facilities?, Berkeley Electronic Press, 1 (2005).

  • 21

    impact both on society (more affordable drugs) and on the drug company (increased

    revenues through sales previously unattainable due to nondiscriminatory pricing).

    However, getting to this positive resolution still requires the analysis explored in previous

    sections.

    First, as we have already discussed, the grant of intellectual property rights is

    necessary to encourage innovation in the first place. The rights must be granted so that

    the innovator can be properly compensated both by initial supracompetitive sales, and

    eventual compulsory license revenues.

    Second, these pharmaceuticals (or their intermediate methods and inputs) are

    often classifiable under the essential facilities doctrine. As in most cases of intellectual

    property, the equivalent of a legal monopoly has been granted over the facility. The

    ability of competitors to practically or reasonably duplicate the facility is blocked by the

    excludability granted with this legal monopoly.34 Additionally, since information is often

    easily transferrable in the age of information, it seems unlikely that providing the facility

    to competitors would be considered unfeasible.

    Lastly, the only element on which the analysis hinges is whether or not the

    innovator is denying use of the facility to a competitor which often occurs within the

    ultracompetitive pharmaceutical industry. However, in the rare case that a benevolent

    pharmaceutical company decides to share its innovations with competitors, an essential

    facility test may fail (being unnecessary).

    34 Even if an adequate substitute or invent-around technology could be designed, such a duplicative investment is inefficient and a waste of capital making it unreasonable to duplicate the relevant capacities of the facility.

  • 22

    In 2001, the WHO released a report recommending that such facilities be subject

    to differential pricing (or price discrimination). Specifically, they call for a more

    coherent global framework for differential pricing [to] . . . facilitate the mobilization of

    the funds necessary to ensure that differential pricing actually contributes to meeting the

    needs of the poor for access to essential drugs. Another report notes that, [p]rice

    discrimination in this context almost certainly raises total consumer welfare.35 However,

    most importantly: If low-price users cover at least their marginal costs and make some

    contribution to R&D costs, prices paid by other users can be lower than they would have

    been in the absence of price discrimination.36 In other words, as long as the price being

    charged to a specific socioeconomic group is above marginal cost, that additional revenue

    will help recover fixed R&D costs. Consequently, the pharmaceutical company will be

    able to capture revenues previously unattainable. In short, since marginal costs are low,

    any additional sales (and especially licenses) are bound to increase profits for the

    innovator.

    It is important to note that I have framed this discussion primarily around the

    pharmaceutical producer and the end consumer. In reality, compulsory licenses

    would likely take place between the producer and a foreign competitor that seeks to

    produce the pharmaceutical locally. This dynamic is simplified in the previous discussion

    because the intermediary does not change the end result: higher profits for the innovator

    and greater access for consumers.

    IV. Concluding Thoughts

    35 Patricia Danzon, Making Sense of Drug Prices, Regulation Magazine, Cato Institute, 23(1): 62 (July 11, 2000). 36 Id.

  • 23

    Antitrust deals with the implicit paradox that competition is, by nature,

    anticompetitive and thus, something that needs to be continually restored. Like a

    chicken-and-egg, innovation protection and promotion must be carefully balanced. A

    chicken must protect its eggs, but once the egg is hatched, its development and growth

    must be encouraged, and it must be permitted the opportunity to live a life of further

    innovations and transformations. Eventually the revolution is complete, and new one

    begins a new egg is hatched.

    Intellectual property rights maintain ex-ante incentives to innovate, and have long

    been properly justified under economic reasoning. Antitrust on the other hand, restores

    competition when competition becomes anticompetitive when the gales of creative

    destruction preclude future creative gales. In this way, intellectual property and antitrust

    law are necessary complements. This is becoming increasingly true in the age of

    information. Information has finally taken its stand in the spotlight as the backbone of

    progress, and the essential input to innovation. Consequently, we must come to terms

    with the fact that intellectual property is, and will continually become, an essential

    facility an essential input for competition.

    However, while intellectual property is commonly accepted as a normal form of

    government intervention, antitrust actions are often seen as an exception to the norm.

    This perception is absurd. No innovator is discouraged from innovating for fear of

    becoming a monopoly subjected to antitrust action. If anything, this result would be

    desired because it signifies the innovators success and profitability. Moreover, the

    antitrust actions recommended in this papercompulsory licensing regimesrepresents

    a continued source of revenue for the innovator.

  • 24

    It is true that it is difficult to set prices in compulsory licensing regimes.

    However, such difficulty should not preclude us from reaching for the optimality that

    would come with its success. As such, we must overturn the stilted perception that

    antitrust is a less legitimate form of government intervention than the assigning of

    intellectual property rights. Indeed, market power associated with an essential facility

    arises because of the absence of a specific legal action (declaration) to remove it, whereas

    market power associated with intellectual property arises because of the presence of a

    specific legal protection.37 Recognizing this factthat the freedom of the market

    actually arises out of government interventionmay be the necessary paradigm shift in

    order to reform the way we view the transformation of information. As a result, it is

    hoped that we can finally, with full force, aim to maximize innovation and promote the

    Progress.

    37 Aoki, supra note 26, at 5.