anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: evidence from the non-paralysed...

8
Neuropsychologia 48 (2010) 3443–3450 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Neuropsychologia journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/neuropsychologia Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb Catherine Preston a,, Paul M. Jenkinson b , Roger Newport a a School of Psychology, University of Nottingham, University Park, Nottingham NG7 2RD, UK b Department of Psychology & Mental Health, Staffordshire University, UK article info Article history: Received 19 April 2010 Received in revised form 17 June 2010 Accepted 19 July 2010 Available online 2 August 2010 Keywords: Anosognosia for hemiplegia Comparator model Non-paralysed Self-other judgement Agency Neglect Motor awareness abstract The current study adds to the growing empirical research into the mechanisms underlying unawareness of paralysis following stroke (anosognosia for hemiplegia or AHP) by investigating action awareness for the non-paralysed limb in a single AHP patient. Visual feedback representing patient GG’s goal-directed reaching movements was either modified by a computer or left unperturbed. Unlike healthy and brain- damaged controls, GG was unable to detect computer-generated visual perturbations as large as 20 . GG also failed to report awareness of the large on-line corrective movements that he made when compensat- ing (often unsuccessfully) for the visual perturbations. These results suggest that the motor comparators implicated in AHP are functioning, but not at optimum levels. Moreover, because the current findings reveal a deficit in awareness for reaches with the unimpaired limb, it is suggestive of common right hemisphere networks for motor awareness in both limbs and that AHP may be a global deficit in motor awareness as opposed to a specific lack of awareness for a particular motor deficit. © 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. 1. Introduction The past decade has seen remarkable growth in our understand- ing of the way in which we move and interact with the world around us. This subject is not only central to identifying the mechanisms responsible for our own actions, but provides considerable insight into how we interpret the intentions and desires of other people (Blakemore & Decety, 2001; Blakemore, Winston, & Frith, 2004). These abilities are fundamental to human social interaction. A driving force behind recent discoveries has been the develop- ment of a computational ‘forward’ or ‘comparator’ model of motor control, based on well-established engineering principles (Miall & Wolpert, 1996). According to this model, the control and awareness of movement relies on the comparison of information derived from various sources (see Fig. 1). Provided that we reach our desired state, such comparisons typically occur with limited conscious awareness (Fourneret & Jeannerod, 1998). The comparisons are thought to serve sev- eral crucial functions, such as allowing the continual fine-tuning of movements during their planning and execution, detecting when errors in movement occur, and correctly discriminating our own actions (self) from those of another person (other) Corresponding author. E-mail address: [email protected] (C. Preston). (Wolpert, 1997). These proposals are supported by the evidence from healthy and brain-injured populations using behavioural experiments (e.g. Blakemore, Frith, & Wolpert, 1999), functional neuroimaging (e.g.m), cortical stimulation/disruption (e.g. Preston & Newport, 2008a) and neuropsychological data (Fotopoulou et al., 2008; Synofzik, Thier, Leube, Schlotterbeck, & Lindner, 2010). However, the exact number, functions, and underlying brain mech- anisms of the comparators remains equivocal. Patients with abnormal motor awareness provide a unique opportunity to cast light on these unresolved issues. In particular, stroke patients who are not aware of severe motor impairments (i.e. patients with anosognosia for hemiplegia, or AHP) can help us to better understand the functional neuroanatomy of motor aware- ness. Recent forward/comparator model accounts of AHP suggest that the underlying cause of the disorder is a failure to detect discrepancies between patients’ predicted and (estimated) actual state (Berti & Pia, 2006; Frith, Blakemore, & Wolpert, 2000). Erro- neous claims that the patient can move their paralysed limb are believed to occur because awareness in AHP is constructed entirely from intact predictions of intended movement (Fotopoulou et al., 2008; Jenkinson, Edelstyn, & Ellis, 2009)). Such discrepancies usu- ally trigger the mechanism responsible for conscious awareness and self-correction of the error (Fourneret & Jeannerod, 1998); however, AHP seems to represent an instance of pathological (lesion-induced) unawareness of large discrepancies between the predicted and actual state of the body, such that normal monitoring 0028-3932/$ – see front matter © 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.07.027

Upload: catherine-preston

Post on 10-Sep-2016

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

Af

Ca

b

a

ARRAA

KACNSANM

1

iuri(T

mcWov

tJeowo

0d

Neuropsychologia 48 (2010) 3443–3450

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Neuropsychologia

journa l homepage: www.e lsev ier .com/ locate /neuropsychologia

nosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidencerom the non-paralysed limb

atherine Prestona,∗, Paul M. Jenkinsonb, Roger Newporta

School of Psychology, University of Nottingham, University Park, Nottingham NG7 2RD, UKDepartment of Psychology & Mental Health, Staffordshire University, UK

r t i c l e i n f o

rticle history:eceived 19 April 2010eceived in revised form 17 June 2010ccepted 19 July 2010vailable online 2 August 2010

a b s t r a c t

The current study adds to the growing empirical research into the mechanisms underlying unawarenessof paralysis following stroke (anosognosia for hemiplegia or AHP) by investigating action awareness forthe non-paralysed limb in a single AHP patient. Visual feedback representing patient GG’s goal-directedreaching movements was either modified by a computer or left unperturbed. Unlike healthy and brain-damaged controls, GG was unable to detect computer-generated visual perturbations as large as 20◦. GGalso failed to report awareness of the large on-line corrective movements that he made when compensat-

eywords:nosognosia for hemiplegiaomparator modelon-paralysedelf-other judgementgencyeglect

ing (often unsuccessfully) for the visual perturbations. These results suggest that the motor comparatorsimplicated in AHP are functioning, but not at optimum levels. Moreover, because the current findingsreveal a deficit in awareness for reaches with the unimpaired limb, it is suggestive of common righthemisphere networks for motor awareness in both limbs and that AHP may be a global deficit in motorawareness as opposed to a specific lack of awareness for a particular motor deficit.

© 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

otor awareness

. Introduction

The past decade has seen remarkable growth in our understand-ng of the way in which we move and interact with the world arounds. This subject is not only central to identifying the mechanismsesponsible for our own actions, but provides considerable insightnto how we interpret the intentions and desires of other peopleBlakemore & Decety, 2001; Blakemore, Winston, & Frith, 2004).hese abilities are fundamental to human social interaction.

A driving force behind recent discoveries has been the develop-ent of a computational ‘forward’ or ‘comparator’ model of motor

ontrol, based on well-established engineering principles (Miall &olpert, 1996). According to this model, the control and awareness

f movement relies on the comparison of information derived fromarious sources (see Fig. 1).

Provided that we reach our desired state, such comparisonsypically occur with limited conscious awareness (Fourneret &eannerod, 1998). The comparisons are thought to serve sev-

ral crucial functions, such as allowing the continual fine-tuningf movements during their planning and execution, detectinghen errors in movement occur, and correctly discriminating

ur own actions (self) from those of another person (other)

∗ Corresponding author.E-mail address: [email protected] (C. Preston).

028-3932/$ – see front matter © 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.oi:10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.07.027

(Wolpert, 1997). These proposals are supported by the evidencefrom healthy and brain-injured populations using behaviouralexperiments (e.g. Blakemore, Frith, & Wolpert, 1999), functionalneuroimaging (e.g.m), cortical stimulation/disruption (e.g. Preston& Newport, 2008a) and neuropsychological data (Fotopoulou etal., 2008; Synofzik, Thier, Leube, Schlotterbeck, & Lindner, 2010).However, the exact number, functions, and underlying brain mech-anisms of the comparators remains equivocal.

Patients with abnormal motor awareness provide a uniqueopportunity to cast light on these unresolved issues. In particular,stroke patients who are not aware of severe motor impairments(i.e. patients with anosognosia for hemiplegia, or AHP) can help usto better understand the functional neuroanatomy of motor aware-ness. Recent forward/comparator model accounts of AHP suggestthat the underlying cause of the disorder is a failure to detectdiscrepancies between patients’ predicted and (estimated) actualstate (Berti & Pia, 2006; Frith, Blakemore, & Wolpert, 2000). Erro-neous claims that the patient can move their paralysed limb arebelieved to occur because awareness in AHP is constructed entirelyfrom intact predictions of intended movement (Fotopoulou et al.,2008; Jenkinson, Edelstyn, & Ellis, 2009)). Such discrepancies usu-

ally trigger the mechanism responsible for conscious awarenessand self-correction of the error (Fourneret & Jeannerod, 1998);however, AHP seems to represent an instance of pathological(lesion-induced) unawareness of large discrepancies between thepredicted and actual state of the body, such that normal monitoring
Page 2: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

3444 C. Preston et al. / Neuropsycholo

Fig. 1. It is generally accepted that the motor control system contains at least threecomparators comparing and responding to differences between the desired andpredicted state (C1) the desired and estimated actual state (C2) and the estimatedactual and predicted states of the movement effector (C3). Frith’s version argues thatgross discrepancies in C2 and C3 are ignored or are unavailable whereas Berti andPia argue that comparator C3 itself is damaged. Crucially, for comparator modelsotN

i2

erstsbp2dipoweKFmm(af(i

aoentaato

dent when asked about his ability to perform actions: when asked to rate on a scale

f agency, it is discrepancies in comparator C3 that indirectly evokes the evalua-ion that a movement or event has been externally produced (Synofzik, Vosgerau &ewen, 2008).

s impaired and awareness is deceived (Jenkinson & Fotopoulou,010).

Accounts of AHP disagree on the source of this failure to detectrrors. Frith et al. (2000) propose impaired input to the comparatorsesponsible for monitoring concordance of the estimated actualtate of the limb with the predicted and desired states. Alterna-ively, Berti and Pia (2006) suggest that the actual vs. predictedtates comparator itself is damaged with the main distinctionetween the two theories being the certainty with which the com-arator is held responsible (see Fig. 1 and Jenkinson & Fotopoulou,010 for further discussion of this point). However, no study toate has directly assessed the functionality of the comparator(s)

n AHP. What is more, the suggestion of an impaired motor com-arator may not be so straightforward. The observed specificityf AHP (e.g. differential perceived abilities for the arm and legithin patients; Marcel, Tegner, & Nimmo-Smith, 2004), and appar-

nt independence of verbal/behavioural (Jehkonen, Laihosalo, &ettunen, 2006) or implicit/explicit awareness (Cocchini, Beschin,otopoulou, & Della Sala, 2010) suggests that certain comparatorsay be impaired in AHP, while others remain intact. Further-ore, reports of AHP following unilateral left-hemisphere lesions

Cocchini, Beschin, Cameron, Fotopoulou, & Della Sala, 2009) arguegainst explanations that have located the mechanisms responsibleor conscious error detection exclusively in the right hemispheree.g. Preston & Newport, 2008b; Ramachandran, 1995). More exper-ments are needed to further investigate these unresolved issues.

Observations in patients with AHP, such as those describedbove, have been useful in providing insight into the workingsf the healthy motor system; however, they present only indirectvidence regarding the possible operation of comparator mecha-isms. The current experiment directly explores the functioning ofhe motor comparator (s) in a case of chronic AHP, primarily using

movement agency task to assess the patient’s ability to detect

nd correct movement errors, by examining the performance usinghe unimpaired limb. AHP performance was compared with thatf a group of hemiplegic patients without anosognosia (patient

gia 48 (2010) 3443–3450

controls), and young healthy controls. The task involved makingself-other judgements about observed reaching movements involv-ing the intact (non-hemiplegic) hand, during which the participantsreceived visual feedback of a visually coincident cursor that wasspatially perturbed or unperturbed. The ability to detect discrep-ancies was assessed by asking the participants to state whetherthe movement seen was self (unperturbed) or other (perturbed).Furthermore, kinematic data regarding the participants’ movementtrajectory was used to objectively assess reach accuracy and on-linecorrection.

If damage to a general right-hemisphere motor comparator isresponsible for impaired awareness in AHP, then self-other judge-ments should be selectively disrupted in the AHP patient regardlessof which arm was involved in reaching. That is, if awareness ofmotor actions for both the left and right hands predominantlyinvolves a right hemisphere network (e.g. Preston & Newport,2008a, 2008b; Ramachandran, 1995), then damage to this networkshould also have implications for awareness of movements per-formed by the non-paralysed limb and should not be restricted tothe paralysed contralesional limb for which the patient exhibitsanosognosia. Furthermore, selective impairment of the comparatorthat provides information for high-level monitoring of self-otherjudgements might spare other low-level comparators responsiblefor the automatic updating and correction of movement errors, inwhich case subjective self-other judgements and reach accuracymeasures should dissociate. The current study considered both ofthese measures in order to tease apart the different components ofmotor awareness.

2. Methods

2.1. Subjects

2.1.1. AHP patientPatient GG was a 64-year-old right-handed male who suffered an extensive

right-hemisphere frontoparietal haemorrhage focused at the level of the lentiformnucleus 1 year prior to testing (Fig. 2). GG’s brain damage resulted in unilateralvisual neglect and left-sided hemiplegia such that he had no volitional movementin his left arm or left leg (power = 0; Medical Research Council scale). On exami-nation of his intact right arm GG was found to have no significant motor deficit(power = 5; Medical Research Council scale) and, while he was poor at two pointdiscrimination, he appeared to have preserved position sense (for example, hewas able, with his eyes closed, to point accurately to tactile targets on both sidesof his body and to accurately detect small, passive changes in limb posture). Nosignificant cognitive impairment was identified using the mini mental state exam-ination (MMSE, Folstein, Folstein, & McHugh, 1975). GG also suffered from chronicanosognosia for his left-sided hemiplegia, as demonstrated by frequent spontaneouscomments that suggested impaired awareness regarding his injuries. The most strik-ing of these involved aspects of gardening which, given his dense hemiplegia andwheelchair/carer dependence, were clearly beyond his capabilities. For example,GG was noted as saying “I think I am going to move the lettuces nearer to the houseso that we don’t have to walk as far to get to them” and “This year I am going to builda cold frame for the garden”. GG also lives in a residential home due to his ongoinghemiplegia, but when asked why he had to live there he reported that it was dueto his wife being unwell, although he sometimes referred to the home as a hospitaland he now admits that he has had a stroke. In addition to these informal mea-sures, GG’s anosognosia was confirmed by formally assessing his awareness (or lackthereof) when asked directly about his injuries (Marcel et al., 2004, see below). GGwas also unaware of his visual neglect and neither did he spontaneously mentionanything wrong with his vision or attempt to employ strategies on clinical tests forneglect.

2.1.2. Upper limb awarenessAlthough GG reported some problems with his left hand such as limited move-

ment and pain they were greatly understated. In the verbal assessment of his upperlimb paralysis he claimed to have movement in his left arm (in fact, GG had no voli-tional movement of his left hand) but refused to attempt to point with it claimingthat he could not do it “with any degree of accuracy”. GG’s anosognosia was most evi-

from 0 to 10 his ability to perform actions with, or involving, his left hand (0 = notat all, 10 = very well) he frequently gave scores of 5/10 or greater. For example, GGscored 5/10 for opening a door and lifting up a small object with the left hand onlyand 10/10 for clapping, saying that he could clap as well now as he could before hewas in hospital. Across all of the 14 action questions, GG gave a median response

Page 3: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

C. Preston et al. / Neuropsychologia 48 (2010) 3443–3450 3445

mage

oc1et

Fig. 2. CT scan of GG showing extensive frontoparietal da

f 5/10, ranging from 0/10 for eating with a fork using his left hand to 10/10 forlapping. It should be noted that for scores lower than 5, and for some lower than0, he always gave a confabulatory explanation. For example, the score of zero forating with a fork was accompanied by the statement, “I don’t know, I haven’t reallyried that, so I had better give it a zero.”

to the right hemisphere (images are left/right reversed).

2.1.3. Lower limb awarenessWhen asked “how is your left leg” GG stated that it was “showing improvement”

and although he reported having pain in his left leg and admitted limited movement(there is no volitional movement of his left leg) he stated that he could walk with noproblems (i.e. severe AHP according to the AHP assessment of verbal awareness of

Page 4: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

3446 C. Preston et al. / Neuropsychologia 48 (2010) 3443–3450

Table 1Table of patient demographics, lesion site and cognitive scores. All patients had extensive lesions restricted to the right hemisphere. Two of the control patients had lowscores on the MMSE but were still able to successfully understand and complete the task. One patient, FA, was unable to complete the NART due to fatigue on day of testingand was unavailable for retesting due to a subsequent rapid decline in her health.

Patient NG LS KM FA GGAge 50 82 57 80 63Lesion site Right temporo-

fronto-parietal CVAPosterior aspect of theright temporal lobeextending to the rightoccipital lobe. Posterioraspect of the rightthalamus

Right temporalhaematoma

Right parietal CVAinvolving the rightfrontal operculum andthe head of the rightcaudate nucleus

Right fronto-parietalhaematoma

824V

tahfteb

2

wdswsallsssi(c

2

occu

3

2hPbmAtspsotrf

4

vtabiT

two blocks using −12◦, −6◦, 6◦ and 12◦ and finally an additionalfour blocks using the perturbations −20◦, −10◦, 10◦ and 20◦. In twoof the blocks using perturbations of 10◦ and 20◦ the question waschanged as an attempt to further verify that GG could not detect

Time since stroke (months) 36 months 21 monthsMMSE 23 17NART 33/50 31/50Verbal IQ (estimated) Verbal IQ = 108 Verbal IQ = 106

he lower limbs, Berti, Làdavas, & Della Corte, 1996). In addition to walking, whensked to rate his ability to perform other activities such as driving and jumpinge gave a median score of 6/10 ranging from 0/10 for riding a bicycle to 10/10

or walking and driving. Note that here also for all activities that GG gave a lesshan optimal score, he attributed his inability to not having done them recently. Forxample, he rated his ability to ride a bicycle as 0/10, not because of his paralysis,ut because he had not ridden since he was a child and would probably fall off.

.1.4. Patient control groupA control group of 4 stroke patients (1 female, 3 male) participated in the study

ith a mean age of 67 (range 50–82). All patients were pre-morbidly right handominant and had right-hemisphere lesions that resulted in left sided hemipare-is/hemiplegia and all had visual neglect. As a selection criterion, all control patientsere assessed for AHP and were found to be fully aware of their motor deficit, all

coring 0 (normal awareness) in a verbal assessment of both upper and lower limbwareness and when rating ability in performing specific actions using the impairedeft limb their scores accurately reflected their actual abilities (mean = 0.8/10 foreft handed actions, mean = 1.3/10 for bimanual actions). The patients were alsocreened for severe cognitive impairment using the MMSE and, despite 2 patientscoring only 17/30, all could understand the task instructions and perform the taskuccessfully. Each of the patients gave fully informed consent prior to taking partn the study (see Table 1 for patient demographics). Crawford and Garthwaite’s2002) modified t test revealed no significant differences between GG and the patientontrol group on any of the demographic measures taken (minimum p value = 0.53).

.1.5. Young control groupEight healthy young controls took part in the study (1 male) with a mean age

f 25 years (range = 21–29 years). All were right hand dominant with normal ororrected to normal vision. The purpose behind including a group of young healthyontrols was to provide a framework of normal performance on this type of tasknimpaired by age or brain injury.

. Materials

Participants’ reaching movements were represented by the movements of a0 mm white cursor that was projected, along with the target location, onto aorizontal semi-transparent screen positioned 450 mm above the reaching limb.articipants viewed the cursor via a horizontal mirror positioned equidistantetween the limb and projection such that visual feedback of the participant’s move-ents appeared in the same spatial plane as the actual reaching limb (see Fig. 3).n advantage of having the visual feedback in the same plane as the movement is

hat it reduces, or indeed removes, the need for the computation of the additionalensorimotor transformations that would be required were the visual plane be per-endicular to, or detached from, the movement plane – as is often the case in suchtudies. In addition, it is more intuitive that the cursor represents the participant’swn hand when it can be viewed in the same plane as the actual hand. The loca-ion of the cursor was calculated on-line using position data recorded by a vBOT 2Dobotic manipulandum sampling at 1000 Hz (see Howard, Ingram, & Wolpert, 2009or a comprehensive description of this device).

. Procedure

Participants sat looking down into the mirror and held onto theBOT handle with their right hand. Before the beginning of each

rial the vBOT moved the limb to a start location just out of viewnd directly in front of their midline. At the beginning of each trial alue 30 mm circular target appeared for 500 ms at randomly vary-

ng locations averaging 210 mm forward from the start location.arget locations directly ahead of the midline were used due to

months 18 months 12 months9 17 261/50 38/50 38/50erbal IQ = 117 Verbal IQ = 114 Verbal IQ = 114

some of the neglect group being unable to detect leftward targets.Immediately following the target disappearance a tone indicatedthat the participants should begin their reach. Visual feedback ofthe reaches (path of the cursor) was either an exact representa-tions of the actual movement (self) or had an angular perturbationapplied (other). Other actions were defined as actions that werenot self-produced (i.e. not the same as the movement performed),as opposed to the actions of another human being. This was madeclear to, and understood by, all participants.

The experiment consisted of 5 experimental blocks, each ofwhich contained 20 trials (totalling 100 trials). In one-fifth of thetrials, the position of the cursor was taken directly from the vBOTposition (an exact representation of the participant’s actual move-ment). All other trials were equally divided between −8◦, −4◦, 4◦

and 8◦ perturbations (with negative values indicating a leftwardperturbation). At the end of each reach participants were requiredto give a verbal self/other judgments as to whether the movementsof the cursor represented their actual movement (self) or whetherit had been modified by the computer (other).

Due to GG’s inability to detect the perturbations, following justtwo blocks of the 4◦ and 8◦ perturbations he took part in a further

Fig. 3. Participants viewed a cursor representation of their hand via a horizontalmirror positioned equidistant between the limb and a projection screen such thatvisual feedback of the participant’s movements presented on the screen appearedin the same spatial plane as the actual reaching limb.

Page 5: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

ycholo

th(fttattrPo

5

5

foacwmtacclf1i

tttsfsrbiaptp

Fd

C. Preston et al. / Neurops

he perturbations. In the first of these he was asked whether head to make on-line motor corrections in order to reach the target“did you have to correct?”), for which he made yes/no responsesor having to correct or not correct, respectively. In the final blockhe question related to his perceived accuracy to the target (“washe cursor accurate?”), for which he made hit/miss responses forccurate and not accurate, respectively. Note that in the accuracyrials it was made clear to GG that judgments of reach accuracy wereo be made in respect to the cursor and not to his actual limb. Thisesearch was approved by the University of Nottingham, School ofsychology Ethics Committee and conformed to the Code of Ethicsf the World Medical Association (Declaration of Helsinki).

. Results

.1. Judgement data

Self/other judgments were converted into percent self-scoresor each participant at each perturbation size. The overall patternf responses for the healthy control participants exhibited a rel-tively normal distribution with the peak of self-responses beingentred on 0◦ perturbations. This pattern of results correspondsell with the results of similar paradigms using this measurementethod (Farrer, Bouchereau, Jeannerod, & Franck, 2008). GG, on

he other hand, recorded a totally flat response profile, respondingt 100% self for each perturbation size and falling outside the 95%onfidence intervals calculated for both the healthy and neglectontrol groups for each perturbation (Fig. 4). For reaches with thearger perturbation sizes (only performed by GG), again, GG’s per-ormance is clearly abnormal, responding with self-judgments on00% of the trials whereas the patient control group were exhibiting

mproved detection of the perturbations at only 8◦.It is notable that the performance of the neglect patients appears

o be skewed and shifted such that the peak for self-responses fallso the left of centre. This is not simply a group effect as each ofhe patients produced a similar performance. The pattern is con-istent with theories of neglect based on a compression of spacerom left to right (Halligan & Marshall, 1991). If the visual repre-entation of the limb in left space is remapped as being furtherightward than its veridical position, then it might be perceived aseing closer to the proprioceptively felt position of the limb than

t really is–giving rise to an increase in self-judgements. Cursorsppearing in central and right space, on the other hand, might beerceived as more rightward than the veridical position, poten-ially leading to a reduction in self-responses to zero and rightwarderturbations.

ig. 4. Patient GG’s mean % self-responses (crosses) plotted against the mean (and 95%amaged controls (filled squares) at each of the 0◦ , 4◦ and 8◦ perturbations.

gia 48 (2010) 3443–3450 3447

5.2. Accuracy and correction judgements

GG was very accurate when reaching in unperturbed trials. End-point errors (calculated in the lateral × dimension measured fromthe seen cursor position, not the actual hand position) in this condi-tion were very small (median absolute end point error = 1.9◦), andsmaller than all of the other patients (range of medians = 3.5–6.2◦)including the reaches of the most closely matched patient control,KM (median = 3.5◦). This demonstrates that his ability to integratesensorimotor information in order to plan and execute reachesremained intact. Inspection of GG’s handpaths in the perturbedconditions, however, revealed that many of his reaches exhibitedlarge and late on-line corrections. His errors across all perturba-tion sizes ranged from 0.03◦ to 24.94◦ with a median of 3.1◦ (themedian error increased to 12.6◦ for the largest 20◦ perturbations).Note that an error of ∼12◦ for the cursor in the 20◦ perturbation con-dition represents an error of 8◦ for the true position of the hand).Despite these substantial inaccuracies, sometimes accompanied byvery large corrective movements (see Fig. 5), GG rated his per-ception of reach accuracy as always being accurate (100% accurateresponses) for all perturbations while his reporting of motor cor-rections remained fixed at 0% (never having to correct). Although itwas not tested directly, these data would argue against an accountpositing that GG’s deficit was caused by a failure to successfullyintegrate visual and proprioceptive information regarding the limb.In any case, such impairment could only be in addition to, and notinstead of, a failure to be aware of the consequences of his ownreaching movements.

5.3. Kinematic data

The first two blocks of GG’s reaches were compared to thoseof control patient KM. Only the first 36 of KM’s reaches were usedbecause 4 trials were lost from GG’s data due to GG letting go of thevBOt handle, causing early termination of the trial. The first twoblocks were chosen because they could be directly matched for per-turbation size and KM was chosen as the most closely matched ofthe control patients (in regards to age, cognitive score, physical dis-ability). Paired samples t-tests demonstrated that the overall profileof reach kinematics were very similar between the two, with no

significant differences found for peak velocity (t(35) = 0.26, p = 0.8)(GG mean = 336.2 mm/s, S.D = 79.5 mm/s; KM mean = 341.5 mm/s,S.D = 73.9 mm/s) or movement time (t(35) = 1.44, p = 0.16)(GG mean = 1280 ms, S.D = 210 ms; KM mean = 1200 ms,S.D = 220 ms).

confidence intervals) for young healthy controls (open circles) and elderly brain-

Page 6: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

3 ycholo

6

jibtrmhspc((is

eaupn&cdIrjpbaTdto

s(sma[

Fcil

448 C. Preston et al. / Neurops

. Discussion

These results demonstrate a clear dissociation between sub-ective self-reports of motor awareness and objective movementsnvolving the unimpaired limb. Despite perturbations of up to 20◦

eing applied to his real movements, GG consistently reportedhat these observed reaches accurately represented his own actualeaches. GG’s judgements of movement agency are clearly abnor-al, falling far outside the confidence intervals of both young

ealthy controls and age-matched patient controls. This, it must betressed, is in relation to reaches made with his intact limb, whereasrevious accounts of impaired motor awareness in AHP have con-entrated on erroneous reports of action in the paralysed limbwith the exception of an anecdotal description by Ramachandran1995) of a single patient, FD). As such, this experiment is uniquen reporting empirical evidence of abnormal motor awareness foruccessfully executed actions in AHP.

External influences on actions are normally detected relativelyasily by healthy controls, provided the perturbation is aboveround 5◦ (Farrer, Franck, Paillard, & Jeannerod, 2003), althoughnawareness of larger perturbations have been reported underarticular experimental circumstances designed to reduce aware-ess (Michel, Pisella, Prablanc, Rode, & Rossetti, 2007; Preston

Newport, 2010). For this experimental manipulation healthyontrols performed near chance for 4◦ perturbations and easilyetected 8◦ perturbations to either side of the real movement.

nstead of the typically observed normal distribution for self-eports, which is centred around zero (e.g. Farrer et al., 2008), GG’sudgements profile was totally flat. GG judged all reaches as self-roduced, despite the cursor representing his hand being perturbedy up to 20◦ from his real hand, and missing the intended targetrea by an average of 11.95◦ (for the largest perturbation sizes).his remarkable behaviour demonstrates a clear deficit in detectingiscrepancies between the estimated actual and predicted states ofhe arm, and provides strong evidence of a change in the efficiencyf the comparator responsible for this function (see C3, Fig. 1).

In spite of his unawareness at a conscious level, GG’s motorystem nevertheless frequently corrected his movements on-line

Fig. 5), particularly for the larger 10 and 20◦ perturbations. Thisuggests that the comparators thought to be responsible for move-ent control and accuracy (i.e. those between the actual estimated

nd desired states [C2], and predicted and desired state of the limbC1]) are still functioning in GG. The performance of one or both of

ig. 5. Hand paths (left panels) and velocity profiles (right panels) of typical reaches fromorrections (left hand panel a), while for other reaches his motor corrections were secondan velocity late in the movement) in panel b. Regardless of the error or magnitude of corrines represent the trajectory of the actual limb and solid lines represent the cursor trajec

gia 48 (2010) 3443–3450

these comparators appears to be less than optimal, since all move-ment corrections were large and late (although it should be notedthat the velocity profiles suggest that some of these are secondarynovel movements, rather than corrective movements). The currentresults suggest that although these comparators receive appropri-ate input and are functional, their ability to update the controllersresponsible for programming movements and making on-line cor-rections may be compromised. Furthermore, the errors detectedby these comparators did not give rise to conscious awareness.GG claimed to be reaching accurately regardless of whether or nothe made corrections suggesting that these comparators may notfeed into consciousness, or that their usual role in this processis impaired. Minor, unconscious corrections have been observedexperimentally, in healthy participants, using incremental adap-tation (e.g. Michel et al., 2007) or double-step paradigms in whichthe target suddenly jumps to a new location (e.g. Goodale, Pèlisson,& Prablanc, 1986), especially if this change occurs during a sac-cadic eye movement. The dissociation between GG’s correctiveperformance and lack of conscious awareness offers support forthe putative existence of independent mechanisms for automatic,on-line correction and conscious control of movement (e.g. Pisellaet al., 2000).

Despite the cursor being presented in the same plane as theactual hand, it could be argued that GG’s performance results froma problem integrating the seen position of the hand (the cursor)with the felt position of the hand and is thus unable to detect a dis-crepancy between the two. However, the data from unperturbedtrials shows that GG is accurate, demonstrating his ability to inte-grate visual and proprioceptive signals; GG made corrections tohis movements unconsciously, thereby, again, demonstrating thisability to integrate visual and proprioceptive information; if such aproblem were related to his neglect then the control group wouldbe expected to have the same problem, which they do not. This,therefore, cannot in itself explain the lack of motor awareness inthe AHP patient.

A recent study by Jenkinson et al. (2009) investigated the func-tionality of the comparator that detects discrepancies betweenthe desired and predicted state of the limb (C1) in AHP. This was

achieved using the grip selection task that compares judgmentsof how patients state they would grasp a wooden rod (a task thatnecessitates mental rehearsal) with how they actually grasp it.Because our limbs are mirror images of each other, transposingresults from the non-paralysed limb allows predictions to be made

the last two blocks of GG’s reaches. For some reaches, GG made on-line movementry movements (right hand panel b). Note the re-accelerations (secondary increasesection, GG always reported his reaches as being accurate and uncorrected. Dashedtory.

Page 7: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

ycholo

alahthItofpfttA

tosatoamemdea

jtmctrpimIiocemr

cawt(Htptppmcswldwm

C. Preston et al. / Neurops

bout actual grasps with the hemiplegic limb. Jenkinson and col-eagues found no difference in performance between AHP patientsnd matched patient controls without AHP. Both patient groups,owever, showed a significant impairment on the task for bothhe hemiplegic and the non-paralysed limb and comparable resultsave been observed with GG in a modified version of this task.

mproving motor control through mental rehearsal, and the fine-uning of movements during their execution, is thought to be onef the major functions of the third comparator (C1 in Fig. 1). There-ore, the deficit observed for both AHP and non-AHP hemiplegicatients in the grip selection task provides support that the per-ormance of comparator C1 is also disrupted. Importantly, becausehe deficit in performance was not exclusive to the AHP patient oro the hemiplegic limb it suggests that unawareness of paralysis inHP cannot be explained by C1 disruption alone.

It is important to remember that while the overall purpose ofhe comparators is to maintain and improve motor control, becausef inherent noise in the system (partially arising from delays in sen-ory transduction), the various comparators must allow a certainmount of leniency. Take, for example, the comparator that moni-ors concordance between the predicted and estimated actual statef the limb (C3, Fig. 1): if the threshold for judging movementss self-produced is too strict, then genuinely self-produced move-ents would be perceived as being not self-produced, or worse still,

xternally produced. The result would be a subjective sense that ourovements are not our own, like that experienced by patients with

elusions of control in schizophrenia (Synofzik et al., 2010). Suchxperiences severely compromise our ability to function effectivelys social beings.

It is reasonable to expect that the discrepancy threshold forudging movements as self-produced should be at least as great ashe inherent noise, thereby allowing normal and effective move-

ents to pass unnoticed. The same may be true for the otheromparators, particularly that comparing the estimated actual andhe intended states (C2) and experimental examples of small cor-ections going unnoticed are frequently observed in double-steparadigms (e.g. Goodale et al., 1986). When the brain is damaged,

t is likely to increase the level of noise in the motor system, whichay be considerable following a stroke that results in hemiplegia.

n order to deal with everyday movements in the presence of thisncreased noise, the comparators must therefore relax the thresh-ld for signalling errors. The suggestion here is not that any of theomparators are necessarily broken in AHP, but that their param-ters have been pathologically relaxed to the extent that actualovements are treated as self-produced, even when they bear little

esemblance to those intended.This slackening of control is apparent to some extent in the

urrent neglect group, for whom the criteria for self-movementsppears to have been broadened. This suggestion is consistentith anecdotal reports that many neglect patients often fail

o notice errors while undergoing prism adaptation procedureMichel et al., 2007; Rode, Pisella, Rossetti, Farne, & Boisson, 2003).ealthy controls will typically and spontaneously make vocalisa-

ions reflecting surprise when failing to reach accurately towards arism-displaced target, and will make conscious strategic correc-ive movements in order to become accurate. By contrast, neglectatients frequently fail to register surprise, can be unaware of therism-induced error when explicitly asked, and are often slow toake strategic corrective movements (Michel et al., 2007). In the

urrent study, however, GG’s performance cannot be explainedimply by severity of neglect syndrome as he was far from being the

orst in the group for all of the neglect measures recorded (cancel-

ation tasks, line bisection and scene copying), yet all other patientsemonstrated some ability to detect the perturbations (and it isorth noting here that we have not observed this level of impair-ent in any of the patients tested on similar paradigms in our lab).

gia 48 (2010) 3443–3450 3449

Therefore, it is suggested here that in the case of anosognosia, theraising of the comparator thresholds is such that all movements aretreated as both self-produced and accurate. Thus, when a move-ment is intended, and, importantly, a motor programme produced,the movement is treated as self-produced, even though no actualmovement has taken place. This idea is compatible with the Frith etal. (2000) model, in which the comparators are working, but perti-nent information fails to reach consciousness; nor is it incompatiblewith Berti and Pia (2006), as the comparators, while not broken, arenot functioning normally.

A final implication of the present study relates to the neu-roanatomical basis of AHP and the motor comparators, whichremain a matter of considerable debate. Pia, Neppi-Modona, Ricci,& Berti (2004) found that AHP was most frequent following com-bined damage to frontal and parietal areas, while AHP followingpurely subcortical lesions typically involved the basal ganglia andthalamus. Berti et al. (2005) found AHP to be associated with frontalareas responsible for programming movements (Brodmann areas 6and 44), suggesting that the control and monitoring of movementsmay be implemented within the same neural circuitry (see alsoSpinazzola, Pia, Folegatti, Marchetti, & Berti, 2008). These findingsare supported by evidence in healthy controls that the brain mech-anisms responsible for motor awareness are located between theprimary motor and premotor cortices (Haggard & Magno, 1999),and discrepancies between motor intention and sensory outcomeactivate right prefrontal cortex (Fink et al., 1999). Several otherstudies have also identified damage to the insula as a key occur-rence in patients with impaired awareness (Baier & Karnath, 2008;Karnath, Baier, & Nagele, 2005; Spinazzola et al., 2008). Althoughthe current study cannot draw any conclusions regarding the spe-cific brain regions responsible for AHP or the motor comparatorsdue to his extensive lesion, GG’s clear deficit in motor awarenessfor actions performed with his non-paralysed limb, in addition toAHP for his left sided paralysis, provides novel empirical evidencesuggesting that the mechanisms for awareness of both left and righthand movements involve right hemisphere networks, an idea origi-nally put forward by Ramachandran (1995). Whether the compara-tors for both limbs involve right hemisphere regions, or informationproduced by separate left and right hand comparators is fed intoa single ‘conscious awareness detector’ located in the right hemi-sphere remains unclear and cannot be teased apart by GG’s 100%self-reports in the current study (i.e. it is possible that the left handcomparators are functioning normally, but the awareness moduleis damaged). However, GG’s impaired awareness for his right handmovements may suggest that AHP, rather than being a specific lackof awareness for a motor deficit, is actually a more global deficitfor motor awareness. Of course, different within-patient levels ofoverestimation in the perceived motor abilities of the arm and theleg, despite both being similarly impaired, have been observed inpatients with right brain damage (Marcel et al., 2004). For suchcases a global deficit in motor awareness may seem fallacious. How-ever, due to the different constraints of arm and foot movementsit is reasonable to assume that they may be controlled by sepa-rate comparators, or at least separate comparator thresholds, whichmay, in turn suffer differing degrees of abnormal slackening follow-ing stroke dependent on lesion size and location. In any case, thekey suggestion here is that anosognosia, rather than being a lack ofawareness of paralysis per se, is a general deficit of motor awarenesswhether the limb(s) in question are paralysed or not.

In summary, the current results demonstrate dissociationbetween subjective and objective motor awareness of the non-

paralysed limb in AHP. GG was able to perform low-level motorcorrections to compensate for large visual perturbations, albeitpoorly, that he was not consciously aware of, suggesting that for-ward model comparators implicated in AHP are not actually brokenbut that AHP may be a result of an abnormal slackening of normal
Page 8: Anosognosia for hemiplegia as a global deficit in motor awareness: Evidence from the non-paralysed limb

3 ycholo

cAhiotbhafisipa

A

3fFd

R

B

B

B

B

B

B

B

C

C

C

F

F

F

F

450 C. Preston et al. / Neurops

omparator thresholds. Furthermore, the fact that, in addition toHP, GG has a deficit in awareness of movements performed withis unimpaired limb following damage only to the right hemisphere

s suggestive of right hemisphere involvement for action awarenessf both limbs. Although interpretations of the current data are, forhe most part, speculative they do provide an important contri-ution to our current understanding of AHP, as well as testableypotheses that can be pursued in future research. For example,ltering the nature of the target/visual feedback and comparing per-ormance with active vs. passive movements may provide insightnto the respective roles of motor planning and the monitoring ofensory input. Despite recent progress in this area, further exper-mental investigations are essential to understand not only theathogenesis of AHP, but also the mechanisms underlying actionwareness in the normal brain.

cknowledgements

CP was funded by ESRC grants RES-000-22-2802 & RES-000-22-455. We are grateful to Dr. DP Carey and an anonymous revieweror their comments. The authors would also like to thank Janeowlie & Sophia Karok for assistance with patient recruitment andata collection, respectively.

eferences

aier, B., & Karnath, H. O. (2008). Tight link between our sense of limb ownershipand self-awareness of actions. Stroke, 39(2), 486–488.

erti, A., & Pia, L. (2006). Understanding motor awareness through normal andpathological behavior. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 15(5), 245–250.

erti, A., Bottini, G., Gandola, M., Pia, L., Smania, N., Stracciari, A., et al. (2005). Sharedcortical anatomy for motor, awareness and motor control. Science, 309(5733),488–491.

erti, A., Làdavas, E., & Della Corte, M. (1996). Anosognosia for hemiplegia, neglectdyslexia, and drawing neglect: Clinical findings and theoretical considerations.Journal of the International Neuropsychological Society, 2, 426–440.

lakemore, S. J., & Decety, J. (2001). From the perception of action to the understand-ing of intention. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2(8), 561–567.

lakemore, S. J., Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (1999). Spatio-temporal predictionmodulates the perception of self-produced stimuli. Journal of Cognitive Neuro-science, 11(5), 551–559.

lakemore, S. J., Winston, J., & Frith, U. (2004). Social cognitive neuroscience: Whereare we heading? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(5), 216–222.

occhini, G., Beschin, N., Cameron, A., Fotopoulou, A., & Della Sala, S. (2009). Anosog-nosia for motor impairment following left brain damage. Neuropsychology, 23(2),223–230.

occhini, G., Beschin, N., Fotopoulou, A., & Della Sala, S. (2010). Explicit andimplicit anosognosia or upper limb motor impairment. Neuropsychologia, 48(5),1489–1494.

rawford, J. R., & Garthwaite, P. H. (2002). Investigation of the single case in neu-ropsychology: Confidence limits on the abnormality of test scores and test scoredifferences. Neuropsychologia, 40, 1196–1208.

arrer, C., Franck, N., Paillard, J., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). The role of proprioceptionin action recognition. Consciousness and Cognition, 12(4), 609–619.

arrer, C., Bouchereau, M., Jeanerrod, M., & Franck, N. (2008). Effect of distorted visualfeedback on the sense of agency. Behavioural Neurology, 19(1–2), 53–57.

ink, G. R., Marshall, J. C., Halligan, P. W., Frith, C. D., Driver, J., Frackowiak, R. S. J., et al.(1999). The neural consequences of conflict between intention and the senses.Brain, 122(3), 497–512.

olstein, M. F., Folstein, S. E., & McHugh, P. R. (1975). Mini-mental state-practicalmethod for grading cognitive state of patients for clinician. Journal of PsychiatricResearch., 12(3), 189–198.

gia 48 (2010) 3443–3450

Fotopoulou, A., Tsakiris, M., Haggard, P., Vagopoulou, A., Rudd, A., & Kopelman, M.(2008). The role of motor intention in motor awareness: An experimental. Brain,131(12), 3432–3442.

Fourneret, P. R., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Limited conscious monitoring of motorperformance in normals. Neuropsychologia, 36(11), 1133–1140.

Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S. J., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Abnormalities in the awarenessand control of action. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of LondonSeries B-Biological Sciences, 355(1404), 1771–1788.

Goodale, M. A., Pèlisson, D., & Prablanc, C. (1986). Large adjustments in visuallyguided reaching do not depend on vision of the hand or perception of targetdisplacement. Nature, 320(6064), 748–850.

Haggard, P., & Magno, E. (1999). Localising awareness of action with transcranialmagnetic stimulation. Experimental Brain Research, 127(1), 102–107.

Halligan, P. W., & Marshall, J. C. (1991). Spatial compression in visual neglect: A casestudy. Cortex, 27(4), 623–629.

Howard, I. S., Ingram, J. N., & Wolpert, D. M. (2009). A modular planar robotic manip-ulandum with end-point torque control. Journal of Neuroscience Methods, 181(2),199–211.

Jenkinson, P. M., & Fotopoulou, A. (2010). Motor awareness in anosognosia for hemi-plegia: Experiments at last. Experimental Brain Research., 204(3), 295–304.

Jehkonen, M., Laihosalo, M., & Kettunen, J. E. (2006). Anosognosia after stroke:Assessment, occurrence, subtypes and impact on functional outcome reviewed.Acta Neurologica Scandinavica, 114(5), 293–306.

Jenkinson, P. M., Edelstyn, N. M. J., & Ellis, S. J. (2009). Imagining the impossible:Motor representations in anosognosia for hemiplegia. Neuropsychologia, 47(2),481–488.

Karnath, H. O., Baier, B., & Nagele, T. (2005). Awareness of the functioning of one’sown limbs mediated by the insular cortex? Journal of Neuroscience, 25(31),7134–7138.

Marcel, A. J., Tegner, R., & Nimmo-Smith, I. (2004). Anosognosia for plegia: Specificity,extension, partiality and disunity. Cortex, 40(1), 19–40.

Miall, R. C., & Wolpert, D. M. (1996). Forward models for physiological motor control.Neural Networks, 9(8), 1265–1279.

Michel, C., Pisella, L., Prablanc, C., Rode, G., & Rossetti, Y. (2007). Enhancingvisuomotor adaptation by reducing error signals: Single-step (aware) versusmultiple-step (unaware) exposure to wedge prisms. Journal of Cognitive Neuro-science, 19(2), 341–350.

Pia, L., Neppi-Modona, M., Ricci, R., & Berti, A. (2004). The anatomy of anosognosiafor hemiplegia: A meta-analysis. Cortex, 40(2), 367–437.

Pisella, L., Gréa, H., Tilikete, C., Vighetto, A., Desmurget, M., Rode, G., et al. (2000).An ‘automatic pilot’ for the hand in human posterior parietal cortex: Towardreinterpreting optic ataxia. Nature Neuroscience, 3, 729–736.

Preston, C., & Newport, R. (2008a). Misattribution of movement agency fol-lowing right parietal TMS. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 2(1),26–32.

Preston, C., & Newport, R. (2008b). Was that me? The right hemisphere and thesense of agency: Embodiment of others and misattribution of self-generatedaction. In B. Hardy-Vallee, & N. Payette (Eds.), Beyond the brain: Embodied, situ-ated and distributed cognition (pp. 107–122). Newcastle, U.K: Cambridge ScholarsPublishing.

Preston, C., & Newport, R. (2010). Self-denial and the role of intentions in the attribu-tion of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, doi:10.1016/j.concog.2010.04.005

Ramachandran, V. S. (1995). Anosognosia in parietal lobe syndrome. Consciousnessand Cognition, 4(1), 22–51.

Rode, G., Pisella, L., Rossetti, Y., Farne, A., & Boisson, D. (2003). Bottom-up transfer of sensory-motor plasticity to recovery of spatial cognition:Visuomotor adaptation and spatial neglect. Progress in Brain Research, 142,271–283.

Spinazzola, L., Pia, L., Folegatti, A., Marchetti, C., & Berti, A. (2008). Modular struc-ture of awareness for sensorimotor disorders: Evidence from anosognosiafor hemiplegia and anosognosia for hemianaesthesia. Neuropsychologia, 46(3),915–926.

Synofzik, M., Thier, P., Leube, D. T., Schlotterbeck, P., & Lindner, A. (2010). Misattri-butions of agency in schizophrenia are based on imprecise predictions. Brain,

133(1), 262–271.

Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2008). Beyond the comparator model: Amultifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(1),219–239.

Wolpert, D. M. (1997). Computational approaches to motor control. Trends in Cog-nitive Sciences, 1(6), 209–216.