aesthetic force in baudrillard and deleuze

Upload: revocables

Post on 06-Jul-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    1/226

     

     AESTHETIC FORCE

    IN

    BAUDRILLARD AND DELEUZE

    By

    VANESSA, ANNE-CECILE FREERKS 

    Dissertation submitted in fulfilment of the

    requirements for the degree

    MASTER OF ARTS

    In

    PHILOSOPHY

    In the

    FACULTY OF HUMANITIES

     At the

    UNIVERSITY OF JOHANNESBURG

    SUPERVISOR: PROFESSOR J.J. SNYMAN

    MAY 2009

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    2/226

     

    DECLARATION

    I, Vanessa, Anne-Cécile Freerks, hereby declare that the work contained in this

    dissertation is my own original work and that I have not previously submitted it, in its

    entirety or in part, at any university for a degree.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    3/226

     

     ABSTRACT

    When fighting against the dominance of instrumental reason, aesthetic

    consciousness always admitted its allegiance to ‘another state of being,’ i.e., to the

    explosive break with the continual inertia of linear social development. In the

    literature written at the turn of the 20th  century this was symbolized in the ‘life of

    danger’ that contrasted with the normality of ordinary bourgeois life. This study shows

    that Baudrillard no longer believes in ‘another state of being’ with explosive force. In

    Baudrillard's theory of simulation, the crisis of overproduction in capitalism is to be

    understood as the total shift of production into reproduction. His position has

    consequences for the idea of the catastrophic nature of the present social situation

    and for the aesthetic means with which it can finally be thought.

    Baudrillard calls the catastrophic effect of the threat emanating from simulation an

    implosion not an explosion, it results from the fact that under pressure from a merely

    simulated reality, every social energy is expended internally in the play of signifiers,

    evaporating in some catastrophic process. His aesthetic fascination with events does

    not seem to have disappeared completely in the process. For Baudrillard, on

    September 11 2001, the terrorists countered simulation with simulation itself. This is

    what makes it a true event. What is unthinkable in this event is the use of death in a

    staged exchange where a whole culture could be attacked. The attack brings back

    death to a world that pretends it is not there. If political economy is the most rigorous

    attempt to put an end to death, it is clear that only death can put an end to political

    economy. 

    Baudrillard encounters an indifference, a void and death at the heart of thought. This

    leads to apocalyptic tones. For Baudrillard, one only attains to thought when one

    interiorizes the limit and displaces it. Thinking no longer works except by breaking

    down and dismantling itself. For Deleuze, on the other hand, to dissent is to affirm

    other modes of life. Deleuze constructs an entire philosophy of life – conceived as a

    philosophy of difference. This enables  Deleuze to have an affirmative notion of the

    aesthetic impulse: the artwork as an unexpected event that actualizes the virtual. Thevirtual is not a general idea, something abstract and empty, but the concept of

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    4/226

    difference (and of life) rendered adequate. The concept of the virtual gives us the

    time of life. Pure, virtual being is real and qualified through the internal process of

    differentiation. Being differs with itself. It does not look outside itself for another or a

    force of mediation because its difference rises from its very core, from ‘the explosive

    internal force that life carries within itself’ (Deleuze, 1988: 105). Deleuze conceives of

    a discrete art with metamorphic force. Deleuze, unlike Baudrillard, manages to pull

    back from the capitalist void and construct a ‘desiring machine’ to manipulate

    capitalist simulacra.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    5/226

     

     ACKNOWLEGEMENTS

    致志的 

    I would like to express my deepest gratitude to my supervisor Professor J.J. Snyman

    for being so patient with my ubuesque research and also for leading me to my

    personnage rhythmique et mon paysage mélodique.

    I am thankful for Professor Lötter’s motivation and for Professor MacKenzie’s élan

    vital.

    Un grand merci à Madame Wilreker pour m’avoir ouvert les voies de l’Art, à Dr. S.

    Leissner pour m’avoir permis de réaliser la force de la mise-en-scène française, et à

    Professeur A.E. Snyman pour m’avoir montré un chemin dans les labyrinthes

    galliques.

    http://www.nciku.com/search/zh/%E4%B8%93%E5%BF%83%E8%87%B4%E5%BF%97http://www.nciku.com/search/zh/%E4%B8%93%E5%BF%83%E8%87%B4%E5%BF%97

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    6/226

     

    TABLE OF CONTENTS

    Chapter One – Force of Destruct ion and Force of Desire

    1.1. Introduction 1

    1.2. Illusion, Allusion, Collusion 3

    1.3. Virtual Ontology 13

    1.4. Preview 20

    Chapter Two – Death of the Social

    2.1. Introduction 26

    2.2. System of Objects 29

    2.3. Waste 39

    2.4. Conclusion 49

    Chapter Three – Symbolic Exchange and Terrorism

    3.1 Introduction 51

    3.2 Symbolic Exchange 53

    3.3. Death 67

    3.4. Symbolic Violence 77

    3.5 Conclusion 87

    Chapter Four – Deleuze: The Politi cs of Life

    4.1. Introduction 89

    4.2. The Plane of Immanence 91

    4.3. Desire and the Social 110

    4.4 Capitalist Cynicism 121

    4.5. Conclusion 129

    Chapter Five – Forces of Sensation

    5.1. Introduction 1325.2. Revolution of Desire 135

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    7/226

    5.3. Imperceptible Aesthetics 143

    5.4. Francis Bacon 157

    5.5. Conclusion 167

    Chapter Six – Baudril lard’s Metastasis and Deleuze’s Metamorphosis

    6.1. Introduction 170

    6.2. Baudrillard’s System of Objects Revisited 173

    6.3. Deleuze’s Plane of Immanence Revisited  187

    6.4. Kafka’s minor joie de vivre  189

    6.5. Conclusion 199

    Bibliography 201

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    8/226

     

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    9/226

      - 1 -

    Chapter One

    Force of Destruction and Force of Desire

    1.1. Introduction

    In the spirit of bricolage, I wish to open the connections between Baudrillard

    and Deleuze. By oblique comparison, by analogy, this study seeks to present

    the ways Baudrillard and Deleuze are of central relevance to today’s social

    and cultural climates. I do not seek to critique Baudrillard but rather push his

    forces of negativity to the limit. Baudrillard’s catastrophic view of the social

    cannot set forth a point of view from which to justify critique, resistance and

    struggle. The only practices he really recommends are total refusal, total

    negativity and radical otherness. Following Marcel Mauss and Georges

    Bataille’s anthropology, Baudrillard claims that power is based on a propensity

    to destroy, disaccumulate, waste and expend. Power by its nature is

    reversible and not productive. The oppressed can turn into the oppressors.

    For Deleuze, on the other hand, power is a productive, positive and

    generative force, and not solely repressive, negative and prohibitive. This is

    based on Deleuze’s view of life and desire. Deleuze emphasises the creative

    and concentrates on the need to transform our perceptions of the world. He

    maintains an optimistic attachment to the political significance of art. For

    Deleuze, artistic revolution is not only a matter of destruction, for one is then

    left with no relations. Liberation occurs through addition. Art breaks one world

    and creates another, and brings these two moments into conjunction to bringsomething new.

    Either one sees the art work as always already constituted, determined by the

    scene of the existing (capitalist) structure. Or one is more optimistic: the art

    work as an event that is truly unexpected. This need not involve a

    transcendent aesthetic. Deleuze reconfigurates art as an event that is

    immanent to this world, as not arriving from some transcendent plane and nottransporting us there, but as emerging from the realm of the virtual. This is the

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    10/226

      - 2 -

    true sense of freedom, an embrace of the virtual that is not limited to the

    possibilities that are contained within our present point of view. Perception

    must therefore be freed from its location or actualised scene. The virtual is life

    in all its imperceptibity. This view of art’s metamorphic power is much stronger

    than Baudrillard’s anti-productive void or terrorism.

    In Baudrillard, everything circulates around the absence of the real: death.

    The object of Baudrillard’s critique holds back and even consumes Baudrillard

    himself. He refuses to participate in the game of producing positive solutions.

    Baudrillard cannot conceive another regime of discourse outside of the

    capitalist simulation structure. For Deleuze, on the other hand, nothing can

    step outside the difference of life, for life always has the power to produce

    further events of difference. Life is transcendental, which means life has no

    ground outside itself. The plane of immanence is the starting point for a

    transcendental method that does not accept that life takes the form of some

    already differentiated or transcendent thing. 

    In post-structuralism, everything revolves around the abandonment of

    ‘transcendence’ – an all-encompassing term for metaphysics, universalism,

    and any theory that seeks to think the whole. The desire for transcendence

    has a complex genealogy in philosophical thought and political philosophy. All

    such logics appear to operate within a space enclosed by a realm of truth that

    also corresponds to a particular form of sovereignty. The universal truth

    claims of each realm are internally related to its corresponding form of

    sovereignty so that post-structuralism engages in a critique of knowledge that

    is at the same time a social critique. For post-structuralism, however, there isneither a logic of development to the historical forms that are criticized nor a

    new set of truth claims about ‘reality’ to be revealed by the critical knowledge

    that is produced. Any such claims concerning a final referent for conceptual

    knowledge would reintroduce a transcendent perspective.

    Deleuze and Baudrillard both undermine the central metaphysical and

    positivist dichotomies, yet they also draw a line that makes it easy todistinguish between friend and foe. Thought that remains directed toward the

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    11/226

      - 3 -

    priority of the identical is charged with having fallen prey to an illusion, be it

    necessary (Baudrillard) or an avoidable one (Deleuze) that obscures and

    falsifies the originary as well as originless play of difference.1  This study

    argues that aesthetics in this kind of post-structuralist context, in their positive

    (Deleuze) and negative (Baudrillard) forms, are examples of thought aiming to

    preserve the difference of otherness.

    Deleuze connects the critique of transcendence to a collectively mediated

    experience and to practical-political strategies of resistance without requiring

    that the collective embody a transcendent identity. This allows for a theoretical

    grasp of socially bonding action and potentials that have a certain universality

    without transcendence. Deleuze is a thinker of synthesis, one who masters

    the immense proliferation of thoughts and concepts by way of assimilation

    and appropriation. Baudrillard is his opposite in this respect, tirelessly

    dissolving all the reified thoughts he encounters back into the void from which

    they allegedly sprang.

    1.2. Illusion, Allusion, Collusion

    In his 1952 essay ‘Pataphysics,’ Baudrillard said that ‘the pataphysic mind is

    the nail in the tire’ (Baudrillard, 2005: 213). He was only 23 when he wrote this

    essay but it introduces many concepts he would work with for the remainder

    of his life. The so-called pataphysical was invented by Alfred Jarry, and

    occupies the place of a comic intermezzo in fin de siècle  French thought.

    Jarry's pataphysics or his science of imaginary solutions was a minor and

    absurd movement of infinitessimal brevity and it represents an obverse andparodic mirror to the philosophically and scientifically serious (Pefanis, 1991:

    9).

    Pataphysics reveals that science is not as lucid as it appears, since science

    must often ignore the arbitrary, if not the whimsical, status of its own axioms.

    Modern science colonises the alterity of the object, leaving no space for poetic

    1Although Deleuze considers this possible, he also regards the mask as a means of expression that isindispensable to every new force: ‘A force would not survive if it did not f irst of all borrow the feature ofthe preceding forces with which it struggles ’(Deleuze, 1983a: 5). 

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    12/226

      - 4 -

    wisdom to speak the truth about nature except through an act of alliance with

    such a norm. Poetic wisdom must adopt the values of modern science in

    order to state any objective verities. Truth is the best ornament because it has

    no ornaments – so science is the best poetry because it has the least poetry.

    The irony is that poetry must draw its rules of metaphor from a genre that

    rules out metaphor. Science becomes the muse of poetry. Jarry does not

    borrow scientific concepts so much as scientific conceits, doing so, in order to

    imagine a ‘counterdynamic’ (Jarry, 1965: 253).

    Pataphysics supplements metaphysics, emphasising it then replacing it, in

    order to create a philosophical alternative to rationalism. Science disappears

    when reason would be pushed to its logical extreme. Such a pataphysical

    qualification of rational validity is symptomatic of a transition in science from

    absolutism to relativism, which can also be characterized as a transition from

    modern to postmodern scientific endeavour (Bök, 2002: 20).

    Pataphysics valorizes the exception to each rule in order to undermine the

    rigidity of science. While a metaphysical science must rule out exceptions,

    such exceptions are the rule. Jarry’s anti-metaphysical metaphilosophy

    argues that anomalies extrinsic to a system remain secretly intrinsic to a

    system. The most credible of truths always evolves from the most incredible

    of errors. The praxis of science involves the parapraxis of poetry. Poetry

    cannot oppose science by being its antonymic extreme. Poetry must push

    reason against itself pataphysically in order to subvert not only the pedantic

    theories of noetic truth but also romantic theories of poetic genius. Such poets

    might learn to embrace the absurd nature of sophistic reasoning in order todispute the power of both the real and the true (Bök, 2002: 5).

    Jarry argues that reality is nothing more than a comparative apperception, an

    as if  for a disparate collection of different views, each one creating the true for

    itself, while opposing every other view (Jarry, 1965: 131). Each perspective is

    thus a solipsistic singularity that has no recourse to perceptual consensus.

    Pataphysics sees that every viewpoint is dissolute – including its own since noview can offer a norm for all others. Jarry suggests that invisible worlds

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    13/226

      - 5 -

    transect our perceived reality at many points across many scales. Jarry

    suggests, through pataphysics, that reality does not exist, reality is never as it

    is but always as if  it is. Reality is quasi, pseudo: it is more virtual than actual; it

    is real only to the degree to which it can seem to be real and only for so long

    as it can be made to stay real. Science for such a reality has increasingly

    become a philosophy of as if , wilfully mistaking possibilities for veritabilities

    (Vaihinger, 1966: xvii).

    For the pataphysical Baudrillard, the world is given to us as enigmatic and

    unintelligible – there is no reason then why we should not attempt to make it,

    in our writing or in our art, more enigmatic and more unintelligible. This takes

    us to the core of Baudrillard's dissatisfaction with the art world – art's task is to

    help us cope with our vital illusion – the fact that we do not know the real,

    merely the appearances behind which it hides. All good art for Baudrillard

    (and the contemporary British painter, Francis Bacon, is an example)

    appreciates this vital illusion that encompasses our existence. In recent years,

    art has become entangled with notions of reality. Baudrillard observes that so

    much contemporary art incorporates waste and notions of worthlessness. For

    Baudrillard, art that has lost illusion is truly worthless. He notes how it is

    interesting that art and its market thrive today to the very extent that they

    decompose.

    Contemporary art for Baudrillard was confiscating banality, waste and

    mediocrity. For Baudrillard, art today connects everything to super-high-tech,

    super-efficient, super-visual style. No void, no ellipsis, no silence. We are

    going more and more in the direction of high definition, that is to say, towardsuseless perfection of the image – which is no longer an image. The more it

    becomes real, the more it is produced in real time, the more we approach

    absolute definition, or the realistic perfection of the image, the more the

    image’s power is lost. The art market is merely a system for aesthetic storage,

    exhibition and recreation, where culture no longer offers an illusion, only the

    memory of illusion. For Baudrillard, art does not come from a natural impulse,

    but from calculated artifice. So it is always possible to question its status, andeven its existence. One has to nullify art in order to look at it for what it is.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    14/226

      - 6 -

    Proclaiming that art is null was not an aesthetic judgment on his part, but an

    anthropological problem. It was a polemic gesture towards culture as a whole,

    which now is simultaneously nothing and everything.

    ‘Art is never the mechanical reflection of the positive or negative

    conditions of the world; it is its exacerbated illusion or hyperbolic mirror.

    In a world of indifference, art can only add to this indifference, by

    focussing on the void of the image or the object that isn’t an object

    anymore. Thus the cinema of Wenders, Antonioni, Altman, Godard or

    Warhol explores the insignificance of the world through the image, and

    by its images contributes to the insignificance of the world – they add to

    its real or hyperreal illusion. Whereas recent cinema like that of

    Scorsese, Greenaway, etc. with its high-tech machinery, and its frantic

    and eclectic agitation, only fills the void of the image, and thus adds to

    our imaginary disillusion’ (Baudrillard, 2005: 115).

    Baudrillard’s provocative and iconoclastic theories are very much in the anti-

    foundationalist line of development. In this study, I will be confronting

    Baudrillard’s theories in order to demonstrate a particularly extreme version of

    the anti judgmental imperative: a version which might be called post aesthetic.

    There is an apocalyptic cast to Baudrillard’s thought:

    ‘For the problem of the disappearance of music is the same as that of

    the disappearance of history: it will not disappear for the want of music

    it will disappear for having exceeded that limit point, vanishing point, it

    will disappear in the perfection of its materiality, in its own special effect(beyond which there is no longer any aesthetic judgement or aesthetic

    pleasure, it is ecstasy of musicality and its end). It is exactly the same

    with history. Here too we have exceeded that limit where, by

    sophistication of events and information, history as such ceases to

    exist’ (Baudrillard, 1986: 21).

    Baudrillard believed that art had exhausted itself and he became associated

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    15/226

      - 7 -

    with the ‘end of art’ theory.2 Baudrillard claims that every possible artistic form

    and function has been exhausted. Furthermore, against Benjamin and

    Adorno, Baudrillard claims that art has lost its critical and negative function.

    Art has entered all spheres of existence. With the realization of art in everyday

    life, art itself as a separate and transcendent phenomenon has disappeared.

    Baudrillard calls this situation ‘transaesthetics’ which he relates to similar

    phenomena of ‘transpolitics,’ ‘transsexuality,’ and ‘transeconomics,’ in which

    everything becomes political, sexual, and economic, so that these domains,

    like art, lose their specificity, their boundaries, their distinctness. In this

    confused state, there can be no more criteria of value, of judgement, of taste,

    and the function of the normative thus collapses into indifference and inertia.

    Our society has given rise to a general aestheticization. In contemporary

    media and consumer society, everything becomes an image, a sign, a

    spectacle, a transaesthetic object, thereby revealing a further dimension of

    the postmodern (Sim, 2000: 87).

    In For a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign (1981), Baudrillard takes

    the painting as a signed object (signature) and as a gestural object, the

    product of artistic gestures or practices. He sees art as exemplary of how

    objects in the consumer society are organized as a system of signs. Art is

    subject to the same rules and system of signification as other commodities

    and follows as well the codes of fashion, determination of value by the market

    and commodification, thus subverting its critical vocation. Modern art is an ‘art

    of collusion vis-a-vis the contemporary world. It plays with it and is included in

    2 The lament that art has come to an end because its choices have been rendered arbitrary dates back

    to Hegel, who claimed in his  Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art  that art had now become ‘a freeinstrument,’ and that nothing ‘stands in and for it-self above this relativity any longer’ (Hegel, 1975: 605).Hegel’s aesthetic repealed modernity before it had even begun, thus simultaneously ensuring that theend would have to be repeatedly invoked (Geulen, 2006: 4). Baudrillard believes he can squeezedialectical surplus value from the end: ‘Perhaps a product of pure simulation might manage to become aseduction, a confrontation with the other, an illusion’ (Geulen, 2006: 4). What Baudrillard callssimulation, Hegel termed dramatization. Among the most subtle post aesthetic art theories are thosethat seek to shake off the Hegelian spectre by emphasising the formlessness of the end, for instance byradically temporalising the end. The dictum Hegel arrogantly decreed can be played off against theunending end presumably operative in works of art. In another vein, the end of art is interpretedantiaesthetically as interruption or rupture (Bohrer, 1981: 86). Perhaps the rediscovery of the sublimefollowing Lyotard in the 1980s can be understood as the effort to locate an antiaesthetic moment deepwithin the aesthetic tradition. With the limit category of the sublime, the end reveals itself as aspecifically antiaesthetic counterlogic of art (Lyotard, 1984). In the context of such strategies, the end of

    art tends to be called a departure (Bohrer, 1996). 

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    16/226

      - 8 -

    the game. It can parody this world, illustrate it, simulate it, alter it; it never

    disturbs the order, which is also its own’ (Baudrillard, 1981: 110).

    Contemporary art had an ambiguous status, halfway between terrorism and

    de facto cultural integration. Art’s collusion was affecting society at large and

    there was no more reason to consider art apart from the rest. Obstacles and

    oppositions are used by the system in order to reinvigorate itself.

    Baudrillard is deliberately provocative. For him there are only signs without

    referents. He presents us with a realm where reality is nothing other than its

    own simulation. This study will engage in the concepts of simulation and

    simulacra and hyperreality, but the major reason for tackling Baudrillard is to

    discover where his post aesthetics takes criticism. Simulation takes us beyond

    foundations. Baudrillard cuts us free from the world of epistemological

    commitments and he delivers us into a value-free realm beyond judgement:

    ’we leave history to enter simulation … this is by no means a despairing

    hypothesis, unless we regard simulation as a higher form of alienation – which

    I certainly do not. It is precisely in history that we are alienated and if we leave

    history we also leave alienation’ (Baudrillard, 1986: 23).

    Baudrillard is not only post aesthetic but also post Marxist. According to

    Marxist theory, alienation is a problem to be worked on and overcome in

    history. The possibility of social change in Marxist terms is being denied in

    Baudrillard with history inexorably accelerating towards its end: ‘everything

    happens as if we were continuing to manufacture history, whereas in

    accumulating signs of the social, signs of the political, signs of progress and

    change, we only contribute to the end of history’ (Baudrillard, 1986: 21).

    For Baudrillard, the Enlightenment has both failed and collapsed and been

    realised, leaving us to wonder what to do next, how can critical thought

    continue to operate in the wake of this fully realised utopia? The ‘golden age’

    of alienation is over and Western cultures enter a new configuration with the

    arrival of simulation processes. Baudrillard identified the dissolution of

    relations between subject and object, true and fake in the triumph ofconsumer capitalism. In consumer capitalism, political and cultural events are

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    17/226

      - 9 -

    modified so fundamentally that in effect they no longer exist apart from their

    mode of representation. Baudrillard sees reality as entirely impregnated by an

    aesthetic that has become inseparable from its own image. The fusion of the

    real and the imaginary means there is no longer a play of representation

    based on clearly demarcated separations: the real swallows its alienated

    double and paradoxically becomes at the same time transparent to itself. In

    this fusion, the aesthetic dimension enters into reality even into what he calls

    the new aesthetic ‘game of reality’ (Baudrillard, 1976: 74).

    There is no longer external repression but the installation of new inner

    controls. The reality principle passes and the more intimate simulation

    principle takes over. This leads Baudrillard to conclude that the principle

    struggle of today is not a political but a cultural revolution. Or rather that the

    cultural revolution must ‘make itself against the economic-political revolution’

    (Baudrillard, 1975:146).

    Baudrillard connects the poetic and the utopian vision of culture. For the poet,

    the important thing is the immediate realisation of utopia: ’Poetry and the

    utopian revolt have this radical presentness in common … the actualisation of

    desire no longer relegated to a future liberation but demanded here

    immediately’ (Baudrillard, 1975: 165). Time in this conception (symbolic) is

    quite different. It is not linear or historical. Utopia in this conception is not to be

    regarded as something in the future to be waited for. In Marxist theory, the

    actual moment of revolt is only an aspect of revolution. For Baudrillard, every

    society is already a complete totality, always already present. Here there is no

    room for a theory of alienated essence which will be recovered at some futurepoint. For each person is completely present at each moment (Gane, 1991a:

    114).

    In Baudrillard, the poetic very much dominates the theoretical. Baudrillard’s

    writing is an artistic strategy. Baudrillard refuses to play the theoretical game. 

    ‘In truth there is nothing left to ground ourselves on. All that is left is

    theoretical violence. Speculation to the death, whose only method is theradicalisation of all hypotheses’ (Baudrillard, 1993a: 5). The sense of

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    18/226

      - 10 -

    detachment that characterises the post aesthetic reflection of Baudrillard

    should not distract us from his highly politically motivated anti foundationalist

    campaign. The playfulness of Baudrillard is reached by means of some very

    serious play indeed:

    ‘Such is the fatality of every system devoted through its own logic to

    total perfection and thus total defectiveness, to absolute infallibility and

    thus incorrigible extinction: all bound energies aim for their own

    demise. This is why the only strategy is catastrophic and not in the

    least dialectical. Things have to be pushed to the limit, where

    everything is naturally inverted and collapses. At the peak of value,

    ambivalence intensifies; and at the height of their coherence, the

    redoubled signs of the code are haunted by the abyss of reversal. The

    play of simulation must therefore be taken further than the system

    permits’ (Baudrillard, 1993a: 4).

    Baudrillard’s work raises the whole problem of how to judge, how to speak

    critically in the absence of outside criteria. How is it possible to criticise

    capitalism’s mise-en-abîme? Capitalism is a self-legitimising, self-authorising

    system, a system that sets the horizons for its own evaluation. For Baudrillard,

    there is no point in opposing capitalism, because there is no ‘outside’ to

    capitalism. Baudrillard does not directly oppose the capitalist system he

    analyses because it is closed, has no other. The very problem this study will

    be looking at in Baudrillard’s work is how to think an other to the capitalist

    system that has no other, in which otherness is its very object. It is not a

    matter of simply refuting or proposing alternatives to capitalism, but thinkingwhat is excluded to allow this all inclusiveness, that other excluded to ensure

    it has no other. In Baudrillard, there is a new notion of criticism, one that

    works not by evidence, enunciation but by annunciation and prescription.

    Baudrillard’s post-structuralism is driven by doubling: thought continues even

    in the absence of any external standards of judgement outside the world and

    its systems (Butler, 1999: 165).

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    19/226

      - 11 -

    Baudrillard does not oppose the perfection of capitalism or technological

    development of art, he does not propose some empirical reason why it is not

    perfect. On the contrary, Baudrillard entirely agrees that capitalist hyperreality

    has no limit – but this only leads to a completely different explanation of the

    one it gives itself. For instance, technological, hyperreal art leads to the end of

    art, or this limitlessness is only possible because of the end of art. Art pushed

    too far leads to the end of art.

    Baudrillard’s work is an endless elaboration of the necessity for aesthetic

    illusion. It is this that must be grasped first of all about his work. Although the

    real is only ever a function of its system (as music today can only be heard

    through technology) there still remains a certain real left out of any attempt of

    the system to speak of it (just as any real music is left out of technology). This

    real might be understood as the very difference between the original and the

    copy, what the original and the copy both resemble and what therefore allows

    them to resemble each other. It is this real that Baudrillard speaks of

    throughout his work, beneath all the different names he gives for it (death,

    symbolic exchange, fatal object, reversibility, illusion, terrorism).

    It is this real excluded by any attempt to speak of it that is the limit to every

    system – it is the Platonic paradox that Baudrillard means by the real. The

    work of Baudrillard endlessly reproduces the paradox first stated in Plato’s

    Cratylus. For Plato, the point was that when two things resemble each other

    too closely they no longer resemble each other anymore. There is no longer a

    relationship of original to copy but two separate originals. The copy only

    resembles the original in so far as it is different from it. The relationship ofresemblance is paradoxical, therefore in that it cannot be pushed too far

    without turning into its opposite: a bad imitation is a good imitation and a too

    good imitation is a bad imitation. There is a limit to the technical perfectibility

    of music, a point beyond which it cannot go except at the risk of no longer

    reproducing music. Beyond this point, technology no longer resembles its

    music, but only itself. It would no longer resemble its music, but would be only

    a simulacrum of it (Butler, 1997: 51).

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    20/226

      - 12 -

    This is Baudrillard’s constant argument. For Baudrillard, the only strategy is

    one of reversibility: the basic codes of a system must be pushed to the point

    where they begin to turn upon themselves, to produce the opposite effects

    from those intended. By pushing capitalism to its furthest extent, Baudrillard

    hopes that it is at this point that it cannot complete itself. Baudrillard wants to

    discover an internal limit, a limit which the system is not prevented from going

    beyond, but which it cannot go beyond. This is Baudrillard’s theory: by

    imitating nothing, by following only its own rule, it is able to catch a system

    that similarly owes nothing to anything, is completely able to account for itself.

    Baudrillard’s point is that each system he analyses creates its own reality.

    Against the undeniable hypotheses of the social, Baudrillard’s writing hopes to

    oppose an equal hypothesis which somehow doubles the social, is able to

    explain how it arises for reasons absolutely different from the ones it gives

    itself.

    For Baudrillard, the true key to this world is this fundamental illusionality. For

    him the world can resemble itself, can realise itself only because of an

    otherworldy explanation: the very difference between the world and itself, the

    real and its copy. It is this point – already two – at which absolute

    resemblance and absolute difference come together (death, reversibility,

    terrorism) that Baudrillard means by the real. For Baudrillard, it is the

    unrepresentable, the unthinkable that is the most real thing in the world. It is

    the vital aesthetic illusion which saves us from the disillusionment of the world

    (Butler, 1997: 62).

    In different ways, post-structuralists like Baudrillard, argued that the origin ofstructures is unrepresentable. Representation already relies on a given

    structure; we represent life through language, so we cannot represent the pre-

    linguistic origin of language. For structuralism, then, we always remain within

    structure, within a system of representation out of which we can never step.

    Baudrillard sees radical thought and the radical use of language as being

    foreign to any resolution of the world in terms of objective reality and its

    deciphering. Baudrillard stops thinking in terms of ontology, because ontologyteaches us that what appears to us is natural and inevitable. Things cannot be

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    21/226

      - 13 -

    otherwise. Baudrillard teaches us that if we think of life solely as what appears

    to us, if we think of what appears to us as exhausting our possibilities, we are

    already hedged into and committed to conformism.

    1.3. Virtual Ontology

    Deleuze agrees with this diagnosis, but not with the cure. Deleuze constructs

    an ontology that is concerned with becoming and experimentation. Deleuze

    attempts to think our own subjectivity differently. Deleuze’s ontology is

    productive, it is not a final answer. It is the opposite. An ontology of difference

    is a challenge to recognize that what is presented to us is only the beginning

    of what there is. We are never finished with living, there is always more. The

    alternatives of contentment (I have arrived) and hopelessness (there is

    nowhere to go) are two sides of the same misguided thought: that what is

    presented to us is what there is.

    Like Baudrillard, Deleuze replaces the practical and rational view of reality

    that we derive from everyday experience, with a philosophical speculative

    account of reality. A central element of this new account is that the human

    being is not presented as a conscious centre of action and belief. In the

    philosophical tradition, the concept of the subject grants precisely such a

    privileged role to the human being and to self-conscious thought. Deleuze’s

    philosophy, like Baudrillard’s, is therefore a critique of the subject. Yet the

    Deleuzean critique is not a straight forward attack or rejection. His philosophy

    constructs different and quite sophisticated arguments to show that what the

    philosophy of the subject takes as an origin or as a basic premise (self-consciousness, individual freedom) is in fact derived from or produced within

    a larger process bearing no resemblance to subjective experience. In

    Deleuze’s account of reality, the human being occupies a limited place as a

    process unfolding amidst other processes to which it is subordinated and with

    which it also interacts.

    Central to Deleuze’s conception of reality is a philosophy of signs andsignification, or semiotics. Signification is here neither a mental occurrence

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    22/226

      - 14 -

    nor a mere social convention. Signification is neither mental, material nor

    social. Signification has its own unique place in reality, its own ontological

    status. Deleuze argues that from the point of view of this special ontological

    status of signification, we can gain a very different conception of the psyche,

    of political power, of social and cultural practices. Deleuze constructs a

    metaphysics and a semiotics in his early work and then applies these

    metaphysical and semiotic principles within the sphere of a general and

    formal social theory. The application of semiotics to a general theory of the

    mind, politics and culture is the joint project of Deleuze and his collaborator,

    the psychiatrist and political activist Félix Guattari, in the two volumes of

    Capitalism and Schizophrenia ( Anti-Oedipus, 1977 and A Thousand Plateaus,

    1987).3 

    The initial metaphysical intuition of Deleuze is very simple: the vital forces that

    can be activated in thought are controlled by an ordering and filtering system

    which imposes on reality a determinate logical structure. We can go beyond

    this logical structure if we produce thoughts that are sufficiently abstract to

    think reality outside of representation. Deleuze’s general account of what it is

    to be, or ontology, therefore leads to a perspective on human life that is in

    conflict with conscious experience. However, Deleuze also seeks to replace

    this conscious subject with another subject, defined by its passage through

    time, its creative potential rather than its conscious experience (Due, 1999: 9).

    The problem of structuralism, to which Deleuze's post-structuralism is a

    response, is the question of the emergence or genesis of all those structures

    with which we use to explain life (such as language, culture, meaning). Wethink, experience and speak through language, but how can we think the

    origin of language? To really respond to the problem of representation, we

    need to think the forces that produce any system of representation. Deleuze's

    3 The connections between Deleuze's separate writings and his collaborations with Guattari are verycomplex and not always clear or consistent; it would be impossible to draw them out in any detail here.If anything, it is the combination of Deleuze's foundational work in the history of philosophy withGuattari's psychiatric and political involvements that gives their work together its particular intensity and

    interest. I draw on both Deleuze and Guattari, whether separately or together. 

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    23/226

      - 15 -

    method is directed against representation, the idea that there is a static or

    meaningless world that is then ordered or represented through culture

    (Colebrook, 2002b: xxxv).

    Signs are not uniquely human. All life is a plane of interacting signs. We are

    confronted by a world of signs and codes: systems and series of biology,

    genetics, history, politics, art and fantasy. And each series of signs creates its

    own lines of difference: genetic differences, chemical differences and so on.

    And all these specific modes of difference are made possible by pure and

    positive difference: a ‘differential power’ that for Deleuze is life itself. There is

    not a simple and undifferentiated life that we then differentiate through signs,

    representations or languages. The signs of a culture are the effects of more

    profound differences. We should try to grasp how signs and differences

    proliferate. Art has a distinct power – opposed to common sense, which works

    with already given signs and conventions – it is the creation of new signs,

    which will allow us to think the emergence of difference. Art presents singular

    differences: the very being of colour, sound, tone or sensibility. Art affirms all

    those differences that allow meanings to appear.

    Art presents us with the power of presentation as such. It might seem that

    such instances give us the exhaustion or end of art, where art can no longer

    do anything but refer to itself. But Deleuze argues that the form of self-

    reference needs to be understood in terms of its potential, or its ‘justification’.

    If there can be a play within a play or a character remembering or an object

    reflected – this is because there can only be the original – the first play or the

    initial character – because life as such is the power to create, to be more thanitself. Art within art or images within images just show what has always

    marked art: the power of opening the virtual from the actual. Art brings the

    virtuality of life to presence. Life is not something that is fully given. Life is a

    potential for multiple creations. Practical relations to the world mostly reduce

    infinite becomings to a closed set of functions; we map an ordered world of

    relations from a stable but repeatable view point. Art, however, repeats the

    events of this actualised world in order to release the further power that wasnot brought to actuality (Colebrook, 2006, 84).

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    24/226

      - 16 -

    Deleuze's project of immanence redefines and reaffirms perception. The

    illusion of transcendence – that there might be some external point from which

    life could be judged – is tied to the problem of point of view. Throughout his

    work Deleuze refers to the ways in which western philosophy has privileged a

    certain ‘optics’. Western thought begins from a subject who views the world,

    assuming a strict distinction between viewer and viewed. There is a world,

    which is then perceived from a number of viewpoints, and these

    representations of the world can be assessed according to their correctness.

    Western thought thereby produces a proper order or sequence for thought.

    The world is actual and original, and this is followed by representations or

    copies, which are virtual and secondary. Deleuze makes important responses

    to what he refers to as this ‘dogma of representation’ (Colebrook, 2002b:

    161).

    Deleuze’s project of immanence abandons the idea that one point of being

    could provide a point of judgement or foundation for being as a whole. This

    means that any connection of beings would be serial not ordered or

    sequential. A series is necessarily multiple and divergent. A series never

    converges into some fixed harmonious unity. A series expands perception

    beyond the human viewer into the universe in general. A linear evolution

    subordinates becoming to some final end; one looks back and sees all the

    changes leading up to one’s own development. From the point of view of the

    present, the past is only presented as a sequence of ordered conditions or

    causes. But Deleuze sees the whole universe as perceptive: responses,

    creations and mutations cannot be explained in terms of the present or interms of the human point of view.

    The past is not some process that culminates in the present human being. It is

    a virtual whole of possibilities that can be retrieved and activated. To affirm life

    means affirming all those changes that go beyond intention, recognition and

    meaning. Art is an attempt to think in an untimely manner. This is the true

    sense of freedom, to embrace the virtual that is not limited to the possibilitiesthat are contained within our present point of view. The virtual is Deleuze’s

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    25/226

      - 17 -

    concept of life as the power to differ, it is possible to perceive life as difference

     – not life that then changes and differs but life as the power to differ.

    Deleuze maintains a passionate and optimistic attachment to the political

    significance of art. For Deleuze, any genuinely creative activity has a political

    significance, precisely because such activities trace new pathways in the

    brain, rather than allowing the ‘most basic conditioned reflexes’ to prevail. The

    task of the artist is not to recognise the world, but to explore all its virtuality.

    This commitment to what one might call a politics of perception is a constant

    in Deleuze’s work.

    Deleuze’s metaphysics of virtuality is the basis of the visionary politics that he

    proposes. Thought for Deleuze involves the construction of a virtual universe

    of images, rather than the contemplation of a world, which pre-exists thought.

    In Deleuze’s books on cinema, thought and perception are matters of speed

    and slowness. There are three orders of speed: there is the infinite speed of

    the virtual image, which is unthinkable in human terms; then there is the

    speed of the actual image which is imperceptible in human terms; finally,

    there is the slowness of representation, which can be perceived in human

    terms. The (crazy) possibility of constructing works of art which attain these

    imperceptible or unthinkable speeds is the cornerstone of Deleuze’s

    aesthetics. Art has the potential to go beyond the representational limitations

    of human perception and move into the realm of the virtual (Marks, 2003:

    117).

    Antonin Artaud, for example, talks of bringing cinema into contact with the‘innermost reality of the brain’, which fragments the thinking subject and

    allows thought to think itself (Deleuze, 1989: 167). This form of cinema might

    be considered as exploring the virtual possibilities of thought and perception.

    Such cinema achieves ‘self-movement’ or ‘automatic’ movement (ibid). It

    gives rise to the conviction that it can act directly on the nervous and cerebral

    system, producing a shock to thought, a new flow of thought. Deleuze’s

    privileging of such non-narrative modern cinema is not reducible to a Frenchavant garde fantasy for the shock of the new, the resistant and difficult. It is

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    26/226

      - 18 -

    grounded on a philosophical commitment to understanding how systems of

    signs emerge.

    To ‘resist’, in Deleuze’s terms, is to refuse to have one’s possibilities for life

    and creativity curtailed, to create something new: it is to go beyond the ‘piety’,

    as he puts it, of recollection (ibid). Resistance is a key theme in Deleuze’s

    work, it involves the refusal to be judged, and the refusal to be forced back on

    one’s own identity and individuality. Resistance means making contact with

    the forces which compose an individual. Resistance is about the capacity to

    direct oneself through perceptions or relations. Theory relates to society in

    and through immanent relations or desires. Revolution is not about destroying

    external political and economic institutions, as well as internal conventions

    and expectations, for one is then left with no relations. Instead revolution

    occurs by bringing in the unexpected amendments, by borrowing strategies

    from elsewhere (Goodchild, 1996: 4).

    There are no true or false presentations, there are just simulations. Any move

    of thought or social relation is desirable so long as it deterritorialises, leaves

    known territory – old or new conventions, because they have become just

    that: coagulations of thought and relations – behind. Capitalism creates

    relations between workers that are temporary and the sites of production

    separate workers from their environment. Everything becomes mobile:

    images, consumer products and people are cut off from their conditions of

    production and circulate globally. Deleuze and Guattari call this

    deterritorialisation. Their views differ from capitalism insofar as they do not

    see deterritorialisation as merely a means for the increase of capital. Nor dothey see deterritorialisation as an end in itself. They wish not to extend

    relations but to intensify social relations. Extension organises the world

    spatially. Extension synthesises the world according to presuppositions or

    intentions. An intensification of relations is an increase in the number of parts,

    dimensions, connections (Goodchild, 1996: 3).

    Intensity will not be produced by a sterile group of objects. This involvesextracting terms from their social and cultural contexts that render them sterile

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    27/226

      - 19 -

    and inactive and assembling them into a constructive machine that is capable

    of producing something. Production does not repeat predetermined

    processes; the machine is singular and its product is entirely new. This

    product can then react back upon and affect its conditions of production,

    becoming a component of further machines. The politics of desire acts directly

    on the unconscious but can only do so by acting directly on its own social

    context at the same time. Theory is an attempt to think otherwise, to explore

    new relations, new subjectivities. Instead of tearing away from truth to show

    that ultimately there is no essence apart from her veils, one adopts the signs

    of truth in order to fabricate something else, even if this is a further patchwork

    of veils and signs. Deleuze and Guattari move away from the mere suspicion

    of truth and pose the problem of philosophy through the power of relation and

    desire.

    Desire is not primarily sexual and they reject the idea that it naturally tends

    toward the formation of a fixed or centred subjectivity. Desire produces real

    relations, connections, investments within and between bodies. In this sense,

    Deleuze and Guattari (1977: 30) say ‘desire produces reality’. Desire is not

    constituted by the ever-renewed and impossible attempt to regain a lost object

    of satisfaction. The point is to deny that unsatisfied desire is the essence of

    desire. Deleuze and Guattari’s theory of desire is constructivist.

    Desire permeates all social relations, penetrates the body at a sub-individual

    level, and implements an immediately political investment of the body within

    larger circuits of action and production. Deleuze explicitly aligns his

    conception of desire with Nietzsche’s conception of life as the will to power. Abody will increase in power to the extent that its capacities to affect and be

    affected become more developed and differentiated. Deleuze follows Spinoza

    in calling such capacities to be affected the ‘affects’ of a body. These

    correspond to the transition of the affected body from one state to another.

    Affects are intensive, they are not objectifiable or quantifiable. The

    proliferation of intensities in art disrupts the unified viewing subject. It is the

    power of art to produce disruptive affects that allows us to think intensities,and to open lines of movement to differences in kind.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    28/226

      - 20 -

    1.4. Preview

    This study does not seek to systematise or freeze a deleuze-baudrillardian

    connection or be a self-confirming representation. I therefore proceed in

    piecemeal fashion. This dissertation begins at Chapter Two, in which I will

    show that for Baudrillard, the theorist of today confronts a sociality which

    mimics a mere model of itself – a culture cynically living the ideal of its own

    electronic image, a hyperrealism and a hypersociality (in which what is

    artificial is indistinguishable from what is real). I outline the simulated system

    of equivalences (sign value, exchange value and use value). I will make

    reference to Baudrillard’s use of Alfred Jarry’s farcical pataphysical Ubu,

    whom Baudrillard sees as the definitive hypostasis of capitalism. A system is

    ‘ubuesque’ due to its hyperplastic spiral into what is more real than the real.

    As a figure of the social, Ubu comes to absorb everything, leaving no

    remainders, just as the social, in progressively eliminating by absorbing all of

    its residues, itself becomes residual. The social system begins to develop

    programmes out of its own 'living waste' in search of new bases of legitimacy.

    In Chapter Three I will show that Baudrillard abandons social theory. He

    refers to theory as, among other things, a ‘mode of disappearance’. Theory no

    longer represents or mirrors the real, but rather must be the pataphysical

    intensification of its object. For Baudrillard, this calls for a ‘theoretical violence’

     – a stylistic excess whose function is to be as ‘extreme’ as the object itself. In

    the intensification of writing, theory renounces its distance and merges with its

    object. Baudrillard’s notion of ‘challenge’ has metaphysical andanthropological resonances. Baudrillard assumes that pre-capitalist societies

    are governed by forms of ‘symbolic exchange’ similar to Bataille’s notion of

    general economy and Mauss’s gift and counter-gift. Baudrillard returns to

    symbolic societies as his revolutionary alternative to capitalist values and

    practices. Symbolic exchange is ambivalent, non-equivalent and non-

    reductive. Gratuitous gift-giving, sacrifice and destruction stand outside the

    logic of capital which tries to control and profit from every aspect of life.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    29/226

      - 21 -

    In reaction to the events of September 11 2001, Baudrillard pushed his fatal

    strategy further by claiming that the sacrifice and death of the Islamic

    terrorists were the ultimate event against capitalism. For Baudrillard terrorists

    create a void around themselves, a vacuum of non-meaning. Terrorist acts

    cannot be understood as grounded in the objectives of the terrorists; that is at

    the level of content of their demands. Baudrillard completely empties Islamic

    terrorism of any characteristics or qualities other than of pure disruption. Islam

    is defined in terms of what it is not.

    In Chapter Four I will move on to Deleuze’s concept of life. There are three

    qualities that characterize life in Deleuzian thought: positivity, productivity, and

    incorporeality. Productivity is the creative aspect of life. Incorporeality means

    that life must be thought temporally if it is to make any sense; and here

    Deleuze's debt to Bergson is profound. Chapter Four will navigate through

    Deleuze's early work to discern a powerful, progressive evolution: Bergson,

    Nietzsche, Spinoza. These philosophers form a foundation for Deleuze's

    thought. Deleuze's work, however, does not stop with a revalorization of this

    alternative tradition: He selects what is living and transforms it, making it

    adequate to his concerns. In this way, he both makes the history of

    philosophy his own and makes it new.

    Deleuze's ontology is grounded in the conceptions of difference that he

    discovers in Bergson and Spinoza. Bergsonian difference defines, above all,

    the principle of the positive movement of being, that is, the temporal principle

    of ontological articulation and differentiation (the virtual or duration).

    Opposition, Deleuze claims, is too crude a notion to capture the nuances thatmark real differences. In the Spinozian context, the positivity of being is

    characterized by its singularity and its univocal expression. The singularity of

    Spinoza's being is not defined by its difference from an other, from nonbeing,

    but rather by the fact that being is different in itself.

    Deleuze constructs a concept of life on the basis of Spinoza (univocity),

    Bergson (the virtual or duration) and Nietzsche (will-to-power or desire). Eachone envelops a possibility of life, expresses a particular point of view on life,

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    30/226

      - 22 -

    differentiates in its own way, the indeterminate element of life. And in its own

    way, resolves the problem of living. Life obeys a logic of internal difference.

    There is no identity to life nor is there life in general, there are only

    differentiated ways of living (and ways of thinking that envelop ways of living)

    Life exists only in being differentiated, in its internal difference, or that which

    affirms itself only in differing from itself.

    Chapter Four will also show that Deleuze's politics are based on his concept

    of life as internal difference. The struggle to promote life – to promote positive

    difference, production of the real, and a fluid incorporeality of events – is

    pursued against a background which is that of life itself. What Deleuze values

    is life, its unfolding and its various concrete realizations. But in valuing life, the

    question arises of why there would ever be a politics, and political struggle, in

    the first place? If everything is already positive, then what is there to revolt

    against?

    Deleuze values life, yet he does not value everything that is actual. It is not

    the same to affirm life in its temporality and to affirm everything that occurs

    within this temporality. What is at issue, if the need for a politics is to become

    manifest, is how it is that negativity is introduced into life. How is it that life can

    admit of negativity, death, or repression, if it is pure positivity and productivity

    in its principle? If negativity comes later, as Deleuze's anti-dialectical position

    insists, then how does it come? In the book on Nietzsche negativity arises in

    the question of how active forces can become reactive, when active forces

    are the only ones that act. In Anti-Oedipus, written with Guattari, it appears as

    the question of how desire can desire its own repression.

    Desire, or life, exists only within the context of a determinate social situation.

    In that social situation, there are forces that work against life, but not by

    repressing it from the outside. The problem of repression or negativity is not

    that it comes to bear upon life from something which is not life, but that it is a

    possibility internal to life itself as it unfolds under determinate social

    conditions.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    31/226

      - 23 -

    Life, although naturally fluid, can produce that which blocks production; it

    produces anti-production. All other negativity, repression, and death follows

    from this.

    Deleuze and Guattari have given many names to the types of interventions

    that attempt to release life. The most well known of these is the line of escape

    or flight. In conceiving the line of escape, what are commonly called political

    structures must be understood not in the spatial metaphor of structure but in

    the temporal metaphor of coding or axiomatizing. Flows of life are coded, they

    are constrained into precise networks which act like channels to divert them

    along specific routes and in specific directions. Kinship rituals in ‘primitive

    societies’ are ways of coding sexual production (production of pleasures as

    well as of children). And ‘overcoding’, a state process, is a way of making the

    various codes in different sectors of a given society ‘resonate’ together.

    Finally, in capitalist societies, flows which are no longer subject to traditional

    forms of coding are axiomatized, administered by broad constraints that

    regulate whole areas of experience rather than specific flows. The regulations,

    formal and informal, of investment banking provide an example of axiomatized

    flows of money.

    Deleuze and Guattari see cynicism as a structural effect of a social machine

    in which axioms replace codes. In capitalism power is indifferent to the

    intentions of its rulers. Deleuze and Guattari argue that the defining

    characteristic of capital is not simply the difference between being ruled by

    individuals or abstractions, but by being ruled by abstractions produces and

    presupposes its own particular form of subjectivity. Money is not simply aquantity, a unit of measure, but a complex relation.

    Lines of flight are flows that break with both the axioms and the codes of a

    given society in order to create new forms of life that are subversive to the

    repressions of that society. They do not flow along regulated pathways, but

    are instead ‘transversal’ to them, cutting across them and using elements

    from them in the process of producing something new, different, and mostimportant, alive. It would be a mistake to say that the productions of a line of

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    32/226

      - 24 -

    flight are prohibited by the society it arises from; its productions have probably

    never been considered for prohibition by that society. Instead, a line of flight

    subverts life's attachment to the negativity of repressive social constraints. A

    line of flight is not an escape from society. It is an escape from the negativity

    of determinate social conditions within a society. For Deleuze, life is the core

    of reality; the negativity that must be escaped is derivative.

    In Chapter Five I will move specifically to art’s line of flight. For Deleuze it is

    the artist who sees the limit of the liveable (exhausts the ‘lived’). The artist

    lives what was enveloped within lived experience, yet nevertheless was not

    lived through (the virtual). Art expresses something other than itself: life in all

    its imperceptibility. In art, sight is potentialized, raised to a second power. In

    its ordinary employment sight is separated from what it can do. Sight regains

    its power when it sees the invisible or imperceptible, or when what cannot be

    seen is perceived: the invisible enveloped in what is seen not as a hidden

    world beyond appearance but animating sight itself from within appearance,

    or what one sees. I will show that for Deleuze, Francis Bacon, as a painter of

    forces or sensations, shows an experience of the body that leads one beyond

    the phenomenological lived body to the chaotic body without organs. This

    means deforming organised forms of conventional representation. Bacon

    paints the body, the figure of sensation as opposed to the figurative body of

    conventional representation.

    The body with organs is a virtual state of being, an unorganised level of life.

    Deleuze and Guattari argue that the image of the organism is really opposed

    to desire. Desire must be understood to embody the power of metamorphosisor differential reproduction, which is the condition of creativity in culture as

    well as in nature. Social production stabilises, identifies and codes the flow of

    pure becoming and differentiation. I show the various historical stages of

    Deleuze and Guattari’s political theory of desire and how each stage has its

    own dominant form of synthesis. The first synthesis is that of connection

    (primitive society). Then there is the second synthesis of disjunction (State).

    Then there is the third synthesis of conjunction (Capitalism).

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    33/226

      - 25 -

    These syntheses are important because art is itself composed of these

    syntheses. The problem for art is to create a desiring machine that

    synthesises flows of desiring production that forms multiple connections,

    disjunctions, conjunctions and thereby produces and sustains movement. The

    artwork establishes syntheses between elements that in themselves do not

    communicate, and that retain all their difference in their own dimensions. This

    requires passive synthesis. Art establishes ‘transversals’ between the

    elements of multiplicities, but without ever reducing their difference to a form

    of identity or gathering up the multiplicity into a totality. Deleuze and Guattari

    describe the movement of desire, but they also speak at length of the ways in

    which movement is blocked, encoded, channelled into circuits that are limited

    in their connections, exclusive in the disjunctions and fixed in their

    conjunctions.

    In the concluding synthesizing chapter I shall emphasize that for both Deleuze

    and Baudrillard resistance is not opposition; it constantly accompanies power.

    For Baudrillard it is the spiral of intensification, the raising of the power that

    counts. The massive logic of the capitalist system can only be resisted by

    redoubling capitalism back against itself in a movement of hyperconformist

    simulation. Baudrillard’s critique rests upon an allegorical mode of reading

    and writing. Allegory, as defined by Walter Benjamin, ‘is appropriated

    imagery; the allegorist does not invent images but confiscates them' (Owens,

    1980a: 69). Benjamin saw the critical yield of the allegorical way of seeing.

    The task of criticism is not to conjure up the appearance of the world ‘as it

    really was,’ restoring a false totality to it, but to collaborate with the corrosive

    effects of the passage of time. Deleuze has a more affirmative notion of theaesthetic impulse. Art must be thought as the expression of possible worlds.

    Deleuze can always hear a song to life in the artists he admires, such as

    Franz Kafka, however violent or intense their work. With Deleuze there is no

    resigned and pessimistic cult of death. It is to this cult of death in Baudrillard

    that I now turn.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    34/226

      - 26 -

    CHAPTER 2

    Baudrillard: Death of the Social

    2.1. Introduction

    Baudrillard totalizes the social.4 The present, he claims, serves as testimony

    to a perfect socialization; the social expanded to infinity. What emerges most

    powerfully from this is Baudrillard’s sense of the pathology of society.5 At the

    very moment of totalization, the social attempts to extend the sphere of social

    relations to residual groups on the margins of society in order to normalize

    and institutionalize society's relations with what lies outside its boundaries(the so-called remainder). After the inclusion of that which has previously

    remained at the margins of the social, the social totality (which survives and

    grows only through its capacity to generate and administer to marginal

    elements) reverts back on itself and designates itself as the (sole) remainder.

    In Baudrillard’s view, the social leaves nothing unscathed. It transforms

    everything it draws into its dynamics and thereby turns everything into someform of waste that has to be assigned a social utility and social function. This

    process of the production and redesignation of waste not only defines the

    essence of the social but to give a meaning to wasted lives (which now

    includes everyone), to assign a use-value to what has been rendered useless

    (society as a whole) – that, for Baudrillard, is the face of the social today.

    However, Baudrillard is not content to leave us with this almost indelibly

    oppressive characterization of the social. He takes it one step further. This

    4Baudrillard's notion of the ‘social’ cannot be precisely defined, although the general way in which heemploys the term is fairly clear. For reasons essentially having to do with economy of style, henominalizes the adjectival form of the word as a convenient gloss for an entire range of key terms in thesocial scientific lexicon, e.g. -social structure, social relation, social class, social institution, socialexchange, social interaction, social theory, etc., which taken together with related concepts comprisethe master discourse on society.5Durkheim also emphasizes the pathological features of industrial society and vividly discusses thenegative effects of the high-velocity circulation of bodies, ideas and commodities. Mike Gane(1991a:199-203) usefully compares the two thinkers but concludes (1991a:201-2) that a majordifference ultimately divides them: ‘Durkheim locates himself (not without some hesitations) in theflawed, unfulfilled, or rather incomplete project of the culture of organic societies, in the project for a

    sociology as a science of society. Baudrillard is based in primitive symbolic exchange, and develops aform of sociology which is best described as transtheoretical, a form of resistance from the irrational anda theoretical fatwa against the modern and postmodern system’.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    35/226

      - 27 -

    face has ‘disappeared’.6  In presenting this paradox of an almost tactile

    oppressive regime, which is either unrecognizable or invisible (or both),

    Baudrillard points to another disturbing characterization of contemporary

    social formations.

    For Baudrillard, the web of social relationships, which is the empirical ground

    and reality principle for a uniquely sociological enterprise, has collapsed into a

    homogeneous mass.7  This is the product of a social process, yet can no

    longer be identified with any particular social subject or object. As a result, the

    social field today is purely simulated. This is the outcome of a cultural levelling

    effect created by modern technologies. The social no longer serves to

    designate or analyze anything. This is what we are seeing today – a generalawareness that the social realm is, and has always been, only a delusion. The

    existence of a socius, the critico-empirical postulate of a social order based on

    symbolic reciprocity and companionship, is no longer even a question.

    For Baudrillard, contemporary culture is fascinated by extremes. In a culture

    of electronic reproduction, television has become more true than the true;

    computer models are more real than the real, fashion is more beautiful thanthe beautiful, catastrophe is more eventful than the event and the mass is

    more social than the social. This is the wasteful excess of a culture where the

    faster everything goes, the less anything seems to go anywhere. The reaction

    to all this is a desperate attempt to redeem a meaning for life, work and

    communication that have become useless and meaningless. Baudrillard

    compares present society with the irreversible growth of a cancerous cell in

    6 Baudrillard's style presents the first and most difficult obstacle for anyone more accustomed to thelinguistic conventions of Anglo- American social theory. Rarely does he take the time to define histerms-the social, mass, disappearance, etc. with any degree of precision or construct detailedarguments in support of his position. His mode of expression is intentionally elliptical, declarative,replete with poetic allusions, and marked by abrupt transitions. As Mark Poster (1988: 7) has noted,Baudrillard has a tendency to simply proclaim his insights and make light of apparently contradictoryconclusions which can be drawn from his remarks. Baudrillard does this intentionally, with fullawareness of what he is doing. 7  ‘Mass’ is another of Baudrillard's terms which is impossible to define precisely. He does claim,although not always consistently, that he is not referring to the conventional meaning of the term incritical social theory, viz., the working classes. Similar to his use of ‘the social,’ ‘mass’ often functions asa gloss, and occasionally as a punning device, for a number of related concepts within the socialsciences-mass culture, mass society, etc. The primary connotation of the term, however, appears to be

    physical, as when Baudrillard speaks elliptically of the ‘black hole’ of the mass, which absorbs all theenergy of the social. The images Baudrillard often wishes to convey with the term are those ofrandomness, implosiveness, fragmentation, and entropy.

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    36/226

      - 28 -

    which all attempts to control the decay only result in intensifying it until social

    life finally exhausts itself, collapsing from its own weight and inertia.

    The above stated view of present day society causes problems for a theory

    about such a society. For Baudrillard, simulation closes off forever the

    possibility of an ideological critique of social theory, precisely because such a

    critique cannot itself break free from the assumption of the reality principle of

    the social. Baudrillard sees distinct types of simulation. In the first type, the

    reality principle, which makes possible a distinction between a state of affairs

     – notwithstanding its absence – and its representation, remains intact. In the

    second type, the reality principle itself disappears; simulation winds up

    ‘mistaking’ reality with its reproduction. Better, rather than simple reproduction

    (or even reduplication), what is involved in later stages of simulation is the

    perfect substitution of signs of the real for the real itself – the real, in other

    words, simulation is elevated to the status of a copy without an original.  For

    Baudrillard, it is the third phase, which inaugurates the space of simulation

    proper, while the fourth marks its perfection. In the third phase, the image

    masks the absence of a basic reality, whilst the fourth phase bears no relation

    to any reality whatever: it is its own pure simulacrum.

    Simulation proposes the system on the basis of a certain other but simulation

    in the end always seeks to master this other. This chapter will show how

    Baudrillard’s simulated and totalised social puts forward an ‘other’ but what is

    realised is that this ‘other’ only exists because of the social, only leads to a

    growth in the system. This is the ability of the social to prove itself via the

    remainder .  The social exists to take care of the useless consumption ofremainders so that individuals can be assigned to the useful management of

    their lives. In Baudrillard’s total system, utility is the dominant principle but it

    exists only as simulation. According to Baudrillard, the economic is born when

    what the object 'is', is assumed to reside within it, it has an essence; when the

    object attains its value in accordance with an abstract code that enables its

    relation to other objects to be ascertained through a logic of equivalence

    which in turn obtains its rationale from the ideology of utility and use value;and when the individual emerges as a 'subject' whose relation to the world of

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    37/226

      - 29 -

    objects is articulated primarily through the ideology of need. From this critical

    viewpoint, the notion of the 'individual' emerged.

    This chapter will proceed as follows: I will first outline the simulated system of

    equivalences (sign value, exchange value and use value) and then show how

    the system safeguards itself by developing many means of waste and

    controlled squandering. I will make reference to Baudrillard’s use of Alfred

    Jarry’s farcical plays. This is not meant as comic intermezzo or relief. Rather,

    Baudrillard’s parody intensifies his apocalyptic vision of the totalized system of

    objects.

    2.2. System of Objects

    Baudrillard’s teacher, Henri Lefebvre, in his Critique of Everyday Life (1992), 

    had turned sociology to the ordinary domestic world, to the objects that

    surround us. It was important for Lefebvre to analyse these things exactly

    because their ideological effects were so easily overlooked or taken for

    granted. His argument was that in consumer society commodities become

    abstracted, and thereby alienated or estranged, from real human contexts,

    and that needs and desires become manipulated by power. Lefebvre critiqued

    everyday society in order to restore an authentic relationship between subject

    and objects and make objects more responsive to actual needs (Poster, 1979:

    253).

    Lefebvre’s Marxist approach wanted to believe in the true value and meaning

    of objects and the possibility of unalienated needs and desires with regard tothem. In capitalism, exchange value functions to mystify use value, because

    the labor process disappears from view leaving a pure object of consumption

    determined solely by a price. For Marx labour is a necessary condition,

    independent of all forms of society; it is an external nature-imposed necessity.

    Without which there can be no material exchanges between man and nature

    and therefore no life. The problem for Marx was that capitalism obscured the

    objective value of labour, so that workers earned less than their labour wasobjectively worth and were thus exploited. Marxism convinces men that they

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    38/226

      - 30 -

    are alienated by the sale of their labour. In the Marxian schema, use-value –

    the glorious autonomy of man’s simple relation to his work and his products –

    is the nemesis of abstract exchange and the promise of a future resurgence

    beyond the fetishism of money and the market. Marxists, like Lefebvre, tried

    to locate and rediscover a natural relation to use value undistorted by

    capitalist exchange value. Lefebvre’s critique leaves the assumptions of use

    value and the ideology of needs intact (and in fact more firmly reconstitutes

    them) (Poster, 1979: 280).

    Roland Barthes (with whom Baudrillard would later collaborate and teach)

    wanted to break with Lefebvre’s Marxist approach. Barthes’s Mythologies 

    showed how relationships with objects are always mediated by the sign.

    Objects are not to be seen in terms of use and function but in terms of

    communication. Objects form a certain language within which such values as

    use and function are merely rhetorical. There is not some underlying

    denotation to the object, but only an endless succession of connotations

    (Barthes, 1972: 116).

    Baudrillard inherits these two contrasting approaches of Lefebvre and Barthes

    toward the everyday object. In System of Objects (1996), Baudrillard attempts

    to fuse the anti-abstractionism of Lefebvre and the abstractionism of Barthes.

    Like Barthes, for Baudrillard every object becomes connotation (of a

    denotation). For Baudrillard the modern world is to be grasped in an analogy

    with 'generalized hysteria'. Understanding and reading the world of needs and

    objects literally will fall into the traditional error of treating the symptom only to

    find another reappearing in a different site. A way of approaching the issue isto imagine that there are two quite different languages, which interpenetrate:

    the logic of objects is a vast paradigm 'through which something else speaks'

    (Baudrillard, 1988: 45). Yet what is spoken from the deeper language is

    realized as a 'lack' which cannot be satisfied at the surface. Just as with the

    hysteric, 'this evanescence and continual mobility reaches a point where it

    becomes impossible to determine the specific objectivity of needs' (ibid.,45).

    ‘In the hysterical or psychosomatic conversion, the symptom, like the

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    39/226

      - 31 -

    sign, is (relatively) arbitrary. Migraine, colitis, lumbago, angina, or

    generalized fatigue: there is a chain of somatic signifiers which the

    symptom 'walks' along – as there is an interlinking of object/signs, or

    object/symbols, along which walk, not needs … but desire, and a further

    determination, that of unconscious social logic’ (Baudrillard, 1970: 107,

    295-296).

    Baudrillard attempted to achieve a non-essentialist notion of fetishism as a

    theory of ‘the perverse structure that perhaps underlies all desire’; thus

    transformed it might become, he hoped a genuine analytic concept

    (Baudrillard, 1981: 90). If fetishism exists, it is fetishism of the signifier,

    leading to the manipulation not of the concrete commodity but of the abstract

    sign. For example, money fetishism is not a fetishism for a substance but for

    the abstract system in its systemic fascination. For Baudrillard, one of the

    consequences of the object’s entry into the field of the sign is that just like the

    individual elements of language, no object has any meaning in itself but in its

    relationship with other objects. The very system of objects precedes the

    possibility of any single object. Consumers do not so much directly desire any

    specific object as desire only in a competitive relationship with others, as

    mediated by the social signs of status and prestige. We desire only another’s

    desire (Butler, 1999: 27).

    The fundamental paradox of the sign on which the system of objects is based,

    is that if the comparison opened up by the sign (the fact that every object can

    be compared to another, that our desire is given to us by way of another)

    means that everything can be consumed, that nothing is outside the system ofconsumption, it also means that nothing can be consumed, that everything is

    outside the system of consumption, in so far as we actually never consume

  • 8/18/2019 Aesthetic Force in Baudrillard and Deleuze

    40/226

      - 32 -

    anything as such but only insofar as it resembles the desire for another.8 The

    fact that everything can be compared in terms of the sign means that there is

    nothing outside consumption, it also means that nothing is actually consumed

    because it is only consumed as something else. The fundamental limit of

    consumption is that in the very act of consumption something goes missing;

    the very thing i.e. the sign that allows and forces us to consume also means

    that we cannot, that there is nothing to consume. We only consume the myth

    of consumption. Baudrillard emphasizes much more than Barthes the inherent

    abstraction of the system of objects. Yet at the same time Baudrillard also

    wants to speak like Lefebvre against a system of objects, to show in the end

    why there is no such thing as a system of objects, why any description of the

    system of objects cannot be divorced from a critique of that system’s practical

    ideology (Baudrillard, 1998: 316).

    With Lefebvre, Baudrillard wants to show what is excluded from this system of

    objects, what the limit is to its organization through signs. The system of

    objects is the most complete expression of function; function is only possible

    in the form of the sign. The System of Objects  shows that function and use

    are no longer real but only effects of the sign, only rhetorical values within the

    system of objects (and that they were perhaps like this from the beginning).

    Nature becomes naturality and function becomes functionality. Functionality is

    the lynchpin of the system: ’Every object claims to be functional like every

    regime claims to be democratic’ (Baudrillard, 1996: 89).