2012 - non-fideistic interpret 1

Upload: ria-metaxa

Post on 01-Jun-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    1/21

    A NON-FIDEISTICINTERPRETATION

    OF IIILTIL IN PLUTARCH'SWRITINGS:

    THE HARMONYBETWEENIIILTIL AND KNOWLEDGE

    In this paper I would like to challenge the straightforward applicability

    of modern categories such as "belief' in the study of ancient philosophers

    such as Plutarch, and early Christians such as Paul. It seems possible that

    the modern concept of "belief', the English rendition of1tlo-rlt;, is heavily

    indebted to a particular Christianizing interpretation, that of Luther, who

    took 1tlO"'t'lt; for the central notion in Christianity. His emphasis on faith

    was then subsequently reinforced in Kantian philosophy, in which belief,

    as the characteristic of religion, became opposed to knowledge, as the hall-

    mark of philosophy.1 Contemporary philosophers also see "belief' as anti-

    philosophical. The modern philosopher Alain Badiou, for instance, empha-

    sizes the anti-philosophical nature of Paul's concept of1tlo-rlt; in terms of

    proclamation and declaration. According to Badiou, Paul's "discourse is one

    of pure fidelity to the possibility opened by the event. It cannot, therefore,

    in any way (and this is the upshot of Paul's anti-philosophy) fall under the

    remit ofknowledge".2 Yet, in some New Testament scholarship it has been

    suggested that 1tlO"'t'It;also has an argumentative quality. This gives rise to the

    question of whether Paul's terminology can be contextualized in the phi-

    losophy of his time. Is the concept of1tlo-rlt; unique to Paul? Is it specifically

    Christian? Do ancient philosophers contemporary with Paul use the term,

    and if so, in what sense?

    I Cf.the vies of Novalis and Von Baader, on whom seeU.Dierse, uGlauben und Wissen n",in]. Ritter (ed.), Historisches Worterbuch der Philosoph ie,3 (Basel 1974)648-649: 'Wie Novalis

    fiihrt F. von Baader den Zwiespalt von Glauben und Wissen auf einen von der Reformation

    verursachten ''Verfall" zurUck, der nur behoben werden kann, wenn zwischen Glauben und

    Wissen wieder ein unormales und eintriichtiges Verhalten" hergestellt wird".

    2 A. Badiou, Saint PauL Lafondation de l' universalisme (Paris 1997);idem, Saint Paul: The

    Foundation of Universalism (trans!. by Ray Brassier; Stanford 2003) 45.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    2/21

    This paper calls attention to the uneven approach to the interpreta-

    tion of the terminology of1t[(rt"l~ and 1tl

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    3/21

    A different meaning, however, is found when rrlCT't'li) occurs in lists of

    virtues, acquires the meaning of trust in a relational sense, or is even re-

    garded as an act of "persuasion" in a rhetorical strategy. Most remarkable,

    however, is the way in which Plutarch can also speak of "believing" in philo-

    sophical statements (ConsoL ad ux. 611D)or "believing" that philosophers

    such cfs Socrates were true philosophers-a belief which is founded upon

    their alts, words and lives(DeALex.fort. 328B).Plutarch even talks of "belief'

    in figures such as Homer and Pythagoras. Most relevant are those passages

    in which Plutarch frequently emphasizes that "our belief (rrlCT't'li) in all our

    notions, except those derived from the senses, comes from three sources:

    myth, law, and rational explanation; so it is undoubtedly the poets, the legiS-

    lators, and thirdly the philosophers who have been our guides and teachers

    in what we think about the gods" (Amat. 763C). It is important to note that,

    according to ancient philosophers such as Plutarch, belief is not by defini-

    tion anti-philosophical, but only so if it remains on a mythological level.

    According to Plutarch, faith needs to be rescued from the merely mytholog-

    icallevel and strengthened with philosophical reflection (De aduLat. 3SF).

    It is apparent that according to Paul's pagan contemporaries faith is not in

    itself anti-philosophical; there are two kinds of belief, an "unskillful faith"

    (literally an chE)(Voi) rrlCT't'li)and a "strengthened faith".5

    First, then, I shall discuss those passages in Plutarch in which rrlCT't'li)seems

    to acquire the meaning familiar to modem ears, of faith in a fideistic sense,

    in other words, of an unfounded religious faith as opposed to knowledge.

    In Plutarch's treatise on brotherly love, for instance, he argues, among

    other things, how we should conduct ourselves towards a brother while our

    parents are alive or dead:

    After the father is dead, however, even more than before it is right for the

    brother to cling fast to his brother's goodwill ... believing all the mythological

    tales about the brotherly love of the Dioscuri (...xalmO"tEuovra TOle;T' ctt.AOle;ex folueOAoyoucTl1tEpl TWV~lo(jJ(6pwv tile; eplAa5EAep[ae;)and in particular the one

    which relates that Polydeuces killed with a blow of his fist a man who whis-

    pered to him something against his brother.6

    5 Plu., Qu. cony. 72SC.

    6 Plu., De frat. arnOT.483C.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    4/21

    In this passage it seems clear that what one does with regard to mytho-

    logical tales is "to believe them".

    The same impression is given in another passage in Plutarch's essay On

    Isis and Osiris, which talks about the hoi poLLoi("ordinary people"), whom

    he describes as tiresome, and who delight in associating aspects of the gods

    with particular phenomena in reality, either "1th the seasonal changes in

    the surrounding atmosphere, or with the gro~ of the crops and seedtimes

    and ploughing".7 Examples given by Plutarch are the burial of Osiris, which

    is associated with the sowing of the grain and his coming to life when plants

    begin to sprout, and the premature birth of Harpocrates by Isis at the time

    of the first fruits.8 According to Plutarch:

    When the people hear these things, they are satisfied with them and believe

    them ('t"c&rcx yap ,h:ouovrl::~ &YCX1tWCTLJc:cxlmcrrl::uouo'lV), deducing the plausible

    explanation directly from what is obvious and familiar.9

    Clearly, then, it are hoi poLLoi who believe in things regarding the gods and

    associate them with visible reality, which is explained with reference to the

    world of the gods.

    Again, another text on superstition seems to communicate that belief is

    equivalent to superstition and opposed to atheism. Whereas belief is the

    domain of the superstitious person, atheism is the domain of supposing,

    thinking and opinion. As Plutarch writes:

    The atheist thinks there are no gods; the superstitious man wishes there were

    none, but believes in them against his will; for he is afraid not to believe.

    (OuJc: O'(l::'t"CXlel::OU~l::lVCXl6 ael::O~, 6 at al::lO"laCX[J.lWVou ~OUM't"CXl,mcrrdl::l a' aJc:wv:

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    5/21

    of those who demand demonstration and proof regarding issues which

    pertain to the gods. When one of the interlocutors in Plutarch's dialogue

    On Love, a certain Pemptides, questions whether Love is indeed a god

    and challenges Plutarch to hear from him "what criterion those who first

    declared Eros to be a god had in mind when they made the statement",11

    Plutart unleashes the following attack, as his son Autobulus relates in the

    dialoga~:

    "Pemptides", he said, "it is, I believe, a grave and dangerous matter that you

    are broaching; or rather, you are altogether violating our inviolable opinion

    regarding the godsl2 when you demand an account and proof of each of them

    (flcXAAOV 5' OAWC; 'ta chdvl')'tcx KIVEIV 't"fjc; TrEpl eEWV M~l')C; ~v E)(OflEV, TrEpl EKcXCTrOl>

    A6yol> aTrCXI'twv Kcxl aTr65EI~IV). Our ancient traditional faith is good enough

    (apKEI yap ~ TrcX'tpIOC;KcxlTrCXAcxla TrlCTrIC;).It is impossible to assert or discover

    evidence more palpable than this faith, 'Whatever subtle twist's invented by

    keen wit' (E.,Ba.203). This faith is a basis, as it were, a common foundation,of reverence towards the godsl3 (aAA' E5pcx 'tIC; cxu't"l'j Kcxl ~cXCTIC;UCPECTrWCTCXKOIV~

    TrpOC; EUCTE~EICXV);if confidence and settled usage are disturbed or shaken at a

    single point, the whole edifice is enfeebled and discredited".14

    Whereas Pemptides demands an account and proof (cbr6oEI~l~) of-the

    actual divinity of-each of the gods, Plutarch wishes to stick to "the invi-

    olable opinion (06~cx) regarding the gods which we hold", which he charac-

    terizes as ~1((hPlO~ xcx11tcxAcxlcX1t[crtl~, "the ancestral and ancient faith", and

    which functions, as he says, as what should be regarded as a common foun-

    dation for piety.15 In this passage, 7t[O"Tl~ seems to acquire a strongly fideisticcolor. Pemptides is rebuked for questioning this ancient faith by his request

    for proof and demonstration ofwhat, in Plutarch's mind, should be common

    knowledge of the gods, in this case of the god of Love, Eros. Hence, Plutarch

    asks Pemptides:

    So what is to be gained by the use of argument (A6yoc;) to make our opinion

    (a6~CX)16 regarding Zeus or Athena or Eros debatable or uncertain. Love is not

    now requesting his first altar and sacrifice. He is no alien intruder from some

    II Plu.,Amat. 7s6A.

    12 W.e. Helmbold, Plutarch's Moralia, IX (Cambridge 1969) 347, confusingly and ratheranachronistically, reads "our inviolable belief in the gods".

    13 Helmbold, Plutarch's Moralia, IX,347,translates eusebeia as "religion", thus pushing the

    virtue of piety into a specific religious post -Kantian domain.

    14 Plu.,Amat. 7s6A-B.

    15 On Plutarch andpatrios pistis, see Frazier, "Platonisme etPatrios pistis".

    16 Helmbold, ibid. again translates a6~~as "belief': "Sowhat is to be gained by the use of

    argument to make our belief in Zeus or Athena or Eros debatable or uncertain?"

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    6/21

    barbaric superstition (EX 'tlVO~ ~cxp~cxpllcri~ aElO"lacxq..tOV(cx~)... He does not ...

    smuggle himself in to reap a harvest of honours to which he has no rightY

    In other words, the reverence for Eros is not newly invented but is respect-

    able and ancient, is distinguished from barbaric superstition and should, for

    these reasons, need no additional proof. Demanfing such proofs, Plutarchargues against Pemptides, is a sign of one's soph*ic inclinations:

    .1.

    If you are going to demand a proof ('tEXI..l~PlOV)18 of each one of them [Le., of

    each one of the gods], probing every temple and attacking each altar with

    sophistic assault, not a god will you exempt from malicious prosecution and

    inquisition. 19

    Moreover, if one questions the existence of the gods and interprets them in

    terms of virtues and other qualities which they symbolically embody (as do

    the Stoics, according to Plutarch), the request for additional proofs is even

    a sign of atheism:

    You surely perceive the abyss of atheism that engulfs us if we list each several

    god on a roster of emotions, functions, and virtues.2o

    Plutarch's defense of the n&-rploc; xed mXAomx nl

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    7/21

    the reverence and faith (1t[crnc;) implanted in nearly all mankind at birth,

    opening wide the great doors to the atheistic throng, degrading things divine

    to the human level, and giving a splendid licence to the deceitful utterances

    of Euhemerus ofMessene.22

    Interestingly, whereas Plutarch defends the faith (1tlcrt'l~) which is "im-plantedl,in nearly all mankind at birth", he criticizes Euhemerus for erect-

    ing a 8.1:Jlwman for his Euhemeristic interpretation by first developing an

    incredible, untrustworthy (&1tlcrro~)mythology which he subsequently sets

    out to criticize:

    ... Euhemerus of Messene ... of himself drew up copies of an incredible and

    non-existent mythology, and spread atheism over the whole inhabited earth

    by obliterating the gods of our belief and converting them all alike into

    names of generals, admirals, and kings, who, forsooth, lived in very ancient

    times and are recorded in inscriptions written in golden letters at Panchon,

    which no foreigner and no Greek had ever happened to meet with, save only

    Euhemerus.23

    In this way the trustworthy 1t[crrl~ of ancient tradition is contrasted with

    the incredible, untrustworthy, tendentious inventions of Euhemerus. Nev-

    ertheless, this seems to be the only justification which Plutarch appears to

    give for his otherwise apparently fideistic notion of 1t[crrl~.Yet other pas-

    sages make clear that his understanding of1t[crrl~ is rather more subtle than

    meets the modern, anachronistic, post-Kantian eye. As is clear in some of

    the passages discussed above, and which is rendered even more clearly in afurther passage not yet discussed, Plutarch takes care to distinguish 1t[crrl~

    from mere superstition (OElCTlOOU/-lOV[cx) and uses it effectively as a synonym

    for ~ 1tEpl eEWV o6~cx ("the opinion regarding the gods"). In his treatise That

    Epicurus Actually Makes a Pleasant Life Impossible, Plutarch has Aristode-

    mus arguing against the Epicureans, claiming that their theory, although

    removing the anxiety caused by superstitious fear of the gods, "allows no

    joy and delight to come to us from the gods".24 Instead, Aristodemus states:

    ... itis better that our opinion about the gods(~m;pl SEWV a6~cx) should include

    an intermixture of a certain emotion that is part reverence and part fear, thanthat, by trying to escape this, we should leave ourselves no hope of divine

    favour, no confidence in prosperity, and in adversity no refuge in God. Now

    we should, I grant you, remove superstition (OElCTlOCXlflovicx)from our opinion

    about the gods (~ 1tEpl SEWV o6~cx) like a rheum from the eye; but if this proves

    22 PIu., De Is. 359F-36oA.

    23 PIu., De Is. 36oA.

    24 PIu., Non pass. nolA.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    8/21

    impossible,we shouldnot cut awayboth together (IlYJOE't"uqlAoilv n1v n:((J"["lV,~v01 n:AE'l(J"["olm:pl (JEWVEx0uow), and blind the faith (n:((J"["lC;)that most men havein the gods.25

    In this passage it is Plutarch's clearly stated intention to distinguish between

    superstition on the one hand, and opinion about and belief in the godson the other. Using the imagery of eye surg~ during which rheum is

    removed, he states that if it is impossible to ~rry out such an operation,

    care should be taken against drastic action by which not only the rheum

    (that is, superstition) is removed, but the eye itself (that is, faith or belief in

    the gods) is severely damaged and blinded.

    In the various passages discussed above Plutarch shows himself very pro-

    tective of faith, both against Euhemeristic and Epicurean ways of thinking.

    Although superstition should ideally be separated from belief in the gods,

    Plutarch, in the interest of faith, is reluctant to emphasize this too stronglyas faith may also fall victim and become seriously wounded. However, in

    other contexts in which Plutarch is not so deeply involved in anti-Epicurean

    polemics, he is indeed interested in purging belief and saving it from false

    and fabulous representations of the gods in poetry. In this way it is possible

    to strengthen faith:

    ... just as in what we have said above we felt that by setting against cheapand harmful poems the sayingsand maximsof men of repute and statesmen,we were indUcinga revolt and revulsion of faith (n:((J"["lC;) from such poetry,

    so whenever we find any edifyingsentiment neatly expressed in the poetswe ought to foster and amplifyit by means of proofs and testimonies fromthe philosophers ... Forthis is right and useful,and our faith gains an addedstrength and dignity (laxuv njc; n:L(J"["EWC;)(cxl cX~(wIlCXn:pocrAcxll~cxvoual')C;) when-ever the doctrines of Pythagorasand of Plato are in agreement with what isspoken on the stage or sung to the lyre or studied at school ...26

    Apparently, according to Plutarch it is possible for faith to acquire "added

    strength and dignity". Although he defends "the ancestral and ancient faith"

    in a rather fideistic way, over against those who demand proof of the gods,

    at the same time his actual concept of faith appears to allow for additional

    strengthening. Indeed, as we shall see, in Plutarch's view there are two kinds

    of faith: misfounded and strengthened faith.

    25 Plu., Non poss. 110lB-C.

    26 Plu., De adulat. 3SE-F.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    9/21

    It is stated or implied in several passages that faith takes two forms. For

    example, in Table-Talks, Plutarch refers to a particular story as EV'tl 'tWV

    Elldj 1tE1t!O''tEUj.lEVWV("one of those stories that gain credence without goodgroun~").27 Apparently some things gain credence and are believed on

    good gJ'bunds, while others are believed without good grounds. Hence, faith

    may be' justifiable or not. Similarly, in his Dinner of the Seven Wise Men,

    Plutarch has someone say that "a good many things, come to be believed

    quite contrary to fact" (1tOAAa ... 1t!O"t'EUE'tCXltj;EU5wC;).28Consequently, it is also

    possible to induce firm belief in one's cause, or fail to do so. For example,

    in the context of his discussion of ill will in the writing of history, Plutarch

    distinguishes between sophists and true historians; whereas the former "are

    not really inducing any firm belief in their cause (OUyap Ej.l1tOlOUO'I1tlO"t'IVIOXUpcXv1tEpi'tOU1tPayj.lcx'tOC;)and ... may even admit that they are trying

    to startle people by a defense of the incredible", the historian "declares as

    true what he knows to be the case and, when the facts are not clear, says

    that the more creditable appears to be the true account rather than the less

    creditable".29 The point for our present discussion is that Plutarch does not

    take 1tlO"t'lC;in a fideistic sense to the extent that everyone can claim that

    his 1tlO"t'IC;is as good as that of everyone else, but differentiates between

    1tlO''tlC;which is strong (loxup&) and 1tlO"t'lC;which lacks this quality. Hence,

    there are two forms of 1tlO"t'IC;,strong belief and, by implication, weak belief.Elsewhere in his writings Plutarch explicitly calls the latter an ChE)(VOC;1tlO"t'lC;,

    "an unskillful, unprofessional, or unsystematic faith",30 rendered in the Loeb

    translation as "a layman's faith".3J The topic of the passage in question is very

    specific, but what is important is that in this section it appears possible to

    bolster this "layman's faith" with the confirmation of a specific, professional

    experience. The background to this notion of ChE)(V0C;1tlO"t'IC;is Aristotle's

    rhetorical theory, in which he differentiates between ChE)(V0C;1tlO''tlC;-proofs

    which are not invented by the orator-and proofs which are. According to

    Aristotle:

    ... rhetoric we look upon as the power of observing the means of persuasion

    on almost any subject presented to us ... Of the modes of persuasion some

    27 Plu., Qu. conl'. 624A.

    28 Plu., Sept. sap. conl'. 151F.

    29 Plu., De Her. malig. 855E-F.

    30 Plu., Qu. conl'. 725B.

    31 E.L. Minar, Plutarch's Moralia, IX (Cambridge 1969) 155.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    10/21

    are technical, others non-technical ('rwv aE nlcT'rE:wv exi flEV eX'rE)(VOlIdcm exi a'

    Ev'rE)(VOl).By the latter I mean such things as are not supplied by the speaker

    but are there at the outset-witnesses, evidence given under torture, written

    contracts, and so on. Bythe former I mean such as we can ourselves constructby means of the principles of rhetoric. The one kind has merely to be used, the

    other has to be invented.32

    This rhetorical concept of ChEXVO~ 1t(crrl~ is no..J applied by Plutarch in a

    wider sense of "a layman's faith", which can still be bolstered by an addi-

    tional argumentation.33 This is indeed how we have come to understand

    Plutarch's notion of 1t((""Cl~. Contrary to the first impression given by some

    passages, which seemed to suggest, when read in a post-Kantian light, that

    Plutarch's understanding of1t(crrl~ is rather fideistic, on closer scrutiny Plu-

    tarch appears to be of the opinion that it is possible for the right, justifiable

    kind of faith to gain "an added strength and dignity" and to be bolstered

    by further argumentation. What is already noticeable in various passagesis that 1t(crrl~ has such an argumentative potential that it can also be trans-

    lated as "persuasion". This is also the case for Aristotle's rhetorical theory, in

    which Evt'EXVOl1t(crt'El~ and Ctt'EXVOl 1t(crrEl~ are "proofs" which are or are not

    invented by the speaker, respectively.

    It is apparent from Plutarch's writings that 1t(crrl~ has such an argumenta-tive potential that, if successful, and contrasted with mere opinions, it can

    also be translated as "persuasion". In his essay Concerning TaLkativeness,

    Plutarch censures chatterers, who "keep their mouths without lock or door",

    and hence:

    ... appear to regard speech as the least valuable of all things. They do not,

    therefore, meet with belief, which is the object of all speech C08EV ~UaE nlCTtW

    E)couaw ~~ 1t(X~A6yo~ Ecp1E'rexl).For this is the proper end and aim of speech,

    32 Arist., Rh. 13SSb3S;See 137Sa22.The notion is also applied by Philo in De spec. leg. 4.40.

    33 A similar wider application occurs in Numenius, fro26.84-90 (apud Eus., PE 14.7.12):

    "And Lacydes for a while was at a loss, seeing that the support of his own doctrines was of

    no help to him; and thinking that, if he could not convict them, everything he had would

    be upset, he fell into perplexity, and began to cry out upon his neighbours and upon the

    gods, Oh! Oh! and Alas! Alas! and By all the gods, and By the goddesses, and all the other

    artless affirmations of men who in cases of distrust take to strong language (((/,ACtlTEeaCH

    EVdtmaT(CXl~IlElVOAOyOUflEVWVE!atV((TE)(\IOlTdaTEl~)-alithese were uttered with loud shouting

    and asseveration". Trans. E.H. Gifford, Eusebii Pamphili Evangelicae praeparationis libri XV

    (Oxford 1903).

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    11/21

    to engender belief in the hearer (,0 yap olxElovcxu,oil,EAO~,oil,' ECT'rl,1tlCT't"lV

    EVEpycXO'cx0'8cxl'Ol~ aXOUOUO'lV).But chatterers are disbelieved even if they are

    telling the truth (a1tlO"rOilv-rCXI5' OtAeXAOl,xiXvcXA}}8EUWO'LV).For as wheat shut

    up in a jar is found to have increased in quantity, but to have deteriorated

    in quality, so when a story finds its way to a chatterer, it generates a large

    addition offalsehood and thereby destroys its credit (w5lCXcp8dpEl-rYjV1tlO"rlv).34, ,

    In this Jt>assage, nlO"tlC; is indeed concerned with the rhetorical act of per-

    suading and being persuaded. It is about meeting with belief, engendering

    belief in the hearer or, conversely, about credit being destroyed. In this light

    the following passage from Plutarch's anti-Epicurean Reply to Colotes is also

    relevant. Here Plutarch also quotes from the Proem of Parmenides' well-

    known hexameter poem, in which Truth is sharply contrasted with "the

    opinions of mortals, in which there is no true persuasion".35 The goddess

    Dike addresses Parmenides as he approaches her on his heavenly journey:

    Young man, you who come to my house in the company of immortal char-

    ioteers with the mares which bear you, greetings. No ill fate has sent you to

    travel this road-far indeed does it lie from the steps of men-but right and

    justice. It is proper that you should learn all things, both the unshaken heart

    of well-rounded truth, and the opinions of mortals, in which there is no 1tlO"rl~

    cXA}}8~~,no true reliance.36

    According to Plutarch, who quotes from this Proem, the criteria of Par-

    menides' world-view are:

    "The unerring heart of most persuasive Truth" which deals with what isintelligible and forever unalterably the same, "And man's beliefs, that lack all

    true persuasion" because they consort with objects admitting all manner of

    changes, accidents, and irregularities.37

    As in the previous passage from Plutarch's Concerning Talkativeness (S03D),

    nla-,lC; acquires the meaning of persuasion, reliance and trustworthiness.

    All these meanings revolve around the centrality of trust, which is the best

    way to render nlO"tlC; in various passages. "Persuasion" and "trust" appear

    to be closely related because they are realized in relationships: people

    are persuaded and are persuasive because they trust and are trusted; andvice versa, they trust because they have been persuaded by someone's

    34 Plu., De garr. 503D.

    35 Plu., Adv. Cof. 1114D-E.

    36 Translation by S. Kirk - J.E. Raven &M. Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers: a Critical

    History with a Selection of Texts (Cambridge 21983), fro 288 (B. Einarson & Ph.H De Lacy,

    Plutarch's Moralia, XIV [London-Cambridge 1967] 233 translate "no true persuasion").

    37 Plu., Adv. Col. 1114D-E.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    12/21

    trustworthiness, for example on the authority of someone's great wisdom.

    This we can we deduce from the following examples.

    5. IIf(JTl~ in the Sense of Trust

    ,

    That Tt[o-rl~is about trust which is realized in rt$tion to other people who

    appear to be trustworthy, transpires readily fr~m a passage in Plutarch's

    Dinner of the Seven Wise Men, which quotes the following remark from

    Thales ofMilete:

    ... Thales is responsible also for this sage remark, that one should not believe

    enemies, even about things believable, and should believe friends even about

    things unbelievable (OEl "rOLe;flEV E)(SpOle; xiXl1tEpl "rwv ma-rwv eXma-rElv, "rOLe;oE

    cplAOle;xiXl "reXama-riX ma-rEuElv).38

    The concept of Ttl

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    13/21

    Homer's very great wisdom here is something which persuades people to

    trust him and to be persuaded by him. In this way persuasion and trust are

    closely linked and this variety of meanings which Tela-Tll;acquires shows that

    Plutarch does not understand it in a fideistic sense, as something like blind

    faith. As we have seen thus far, Tela-Tll;is something which can be further

    strengltlened and it is part of a process of persuasion and trust. It comes

    as no ~rprise then, that in Plutarch's view there is no innate opposition or

    tension between Tela-Tll;and philosophy.

    Indeed, if Tela-Tll;is not a fideistic notion but is about persuasion and trust,

    there is nothing to impede its application to philosophical contexts. A very

    moving example of such an application is found in Plutarch's Consolation to

    hisWife, written on the occasion of the death of one of their children, Timo-

    xena. Plutarch, being absent from home, writes instructions to his wife and,

    although fully confident of his wife's strength, sketches the possible intru-

    sion of two different groups. Firstly, he mentions the "pernicious women"

    who might attempt to visit the bereaved, uttering cries and lamentations,

    "adding fire to fire".42Secondly, he mentions the Epicureans, whose solace

    is their message that death is nothing to humanity but the dissolution of

    which human beings are unaware. Plutarch tells his wife that she is neither

    susceptible to the influence of the "pernicious women", nor to that of the

    Epicureans:

    You doubtless hear the statements of that other set, who win many to their

    way of thinking when they say that nothing is in any way evil or painful to

    "what has undergone dissolution" (Kedfl~Vex TWV&..wv ,h:ouElt;,0'1m:leouC7l1CoA-

    AOUl;AiYOVTEI,;WI,;ouaEvouaafln Tc'l>alaAUeEV['l>c:a>c:ov~UaEAU101poVtC7m); I know

    that the teaching of our fathers and the mystic formulas of the Dionysiac rites,

    the knowledge of which we who are participants share with each other, pre-

    vent you from believing them (ola' OTl>C:WAUEIC7E1C!C7TEUElV0 mXTplOI,;AOyOI,;>c:al

    TeXflUC7Tl>C:eXcrUfl~OAaTWV1CEpl-rov~lOVUC70V6pYlaC7flwv,ex

    crUVlC7flEVcX"~AOII,;01>C:Ol-VWVOilVTEI,;).43

    Highly relevant to our topic is that Plutarch describes the adherence to a

    philosophical position such as that of the Epicureans in terms of believing.

    Despite the attempt of the Epicureans to persuade others of their view

    42 PIu., ConsoL ad ux. 6lOB-D.

    43 PIu., ConsoL ad ux. 611D.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    14/21

    of death, Plutarch's wife, he asserts, cannot believe them. Philosophical

    convictions, thus, are a matter of persuasion and belief. Similarly, at the end

    of his letter to his wife Plutarch also describes their own adherence to the

    Platonic view of death as something they "believe in". Havingjust invoked

    the laws which according to Plutarch:II

    ... forbid us to mourn for infants, holding it i~piety to mourn for those who

    have departed to a dispensation and a regiffn too that is better and moredivine44 .

    And since this is harder to disbelieve than to believe (E1tEl 8ETO cX1tl

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    15/21

    linked with the realm of the dead and the expectation of an afterlife. It is

    for this reason that Plutarch mentions the Dionysiac mysteries in his con-

    solatory letter to his wife. The experiences of these mysteries, apparently,

    strengthen their philosophical convictions and beliefs. Also relevant in this

    context is what Plutarch says elsewhere about the initiation into the mys-

    teries ib relation to an assurance about the existence of an afterlife. Those

    initiat~lI into the mysteries become convinced that there is an afterlife, and

    enriche'd by this experience they also become aware that the uninitiated

    masses do not believe in this other world. They are characterized (X7tlCT'Tl~

    1'WV EXEl cXyiXeWV (by a lack of belief in the blessings of the other world):

    ... he surveys the uninitiated, unpurified mob here on earth, the mob of

    living men who, herded together in mirk and deep mire, trample one another

    down and in their fear of death cling to their ills, since they disbelieve in the

    blessings ofthe other world.46

    Both passages thus make it clear that the mysteries are concerned with an

    experience of the existence of an afterlife, that the non-acceptance of this

    is called CX7tlCT'TliX (unbelief), and that the initiation into the mysteries can

    dissuade one from believing in the Epicurean view of death. In this way,

    belief, mysteries and philosophical conviction are mingled in a way which

    cannot be easily disentangled through a post-Enlightenment approach.

    Plutarch applies the notion ofnlCT'Tll; not only with regard to the Platonic-

    Epicurean controversy regarding the afterlife, but also in very different

    philosophical discussions. This notion is also at stake when the very ques-tion of who qualifies as a true philosopher is discussed. Plutarch raises this

    question in his oration On the Fortune or the Virtue of ALexander. Accord-

    ing to Plutarch, the criterion with which to answer this question does not

    concern whether someone has written something:

    ... it is obvious that Alexander wrote nothing ... And yet even Pythagoras

    wrote nothing at all, nor did Socrates, nor Arcesilaiis, nor Carneades, who

    were all most notable among philosophers ...Whence, then, comes our belief

    that they were true philosophers? (TCOSEV ouv E1ClCi't'EUS}jCTIXV EXElvOI CPIAOCTOCPEIV;)

    Surely from what they said, or from the manner of life which they led, orfrom the principles which they taught (acp' wv ElTCOV ~ acp' wv E~[WCTIXV ~ acp' wv

    EO[OIX~IXV). Bythese criteria let Alexander also be judged! For from his words,

    from his deeds, and from the instruction which he imparted, it will be seen

    that he was indeed a philosopherY

    46 Plu.,fr.178 (apud Stobaeus 4.52-49).

    47 Plu.,De Alex.fort. 328A-B.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    16/21

    Thus, the claim that someone is a true philosopher is a matter of belief

    and trust, neither ofwhich are blind, but rather are dependent on the words,

    deeds and instruction of such men. This very much reminds us of those

    passages in which Plutarch talks of believing in Homer on account of his

    great wisdom.48

    Against this background, I would suggest that the manypassages in Paul's writings about "belief in Christ" should not be taken to

    reflect a specifically religious belief in Christt'kather, what is at stake here

    is the trustworthiness of a particular figure as 'reflected in his words, deeds

    and instruction.49

    Finally, within a philosophical context, Plutarch also discusses the issue

    of 7t[(rn~ when he explicitly focuses on the compatibility of 7t[O',l~and

    philosophy. We have already gained an impression of this discussion from

    a passage discussed above, in which Plutarch stated that "our faith gains

    an added strength and dignity whenever the doctrines of Pythagoras and ofPlato are in agreement with what is spoken on the stage or sung to the lyre

    or studied at school".50As we have seen, this is part of Plutarch's strategy

    to save faith from the fables about and misrepresentations of the gods in

    poetry. It is Plutarch's intention "to induce a revolt and revulsion of faith

    from such poetry" (3SF). Through this process, faith is strengthened and

    acquires further dignity. This discussion of the relationship between poetry,

    faith and philosophy also comes to the fore in other passages, among others,

    in his On Love. As we have seen, Plutarch criticizes Pemptides here for

    questioning the divinity of Eros and accuses him of "altogether violatingour inviolable opinion regarding the gods when you demand an account

    and proof of each of them".51According to Plutarch, "our ancestral and

    ancient faith is good enough" and "a basis, as it were, a common foundation

    48 See Plu., Qu. conv. 627E; Sept. sap. conv. 164D.

    49 This is also apparent in the gospels, which, as examples of the genre of ancient biogra-

    phies, are concerned with portraying the words, deeds and instruction of Jesus. This holds

    particularly true for the Gospel of Matthew which, as an example of a specific hermeneuticalancient biography shows the mutual confirmation and coherence ofJesus' words and deeds.

    According to Matthew, such harmony is missing from the Pharisees, who reveal themselves

    to be hypocrites. For the gospels as ancient biographies, see C.H. Talbert, What Is a Gospel?:

    The Genre of the Canonical Gospels (Philadelphia 1977); C.H. Talbert, "Biography, Ancient",

    Anchor Bible Dictionary, 1 (1992) 745-749 at 748 and 749 on Matthew and the hermeneuti-

    cal function of some ancient didactic biographies; R.A. Burridge, What Are the Gospels?: A

    Comparison with Graeco-Roman Biography (Grand Rapids 22004). For the similar intentions

    of Paul and the gospel writers in emphasiZing the trustworthiness and exemplarity of Christ

    in his words and deeds, see particularly Burridge, What Are the Gospels, 305-306.

    50 Plu.,De adulat. 35F.

    51 Plu.,Amat. 756A-B.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    17/21

    of reverence towards the gods",52 which should not become debatable or

    questionable because of sophistic and atheistic inquisitions.53 Although, as

    noted above, Plutarch's notion of 1tlcrnc; seemed to be rather fideistic here,

    this impression was not confirmed by our exploration of other passages in

    Plutarch's writings. Moreover, further on in his On Love,Plutarch shows that

    his vie~s on 1ticrrlc; are compatible with particular philosophical positions.

    Accori\ng to Plutarch:

    ... our belief (nlcrnc;) in all our notions, except those derived from the senses,

    comes from three sources: myth, law, and rational explanation; so it is

    undoubtedly the poets, the legislators, and thirdly the philosophers who have

    been our guides and teachers in what we think about the gods. They are alike

    in stating that gods exist; but they hold widely varying views about their num-

    ber and rank, as well as their nature and function. 54

    Plutarch adduces this argument because, despite their divergence, all three

    factions, as he calls them, agree about the divinity of Eros. In this way,

    Plutarch finally responds to Pemptides' challenge, although he presents

    the argument in a "detour"55 through a specific discussion with Daphnaeus,

    another partner in the dialogue:

    ... the three factions who theorise about the gods are at variance: they differ in

    their votes and find it difficult to accept each other's candidates. Yet there is

    one god about whom all firmly agree. The most eminent of poets, legislators,

    philosophers,join together in enrolling Eros among the gods ... Sowe see Love

    chosen as king, chief magistrate, and harmoniser by Hesiod, Solon and Plato.56

    The belief (1ticrrlc;) in the very notion of the gods thus also derives from the

    myths of the poets, the laws of the legislators and the rational explanations

    of the philosophers. Hence, "the belief' in them is based, Plutarch argues, on

    the concordance of the most eminent poets, legislators and philosophers,

    such as, Hesiod, Plato and Solon, respectively.

    This view on the harmony between faith and philosophy is also expressed

    in another discussion, in which Plutarch criticizes both the materialism of

    Democritus and EpicuTUs on the one hand, and the monism of the Stoics

    on the other, while embracing a particular form of dualism himself whichaccounts for both the bad and the good being present in reality. Plutarch

    52 Plu., Amat. 7s6B.53 Plu., Amat. 7S6C-7S7C.

    54 Plu., Amat. 763B-C.

    55 Plu., Amat. 764A.

    56 Plu., Amat. 763E.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    18/21

    claims that this form of dualism is already voiced by the poets, legislators

    and philosophers of old:

    ... this very ancient opinion comes down from theologians and from lawgivers

    to poets and philosophers; it can be traced to no source, but it carried a strong

    and almost indelible belief (TYJv cipxYJv ciaEO"1to't"ov ExouO"a, TYJVat 1t{O"'t"lVIOXUPciv

    Jc:al aUO"E~cXAEl1t't"Ov),57and is in circulation i~many places among barbarians

    and Greeks alike, not only in story and traditftm but also in rites and sacrifices,

    to the effect that the Universe is not of itself suspended aloft without sense

    or reason or guidance, nor is there one Reason which rules and guides it by

    rudder, as it were, or by controlling reins, but ...we may assert that ... [Nature]

    has come about, as the result of two opposed principles and two antagonistic

    forces ... The great majority and the wisest of men hold this opinion: they

    believe that there are two gods, rivals as it were, the one the Artificer of good

    and the other of evil. There are also those who call the better one a god and

    the other a daemon, as, for example, Zoroaster ...58

    Although Plutarch's plea for dualism over against materialism and Stoic

    monism is irrelevant for our present purposes, the passage shows that in

    Plutarch's view theologians, poets, lawgivers and philosophers can reach

    agreement in their views on the gods, and that their concordance produces

    "a strong and almost indelible belief (1t[(jn~)". He may well call this belief

    "strong" because he regards it as an example of faith, which as we have

    seen in another passage gains "an added strength and dignity" when it is

    confirmed by the doctrines of the philosophers.

    For this reason, I believe this paper to have established that Plutarch'snotion of faith is not fideistic, despite some suggestions to the contrary. In

    addition, it also belongs to the domain of philosophy-as we have seen par-

    ticularly in the present section-and for that reason often occurs together

    with philosophical and cognitive vocabulary. Not only can philosophical

    doctrines confirm expressions of1t[(j'["l~, but particular philosophical views

    are also the object of faith and are, conversely, reinforced by initiation into

    the mysteries. Faith and philosophy are thus interrelated. Moreover, as the

    previous sections have shown, "faith" is not the only, straightforward mean-

    ing of1t[(j't"l~. The notion of1t[(j'["l~ is deeply rooted in the relational sphere oftrust and is also at home in the domain of rhetorical persuasion.

    Against this background, it seems that the often fideistic understanding

    of1t[(j'["l~ in Pauline studies and its monopoly in reconstructions of Pauline

    theology need to be corrected. It does not seem correct to list various mean-

    57 F.e. Babbitt, Plutarch's Moralia, V (London-Cambridge Ig6g) 109 renders TC!(jTl~ as

    "conviction".

    58 Plu.,De Is. 36gB-E.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    19/21

    ings of 1r[crn~-which are reflected in our discussion of its occurrence in

    Plutarch-with precision in LS] (1408), while a presupposed theological

    meaning, according to which "faith" is opposed to sight and knowledge, is

    reserved for the Pauline writings (1.4).The same applies to the terminology

    of the mysteries. While in several passages in Plutarch we have seen that themysteItes and belief and disbelief are closely associated (ConsoL ad ux. 611D;

    fro178~it is incorrect to separate Christian "mystery" as it occurs in Paul's

    writings from these other mysteries, interpreting the former as a "secret

    revealed by God, i.e. religious or mystical faith" (LS]1156sub 1.4;emphasis

    mine). Further comparative research into early Christian and ancient philo-

    sophical notions, values and virtues might show that, in many respects, they

    are more closely related than a modem, anachronistic understanding of the

    difference between philosophy and religion seems to allow.

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    20/21

    Plutarch in the Religious

    and Philosophical Discourse

    ~ of Late Antiquityr

    Edited by

    Lautaro Roig Lanzillotta

    Israel Munoz Gallarte

    LEIDEN . BOSTON

    2012

  • 8/9/2019 2012 - Non-Fideistic Interpret 1

    21/21

    Ancient Mediterranean

    and Medieval Texts,

    and ConteXts

    Robert M. Berchman

    Jacob Neusner

    Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism,

    and the Platonic Tradition

    Edited by

    Robert M. BerchmanDowling College and Bard College

    John F. Finamore

    University of Iowa

    JOHN DILLON (Trinity College, Dublin) - GARY GURTLER (Boston College)

    JEAN-MARC NARBONNE (Laval University. Canada)