a critique on the falsification of free

23
A critique on the falsification of free will by using Libet- style experiments Xavier Meulders E-mail: xavier.meulders[at]gmail.com Abstract : From the late 20 th century onwards, the idea of a free conscious will which we tend to attribute to each rational human being is coming under serious pressure. It seems that with the experiments of the psychologist Benjamin Libet and, more recently, John-Dylan Haynes, the idea of free conscious will has to sing its final swan song. But if the idea of free will might be a dogmatic relic from pre-scientific times, then this also counts for the famous proverb that science always ought to have the right on a last, final judgement. In this paper, we will examine both the 'weak' and 'hard' problem of experiments conducted in the positivist spirit of Libet and Haynes. Do the experiments have much explanatory power? What about the issue of causality and predictability? Can conscious experience be naturalized to its physical substratum? And what about the nature of deliberate action? These are the main questions that will be addressed in this paper. In most contemporary debates on the issue of free will, the paradigm of physicalist reductionism seems to conquer the minds and hearts of most scientists, and even a huge range of philosophers. The latter is of course a pure embarrassment, since it ought to be one of the ultimate tasks of philosophy never to lose its critical eye on the (recent) discoveries of the positivist sciences, since positivism itself is a metatheoretical framework as well, that should (and could !) severely be put into question. In these reductionist times of “scientism”, as F.A. Hayek would have called it, the danger seems to come from the current attempts of so-called “neurobiology”, trying to convince both the scientific researcher and the interested layman that our current conception of free will is nothing more but a premodern relic, stemming out of ‘mystical’ traditions such as folk psychology, or even religious beliefs, that cannot be sustained by the current discoveries in neuroscience. It seems of course quite obvious that physical determinism seems to be a welcome ally of already existing forms of “cultural” and/or “anthropological” determinism, which states that each person is an object pushed and thrown in a pinball machine between

Upload: aldo-prieto

Post on 05-Dec-2015

217 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

DESCRIPTION

free will

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

A critique on the falsification of free will by using Libet-style experiments

Xavier Meulders E-mail: xavier.meulders[at]gmail.com

Abstract: From the late 20th century onwards, the idea of a free conscious will which we tend to attribute to each rational human being is coming under serious pressure. It seems that with the experiments of the psychologist Benjamin Libet and, more recently, John-Dylan Haynes, the idea of free conscious will has to sing its final swan song. But if the idea of free will might be a dogmatic relic from pre-scientific times, then this also counts for the famous proverb that science always ought to have the right on a last, final judgement. In this paper, we will examine both the 'weak' and 'hard' problem of experiments conducted in the positivist spirit of Libet and Haynes. Do the experiments have much explanatory power? What about the issue of causality and predictability? Can conscious experience be naturalized to its physical substratum? And what about the nature of deliberate action? These are the main questions that will be addressed in this paper.

In most contemporary debates on the issue of free will, the paradigm of physicalist reductionism seems to conquer the minds and hearts of most scientists, and even a huge range of philosophers. The latter is of course a pure embarrassment, since it ought to be one of the ultimate tasks of philosophy never to lose its critical eye on the (recent) discoveries of the positivist sciences, since positivism itself is a metatheoretical framework as well, that should (and could !) severely be put into question.

In these reductionist times of “scientism”, as F.A. Hayek would have called it, the danger seems to come from the current attempts of so-called “neurobiology”, trying to convince both the scientific researcher and the interested layman that our current conception of free will is nothing more but a premodern relic, stemming out of ‘mystical’ traditions such as folk psychology, or even religious beliefs, that cannot be sustained by the current discoveries in neuroscience. It seems of course quite obvious that physical determinism seems to be a welcome ally of already existing forms of “cultural” and/or “anthropological” determinism, which states that each person is an object pushed and thrown in a pinball machine between different forms of empirical parameters as “income inequality”, “discrimination”, “Western cultural prejudices”, etc. ; factors, of course, that should be dealt with by implementing extensive government programmes. Physical determinism also endorses this paradigm, and some moral philosophers therefore even concluded – albeit by using a non sequitur… - that our concept of “personal liability”, as it is widely used as an indispensable key concept in most moral and legal theories and frameworks, should be abolished as well: if human beings are nothing but bundles of matter determined by certain causal processes, then we could not hold them accountable for anything they do. And yes, some scientists and philosophers therefore even maintain that we should re-edit the whole corpus of Western legislation in order to reduce the whole judicial investigation of guilt versus innocence to the pragmatic questions which physical ‘stimuli’ could be the most effective in order to transform the criminal’s mind into something rather desirable by society, whatever that means.

How counter-intuitive the paradigm of ‘scientistic’ (not scientific) physicalism may seem, and how spurious the conclusions they draw from their investigations may be, it is nevertheless a paradigm on the popular move, that seems very attractive to the latest generation of psychological and social engineers applying to get a new job in order to implement their mad

Page 2: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

behaviouristic ideas. But being a counterintuitive idea of course cannot count as a proof for its intellectual and conceptual error. A more profound philosophical investigation is needed in order to refute the intellectual heirs of B.F. Skinner and their dream of a society built along the model of Walden Two.

I. A brief overview of the used paradigm from Libet to now

The dream of a determinist view on the human kind first appeared on the philosophical scene with the refreshed interest in ‘atomistic’ explanations and descriptions of reality, which was due to the final collapse of scholastic Aristotelian philosophy around the 14 th century. Thomas Hobbes, for instance, wrote of humankind not as a being guided by his reason or virtues, but instead driven by immediately present emotions, passions and external causes. The 18 th

century philosophers conceived of the same human being as someone, or rather: some thing, without an inherent, agent-relative ‘telos’, but instead a mechanical framework, hence seducing thinkers such as Jullien Offray De la Mettrie to write treatises titled as “L’Homme Machine” (“Man a Machine”)

But the materialist universe, that already by the 19th finally overthrew the idea of a divine entity that even by someone as Isaac Newton ought to be needed as a first efficient cause to put the universe into motion, still had to cope with the folk psychological idea of a “first cause” in deliberate human action, i.e. the idea that there would exist something as a ‘free will’, conceived by the materialists as a remnant of ancient thinking and definitely in need of an “immaterial soul” in order to exist.

The 20th century with its rise in ‘experimental’ psychology and the soaring interest for research fields such as the cognitive sciences – who finally detached themselves from the philosophical (read as: “speculative”) faculties to whom they once belonged… - could finally give the fatal blow to the illusion of free will. This job seemed to have been done by the notorious Libet-experiments, conducted in the early 1980s by the Californian psychologist Benjamin Libet.

The setting of the experiment was quite simple1: the participants of the experiments were sitting in front of a clock – the “Libet clock” – on which a red spot would turn clockwise with a certain speed. The participants were then asked to choose to press a button at a certain moment, which they may deliberately chose. Meanwhile, the participants were wired to a number of electronic devices – a rather technical issue on which I won’t further elaborate for present philosophical purposes – that recorded the “stimuli” occurring in the brain while performing the acts of conscious awareness, choosing and actually pressing the button.

Libet, then, famously argued that 0.5 second before actually pressing the button, there already occurred an intensified neural activity which he called the ‘readiness potential’. The conscious awareness of actually intending to press the button, then, occurred something like 0.2 second before the action. Hence, the simplified scheme of Libet’s conclusions:

1 For a clearer overview of the Libet experiment, including an animation of the Libet clock, see http://www.blutner.de/philom/consc/consc.html

Page 3: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

Nevertheless, Libet made a modest attempt to uphold the idea of free will, by introducing the concept of a “veto right” of the will: although the readiness potential seems to “determine” the outcome of our actual decision, Libet argued that there nevertheless must exist a certain point in time were conscious will can, indeed, deliberately choose not to follow the motoric input provided by the readiness potential. However, this Libetian deus ex machina cannot count as a staunch concept to preserve the idea of free will, since it is in fact the theoretical framework of Libet-style experiments altogether that appears to be rather questionable.

Moreover, the Libet-experiment has been conducted again quite recently with more advanced techniques by professor J.-D. Haynes, leading to the conclusion that the idea of a conscious “veto right” is an abundant entity that could be easily ignored without losing explanatory power2.

II. The weak problem of the paradigm of Libet-style experiments: the enigma of causal explanation

Both Libet and Haynes (hereafter abbreviated to ‘LH’) work within the explanatory framework of, what we may call, linear causality. In short, linear causality presupposes nothing else but the existence of a linear time continuum in which a certain cause A generates or ‘causes’ an event B. In such a case, the causal relation is ‘linear’, since for each causal process A B, A is considered to be a sufficient reason leading inevitably to B, and in which B always is a ‘passive outcome’ of a certain cause A. Consider for example a wet street (B) after a rainy day (A): the rain is sufficient (though, evidently, not necessary) reason for the street to be wet, and the wetness of the street is an inevitable (‘deterministic’) outcome of the rainfall.

Now, according to LH, the same could count for free will: a certain motoric input (“neural states”) leads inevitably to a certain mental state B (‘pushing the button or not’). Now, here already lies the first problem, which is even the ‘weakest’ one of the whole LH-setting. As far as linear causality is concerned, the word ‘inevitable’ – as I used it – is not wholly unambiguous. For the concept of “necessary outcome” is of course an empirical statement, but if there is one thing that the history of the philosophy of science reveals is, then it is exactly the fact that there does not exist an apodictic category of ‘necessary outcome’ in the empirical method. Hence, we rather ought to speak of ‘gradations of plausibility’, cf. the paradigm of verificationism. In the case of the rain causing wet streets, we have indeed very strong evidence that - seen the wet nature of rain drops and the general tendency of concrete and cobble-stones (materials by which most streets are paved) to be impermeable – that rain 2 See John-Dylan Haynes et all., Unconscious Determinants of Free Decisions in the Human Brain, Nature Neuroscience 11 (2008), p. 543 – 545 . For a short press release by the Max PlanckInstitute where the experiment was conducted, see http://www.mpg.de/english/illustrationsDocumentation/documentation/pressReleases/2008/pressRelease20080414/index.html

Page 4: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

wet streets. We observe a certain amount of times – X1, X2, X3, X4,… - that rain, indeed, does deliver wet streets as a result. But apodictically sure – as in the case of the sum that two and two always equals four – we can never be, of course: there is still the hypothetical possibility that once in a time streets will be dry after a rain shower, e.g. due to improved drainage systems.

But whereas in the case of streets becoming wet, we indeed do have a large amount of ‘certainty’ (or, as we may say, ‘confirmation’) that this will be (say, in 99.9% of the cases rain wet streets), what about the hypothesis – as held by LH – that a certain brain state will lead to this or that behavioural outcome? Well, even in Haynes’s “practically improved” experiment, Dr Determinist has to confess that in only 60% of the cases, he was able to correctly predict whether the images on this or that fMRI-scan would lead to an action with the right or left finger. And then the question may arise: is a 60%-level of prediction really that much significant? It is of course up to the scientific world to decide whether or not a certain hypothesis has been tested enough in order to gain credibility – after all, this is not a formal criterion on which the philosopher can deliver a useful contribution – but I’d certainly doubt the theoretical unambiguity of, say, Newtonian physics if in only 60% of the cases, a heavy object will fall back to the ground when it is thrown up, whereas in 40% of the cases, the object may as well fly up in the air…

This shows again the important distinction that should be made between sufficient and necessary condition in order for each process occurring in time (in section III I’ll further elaborate on the topic of non-causal processes), including causal events. Take again the example of wet streets into consideration: we stated that when it is raining, then the streets will (again, almost) inevitably become wet. But then suppose that we walk through the street on a sunny summer day, and notice that the streets are actually wet. One would not be really persuaded that this is due to heavy rainfall. And indeed, after investigating into the causes of the street’s wetness, we conclude that its cause was, in fact, an industrious housewife emptying a bucket of filthy water on the street after cleaning her house. As a result, there is not one single ‘necessary’ condition that can lead to the street’s wetness: there are different potential causes that may render it that way.

Tracing back deliberate human action to an alleged inevitable neural cause, would hence blur the important distinction between necessary and sufficient condition. There may be other causes as well, for example, deliberate action itself. Of course, a counterfactual argument to mine might well be that neural stimulation is indeed a sufficient reason for conscious will to “emerge”, but then of course one would not leave the framework of linear causality, which I’ll try to refute in section III.

Now, let us turn to some other ‘weak’ problems of causal explanation. Let us sum up some necessary (i.e. metaphysical) conditions for causality:

1) Temporal precedence: a certain event or cause A must always precede in time and space in order for an event B to happen. Moreover, the spatiotemporal connection between A and B should be obvious enough in order to make A a plausible cause for B. E.g.: the famous example of a butterfly flapping with its wings in the woods somewhere in, say, the Flemish Pajottenland, and causing a storm on the Pacific Ocean. In this case, both the distance in time and space are far too huge to consider the butterfly’s flapping even as a possible (sufficient or necessary) cause for the storm.

Page 5: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

2) Constant connection: cf. the remarks made in condition (1): the connection between A and B should be constant enough, inasmuch that one observes A, then B will happen as well. This condition is also linked to condition (3)

3) Predictability: causality should be sharply distinguished from the idea of correlation. Whereas there may be a correlation between the chilly temperature outside, and the man walking down the street wearing a woollen coat but no necessary causal connection; this connection is (quite) necessary between a cigarette butt smouldering and the house catching fire. This implies, by the very nature of causality as a modal relationship, that causal relationships are not events qualified by pure randomness. Instead, all physical causal relationships are events that could be (hypothetically) repeated. For example, by inductive reasoning we obtain the general law that when we drop a stone, then it will fall (X1, X2, X3,… general law). But on the other hand, we could also apply a so-called deductive-nomological model and state that, taken into account the general law and this particular stone I’m currently holding in a firm grip, that it will fall. Hence, we can predict, with a high amount of probability, that the stone will fall.

Now, does LH’s physicalist thesis meet these criteria? This seems to be far from obvious. Concerning the criterion of so-called ‘temporal precedence’, we have to acknowledge that there seems at first sight, indeed, reasons to accept that this is indeed the case: the readiness potential occurs at a certain time t1, and is followed by a ‘conscious state’ at a time t2 .

But what about the conditions of constant connection and predictability? As already pointed out above, John-Dylan Haynes himself had to confess that he could only reach a degree of predictability of 60%. But what does this rather low degree of predictability imply? Of course, one could argue and say that this is due to some technical defaults of the measurement devices, and once these technical problems are solved, then one could obtain a (theoretical) probability degree of, say, 99.9%; and reach the same explanatory heights as Newtonian physics.

Again, this argument does not seem very convincing. Scientists as Galileo and Newton in their time were able to obtain much higher degrees of ‘probability’ in order to verify their physical theories, although the scientific methods, skills and devices were – for quite obvious reasons – much less advanced in the 17th century than nowadays. And in fact, both for Newton as for Haynes, exactly the same thing is investigated: the causal relationship between a certain physical event A, leading to a mental event B. And of course, Haynes and others cannot refer to an abundant “entity” such as “consciousness” or “free will”, which would require the objective peering into another’s mind. Not only is this both a theoretical and practical impossibility, but once we would even accept the “existence” of something like conscious free will, we would abandon the paradigm of linear causality altogether. This is of course something Haynes would not even consider doing so, but we will.

III. The strong problem of the paradigm of Libet-style experiments: meaning correlates, the error of causal explanation and the reduction of freely deliberated processes to bivalent options.

Page 6: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

So far, we only discussed the LH-paradigm from within a linear-causal approach. But what we did in the previous section, was only a kind of skinning the fur of the dead sheep: going through the flesh op to its very bones, is a more demanding job than that, and is the task that will be set forth in this section.

To resume the whole point, to which this entire essay can be reduced, in one single aphorism, we may simply state that the entire project to naturalize consciousness (and free will) to its physical substratum, is a huge category mistake. As we’ll conclude this essay, one therefore does not need to adopt a dualist (sometimes dubbed a ‘schizophrenic’) framework in order to explain free will: both substance and property dualism make the same mistake to ‘explain’ one (be it the physical or mental) realm of consciousness by referring to the former. But we will discuss this later on.

What is needed, is a phenomenological approach to the problem of free will, and it is (again…) Edmund Husserl who therefore provides us with the solid rock on which our Church shall be built. A central recurrent theme in Husserlian phenomenology is that of so-called “material” or “regional” ontology3. A material ontology should be distinguished from a formal ontology: the latter could be best described as a formal theory of being and its categories, or ‘general metaphysics’ as it is understood since Aristotle. A material ontology, on the other hand, is a highest region (therefore it could also be named ‘ontological region’) of generality in which the objects of a particular science are investigated. In Ideas I and II , Husserl distinguishes between three material ontologies, namely Nature, Consciousness and Culture. For example: a certain psychic event, such as joy or sadness, can for very obvious reasons not be found into the physical world, but it ‘exists’ inasmuch that it belongs to another ontological region, i.e. consciousness. Or take a less trivial example: not only do we perceive things, objects around us, in their different shades of colour, but we also maintain (at least when one adheres to a realist account of it) that there exists (not in a Platonic heaven of course) a certain ontology of the manifold of colours we can perceive in the world, and attribute to it a general term: blue-ness, red-ness, yellow-ness, and so forth, than can even be syntactically subdivided. E.g., the realm of “blueness” can be subdivided in other ontological categories of indigo-ness, marine blue-ness, deep blue-ness, having the blue-ness, etc. (I suppose you get the picture where I’m pointing to) Hence, when we perceive a certain (yellow) object, we say that the universal of ‘yellowness’ is instantiated in the object itself. For present purposes I won’t go into deeper detail on the nature of universals, but want even the nominalist reader to be convinced of something rather peculiar: in our daily language we continuously speak about those attributes – colour, brightness, shape, etc. – but in what way do they “exist” ? Since according to the physicalist paradigm, qualities such as colours cannot exist, because they are nothing but manifestations of the physical world: in the physical world, there exists no such a thing as a colour ‘yellow’, but only a certain set of light waves that can be objectively measured. So for the Husserlian, the material ontology of, say, colours would only hold when applied to a regional ontology of ‘Consciousness’, since it is only in the world of consciousness-having creatures that things such as colours may ‘exist’.

It is of the utmost importance to stress that Husserl’s distinction between the threefold regions may not seduce one to commit a certain kind of reductionism: it is not the case that there is one region that would be ontologically supervenient on the other. They are three distinct, irreducible realms. Of course, the distinction that Husserl has set forth so far does not come out of thin air, but was introduced for very clear epistemological reasons that are inherent to

3 For a very clear discussion of Husserl’s account of the regional ontologies, see David Woodruff Smith, Husserl, London: Routledge, 2007, p. 142 – 148

Page 7: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

the phenomenological method, and are presented in his later works such as the Crisis of the European Sciences and The Origin of Geometry , both published in the late 1930’s. Herein, Husserl unfolds his idea of the ‘life-world’ (Lebenswelt), an epistemological idea that has been unfortunately hijacked by a bunch of – mostly French – murky continental “philosophers”, and is nowadays usually related to ‘existentialist phenomenology’ (a contradiction in terms). In its original (Husserlian) meaning, however, the idea of ‘life-world’ means the following: consider again the physicalist approach to the existence of colours. As noted, the physicalist denies the existence of colours as we perceive them to be (red, blue, yellow, etc.), and in the physicalist’s world, there only exists things such as light waves etc. But this vision cannot be consistently maintained from a pure epistemological point of view! How can the physicalist reasonably argue that this bundle of light waves produces the colour ‘red’, without falling back to his own intentional (!) awareness of that very colour? He simply cannot do that. Either he has to say: this bundle of waves A = colour B; but then he would already have to admit that he (and only he? But who would take that for granted?) has “access” to the information that that particular bundle means ‘red’. Epistemologically even more ridiculous would be of course the claim that the colour ‘red’, even as an emergent property, does not exist at all. As a result, even for the natural sciences an investigation into the nature of the [inter(subjective)] life-world should be an epistemic starting point, for the methodological reasons just explained above. Obviously, this does not imply that Husserl – or the author of this text – would be committed to a kind of ontological idealism, in which nature would be reducible to some conscious apprehension of it. This would namely again get us involved into the paradigm of dualism, and lead us to the (seemingly) inevitable chicken-or-egg-problem. Moreover, if one would neglect the primordiality of phenomenological (inter)subjectivity, the frightening gaze of dangerous psychologism is again looming just around the corner: we would have to justify the existence or ‘emergence’ of ideal entities (one must not only think of subjective qualities such as colours, but also of more epistemic notions such as geometrical figures or the laws of logic) by reducing them to their physical substratum, but this would inevitably lead, as pointed out above, to an epistemological contradiction: one simply cannot reduce conscious experience to its psychophysical underlying network, without first qualitatively designating what those conscious experiences actually are or are about (intentionality).

The Husserlian account of regional ontologies could be, for present purposes, best be read together with his conception of philosophy of language and the idea of ‘ideal content’: according to Husserl, a sharp fourfold distinction must be made between a) the linguistic sign, b) the intentional act, c) the meaning of the act and d) the outside world. This could be made clear with an easy example: when I perceive a tree, I’m immediately aware of it being present over there in the field. However, I can turn away from the tree, but still think of it by using my memory skills, and as such, the tree in the field can burn down meanwhile, but my intentional content cannot burn down. On the other hand, when I say or refer to ‘that tree’, I’m implicitly acknowledging that the tree itself is an instantiation of a universal of ‘tree-ness’. Hence, the meaning of the tree should not be confused with its linguistic sign (the word ‘tree’), which can also be expressed in other words, such as ‘Baum’, ‘boom’, ‘träd’, etc.

So where do these Husserlian ideas about regional ontologies and ideal meanings lead us to? This may not seem to be very obvious in an attempt to save the idea of free, deliberate will; but the connection with it is more evident than it may seem at first sight. For the LH-thesis maintains that there is a causal relationship between physical event A and mental action B. Let us, for a very last time, this idea of causality be taken for granted, and considered to be true. What, then, does the physical ‘correlate’ of consciousness, which causes certain mental

Page 8: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

events, actually mean? In the case of light waves “causing” colours this is still obvious: there is a meaning correlate between the conscious-intentional state of colour awareness on the one hand, and its physical substratum on the other. But this seems very unlikely to be the case. Unless…

… Unless one of course keeps on sticking with the whole setting of LH’s quite treacherous experiments!! And this setting is quite reductionist. It is as if it is taken for granted that each deliberately chosen action is nothing but making a choice between just two possible options. In LH’s framework, the options are very simple: lifting a finger, or not lifting a finger; pressing a button, or not pressing a button; lifting my right finger, or lifting my left finger, etc. Now we may say – and for explanatory reasons I’ll even not take the quite suspicious “60%-predictability” as discussed in section II of this paper into consideration! – that there are actually “meaning correlates” between a certain kind of neural activity, and the action that will happen. If Mr Haynes observes either a blue or yellow colour on his computer screen, which is plugged on the experimental person, then he may either say that he will lift up his right or left finger a few seconds later.

But this reduces the whole realm of human action to a kind of sequel of so-called bivalent acts! The principle of bivalence is most widely known as a logical principle: a statement about a certain state of affairs must be either true or false. Moreover, there is no ‘third option’ given (‘tertium non datur’): either A must be true, and then B is false, or vice versa. But it can never be the case that both A and B are true, or that both A and B are false. So take as a very simple example: “Edmund Husserl taught philosophy courses at the University of Freiburg”, then we can check whether he did or not. It seems that he did, which means that our proposition is in accordance (or “correspondence”) with reality, so we may say that this proposition is true. But suppose that we do not know anything about Husserl’s life, but we know at least that he was not appointed professor at the University of Munich. Then the proposition “Edmund Husserl taught philosophy courses at the University of Munich” would be rendered false. But although we are now strictly obeying the laws of logic, we still do not know where he did teach philosophy courses, since there were quite a lot of philosophy faculties in Germany in the early 20th century (he could have been teaching in Berlin, Jena, Marburg, Köln, Heidelberg, Göttingen (which he did), etc. ) .

This example implies that human action is always more than choosing from a range of bivalent options (“doing A, or not doing A; either doing A, or doing B”) . While it is logically and descriptively true that I am currently, say, not doing my dishes; then this logically true proposition does not tell us anything about what I am actually doing.

In fact, in daily human action, the principle of bivalence – in this case defined as: choosing from a range of only two certain given options, no more nor less – is rather an exception in doing things. In short, Libet and Haynes opted for investigating one of the most primitive kinds of “human behaviour”, as if they were merely investigating the reactions of bacteria to a certain set of stimuli. In real life, man’s way of choosing goes ways beyond this primitive paradigm of “lifting my finger or not”. In fact, even when we may suppose that Haynes would ever succeed in falsifying the notion of free will by actually 'proving' that the act of lifting up one's finger is determined by certain neural events – which, seen the objections made in section II seems not much plausible – even then its only a very partial refutation of the idea of this concept.

Page 9: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

Maybe this could be best illustrated by using an idea delivered by medieval scholastic moral philosophy (oh yes, the “dark ages”...). Authors such as St Thomas Aquinas insisted to make a distinction between the finis operis and finis operantis of a certain moral act. In short, the latter is the ultimate moral goal of a certain acting subject, whereas the former concept evaluates the moral goodness of the act itself. Hence, the finis operis is act-relative, whereas the finis operantis is agent-relative. Take as a quite heroic example Robin Hood stealing from the rich, and giving it to the poor and exploited. In this case, his ultimate goal ('finis operantis') could be described as 'obtaining social justice', whereas the means to reach this ('finis operis') is stealing. But since this is not an essay on ethics or political philosophy, the reader may make up his own mind about the good- and rightfulness of Robin Hood's both fines.

But what could the philosophy of mind learn from this distinction? Well, we may argue that each deliberate human action always involves this type of distinction. Take, as an example, writing a dissertation: “writing a dissertation” is, in this case, the 'finis operantis' of the whole action. But there are several 'fines operis' involved in here: going to the library and borrowing some books, searching for relevant articles and papers on the subject matter, starting the computer, opening a new document, etc. These are all separated actions that must be framed into the ultimate goal of the finis operantis.

Genuine deliberate (free) action always involve the use of the setting of a finis operantis, or ultimate goal. The reason why this distinction can shed a new light on Haynes's naïve rejection of free will is simply because we even do not need neuroscience to prove that Haynes's experiments with lifting fingers are quite irrelevant. Daily experience can show this. Suppose that you're cutting a piece of paper with a pair of scissors, which for very obvious reasons involves the use of your fingers (and again: getting the paper cut through is the 'finis operantis' in this example). Does one really intentionally think at each step during this process, in a continuous line, that now I have to lift up my thumb, and now I have to pull down my middle finger – and so on, and so forth – in order to get the job done? Of course not! One cuts immediately through the piece of paper without intentionally thinking at each step about the physical bodily processes that are involved with it. Intentionality, in this example, is immediately focused upon “cutting the paper”; not on the different bodily movements of the fingers. So yes, Haynes and his determinst fellows are in fact trying to predict the weather for the next coming two weeks by looking at an old-fashioned thermometer in grandma's garden...

So far we have stressed the importance of the “finis operantis” in deliberate human action. But suppose, clever genius as he is, that grandma's old thermometer did its job quite well, and Haynes would be an almighty Laplacian demon who can predict each different kind of human 'teleological' behaviour (which may be the case, since a famous French proverb says that it is in the old saucepans that one can cook the best4 ). Even then, Haynes would be doing nothing else but performing a nice magic trick. For not only the amount of 'fines operis' is, theoretically, infinite; but settling final goals is an infinite potentiality as well! But this requires of course the final abandonment, not only of human action as a set of 'bivalent options', but of its very predictability as well. Predictability, in fact, always requires the theoretical assumption that there is a finite amount of possibilities or potentialities that could be actualized. Consider a dice with an infinite amount of sides, which would take the form of a geometrical ball. Although the amount of sides - “fines operis” - is infinite, one could still make a mathematical formula calculating on which exact side the dice would fall. But even

4 C'est dans les vieilles casseroles qu'on fait les meilleurs plats.

Page 10: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

this is not an adequate metaphor in order to illustrate the nature of human action, since throwing the ball-formed dice would be still subject to the physical laws of gravity, speed, and so on and so forth (hence the theoretical assumption that its outcome could still be calculated.

In order to get rid of this view, we have to further improve our view on human action. Consider again our remarks on bivalence: It is possible that I am not at a certain place, say, New York, on this very moment. But if I am not in New York, where, then, am I? Maybe in Los Angeles? Maybe in London? Maybe in Madrid? Or a trip to Australia would also be nice (or Nice, in Southern France, yes indeed!), seen the cold weather these days in Belgium. So far, the amount of possible places where I could actually be, is infinite. But this still involves the metaphor of the 'round dice', since one could indeed actually investigate on the place where I am actually located. And suppose Mr Haynes finally snatched me in, say, Paris. But then new questions arise: for what purpose am I visiting France's capital city? What kind of attractions will I visit there? The Louvre Museum? The Eiffel Tower? The Moulin Rouge? King Louis XIV's palace in Versailles? And then: wherefore? Why? What will I do next? And so on, and so forth.

Once we abandon both the framework of bivalence and predictability, we could conceive human deliberative action as an infinite process: not only the amount of potential actions that could be done is infinite, its motivations are infinite as well!

So let us turn now to the problem of 'neural activity'. So far, we discussed the following topics that are quite devastating for Haynes's theoretical setting:

1) the problem of 'meaning correlates', drawn from Husserl's account of regional ontologies, between a certain neural activity or so-called 'readiness potential' on the one hand, and a conscious outcome on the other hand.

2) The problem with Haynes's option to take only bivalent actions into consideration3) Seen (2) that human action could not be conceived of as a mere choice between only

two options A and ~A or A and B, but should be instead be conceived of as an infinite process in which an infinite amount of potentialities could be actualized, both on the level of (“subconscious”) acts ('finis operis') and intentionally conscious acts (ultimate goals; 'finis operantis')

Let us counter the quite simple scheme that is often used in the LH-paradigm (see section I of this paper), with a new one that represents human deliberate action in a more accurate way:

Page 11: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

This scheme definitely needs come clarification. First of all, seen our remarks on human action as an infinite process, we conceive of the LH-thesis as a grave epistemological mistake, since they take it for granted that they can lift out one single piece of a whole process of human action, and put it in a linear one-dimensional schema. This is, given our remarks, bluntly wrong, and in most all cases of deliberate human action, they even are not investigating genuine free action (consider again the example of cutting a paper with a pair of scissors: intentional aboutness simply does not occur on the level of lifting the fingers up and down, but on the level of interaction with the paper!). In his magnificent essay The Phenomenon of Freedom5, the Flemish philosopher and scientist Jos Verhulst points out to the, widely misunderstood, ancient paradox of Zeno of Elea. In most contemporary philosophy handbooks, the paradox is illustrated by using the story of a race between the athletic Achilles and a slow turtle. The turtle may, seen his slowness, start first and runs (well yes...) a certain distance d1. A few moments later – say, a minute – it is up to Achilles to start his marathon. But according to Zeno, Achilles first has to catch up with the turtle by running through d1, and when he finally arrives at the end of the distance d1, the turtle already proceeded by making a new (smaller) distance d2, which Achilles again has to catch up, and so on and so forth, up to the infinite. Conclusion, according to Zeno: Achilles can and will never move past the slow turtle!

One may indeed laugh and ridicule the imagination of the ancient presocratic philosophers, but of course, it was not Zeno's attempt to prove the impossibility of actual physical motion. Its grain of truth lies on a more epistemological level: we conceive of motion as being a linear

5 Jos Verhulst, Het Verschijnsel Vrijheid, 56 p., publication forthcoming

Page 12: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

process in which an object moves from a certain point A to another point Z, and in which the objects passes through different observable points B, C, D, E, F, G, etc. But observation requires that there are a finite amount of 'points' that can be actually 'seen', and this is not the case at all: when one would observe the object at a certain point, say, K, it is already on another point L, for the very reason that it is in motion: if the object could be actually observed, than it would be (temporally) be stationary, which would of course contradict the very nature of its being in motion. Hence derives the theoretical impossibility to 'observe' the different points through which the object is moving, for it would imply a contradiction!

The reason why Zeno's paradox (and Verhulst's account of it) are of such a tremendous importance, is because Haynes does conceive of human action (“the object going from A to Z”) as being something that could be dissected and analysed in its different constituent parts! And this would equally lead to the same contradiction as sketched above, since being involved into such a process of human activity, requires the constant sequence of different actions.

This is the reason why the scheme, as illustrated above, reveals a dynamic conception of free will. Whereas it is simply naïve and deceitful to consider the free will to be something that could be investigated as a (bivalent) action, our conception as scheduled above takes the thesis of human action as a sequence of different sorts of acts, or “the process”, into account.

One may be of course be misleadingly seduced to conceive of the green arrow going from RP1 to CO1 as a kind of “diagonal draw” of the original linear LH-scheme, moreover since I purposefully put CO1 on a point later in time (= the horizontal blue arrows on which both “physical” and “conscious” activities occur). But the green arrow going from RP1 to CO1 may not be conceived of as a relation indicating causality! This is, indeed, just because human action is a process; so CO1 is immediately followed by CO2 (read as: “second conscious state”), and then CO3 (third conscious state), CO4, and so on and so forth. And the same also holds for the infinite amount of “physical” readiness potentials (RP's): taken for granted that each conscious event is preceded by a “readiness potential”, and seen the fact that deliberate human action is a process, this amount is indeed infinite. But the (i.e. my) scheme – which is, how ingenious it may look like – of course just a scheme, and in any case a reduction of conscious activity, and hence quite deceptive: the reason why one may not conceive of RP1 → CO1 , or RP2 → CO2, and so on, is because of the already illustrated problem of meaning correlates: there is in fact not a single reason why we should attribute a 'meaning correlate' to RP1, RP2, or RP(n) . It might be well the case that the “real” meaning correlate must be found between, say, RP1 and CO3. Or between RP2 and CO1. And so on, and so forth. And even then, seen our discussion of the theoretical impossibility to dissolve human action into isolated acts (as Haynes did), it is simply obsolete and impossible even to try to attribute such a meaning correlate between the different RP's and their conscious pendants. Rather, it would be more accurate to speak of a (“meaningless”) stream of physical events on the one hand, and a meaningful stream of consciousness on the other. As such, each attempt to try to reduce a certain conscious event or the idea of free will to its physical substratum, is nothing else but a huge category mistake.

These meaning correlates are nevertheless a necessary condition in order to grasp the structure of the physical and natural world. In our discussion on Husserl’s outline of the life-world we already noted that without this very concept, even natural science would be rendered obsolete, since it is, at least, an epistemological fallacy to think that we could ever gain any knowledge about this world: the natural scientist at least has to take his life-world as a tacitly

Page 13: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

acknowledged background into account. And even the physical world itself seems to be full of intelligible meanings: not that we have any commitment to make any mystification about this statement (as if the physical world could be studied as the expression of the Will of a certain Divine Entity), but instead, we should conceive of the world as it is investigated, as being more than an indefinable whole of kaleidoscopic chaos. For example: when one sees the leaves of the trees turning into different shades of dark colours, then this means that it will be, or that it already is, Autumn (not that the brown leaves cause the Autumn, of course). Or if a smoke plume is observed, then this means that is has been caused by a fire. As it is very unlikely that brown leaves will show up in the middle of April, or that the object on the roof will fly up in the air, or that the smoke came out of thin air. The category of “meaningfulness” is thus of a huge importance of the world for us to be appearing (as has been most notoriously stressed by Immanuel Kant, with whose impositionist stance toward the a priori of causality and necessity we are, however, not likely to concur), and we simply could not do without. But once this meaning correlate between certain physical events cannot be found anymore, as is the case for the physicalist trying to determine which particular physical neural event will cause this or that particular conscious outcome, one should question the whole paradigm of physical causality altogether.

Hence, since the meaning correlate is absent in our alleged ‘causal explanation’ of consciousness, then the reader should not be misled to read the time interval between a conscious event and a readiness potential – noted as Δ(COn – RPn) in our scheme – as a causal relation (cfr the condition of “temporal precedence”) between them but as events that may occur at different points in time, but cannot be investigated due to this problem of meaning correlates.

IV. A short note on the compatibalist versus incompatibilist debate, or why I am not a libertarian.

For those who are acquainted with my writings and thoughts on political philosophy, there really is no need to worry that I would have changed my opinion on these issues. The culprit in this brief section are the so-called libertarians in the compatibalist/incompatibilist discussion on free will. In short, incompatibilists maintain that the idea of free will and physical determinism are not compatible, hence crediting an ontological priority to either the mental, as libertarians do, or the physical, as determinists do. On the other hand are the compatibalists, who maintain that both categories do not exclude one another.

In fact, it is again the whole paradigm that leads to those kind of debates that is spurious from its very starting premises. Its main default? Dualism. For what both libertarians and determinists share in these issues, is the dualist view that there exist two different, ontologically distinct, realms. Hence libertarian philosophers of mind, such as Roderick Chisholm, introduced – with reminiscence of Aristotle – the notion of a “prime mover unmoved” as a first ontological category that puts the whole “machine” or chain of mental/deliberate events in motion. But the determinst will of course reject that view due to reasons of parsimony. As such, the whole debate tends to be stuck in an eternal rhetorical game of cat and mouse, one side of the debate accusing the other that they introduce an ontological category too much or too less to explain the existence of free will.

Working within the Husserlian-phenomenological framework we put forward in our considerations, these struggles could be easily avoided. For the classification of different

Page 14: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

'regional ontologies' does not imply this dualist view: taking intentional experience as a starting point, does neither imply that it could be merely reduced to its physical substratum, nor that the natural world would be a mere (ontological) correlate of the mental. They are in fact all manifestations of one and the same world we observe and live in, although the description of each ontological region requires its own method of investigation. Or as J.R. Searle put it:

“I do not think we are forced to either dualism or materialism. The point to remember is that consciousness is a biological phenomenon like any other. It is true that it has special features, most notably the feature of subjectivity, as we have seen, but that does not prevent consciousness from being a higher-level feature of the brain in the same way that digestion is a higher-level feature of the stomach, or liquidity a higher-level feature of the system of molecules that constitute our blood. In short, the way to reply to materialism is to point out that it ignores the real existence of consciousness. The way to defeat dualism is simply to refuse to accept the system of categories that makes consciousness out as something nonbiological, not a part of the natural world6”

Indeed, once we get rid of the blurred distinction between 'the mental' and 'the physical' – and the cartesian riddle about how to cope with its interaction – that has been inherited from the dualist framework pervading contemporary epistemology, metaphysics and philosophy of mind; the method of a descriptive psychology or phenomenology is handed us as a powerful tool to rigorously investigate on the issues of intentional consciousness and deliberate human free will.

Acknowledgement: For many of the insights delivered in this essay, I am tremendously indebted to Michaël Bauwens and Tuur Demeester, two friends of mine working dedicatedly within the same framework of metaphysical freedom and moreover: philosophical clarity and truth. It was Michaël who draw my attention to the idea of freely chosen human action as an infinite and unpredictable process; whereas Tuur provided me with the scholastic light I mentioned as well. Without their insightful comments, for which I want both to thank gratefully, this paper would never have seen the (digital) daylight.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Haynes, John-Dylan et all., Unconscious Determinants of Free Decisions in the Human Brain, Nature Neuroscience 11 (2008), p. 543 – 545

Searle, John R., Mind, Language and Society, New York: Basic Books, 1999, 175 p.

Smith, David Woodruff; Husserl, London: Routledge, 2007, 467 p.

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, “Phenomenological Approaches to Self-Consciousness”, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/self-consciousness-phenomenological/

6 See John R. Searle, Mind, Language and Society, New York: Basic Books, 1999, p. 51 – 52

Page 15: A Critique on the Falsification of Free

Verhulst, Jos; Het Verschijnsel Vrijheid, 56 p., draft essay